Skip to main content
Log in

Epistemic instrumentalism and the reason to believe in accord with the evidence

  • S.I.: Epistemic Justification
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Epistemic instrumentalists face a puzzle. In brief, the puzzle is that if the reason there is to believe in accord with the evidence depends, as the instrumentalist says it does, on agents’ idiosyncratic interests, then there is no reason to expect that this reason is universal. Here, I identify and explain two strategies instrumentalists have used to try and solve this puzzle. I then argue that we should find these strategies wanting. Faced with the failure of these strategies, I articulate a heretofore neglected solution on behalf of instrumentalism.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For a nice articulation of this question in the practical domain, see Dreier (2015).

  2. Kornblith (1993, 2002), Stitch (1990), Papineau (1999, 2009), Steglich-Petersen (2006, 2008), Grimm (2008, 2009) and Street (2009, 2008).

  3. Kelly (2003, 2007), Wedgwood (2007) and Parfit (2011).

  4. Cowie (2014) divides the field in much the same way. I follow Cowie in ignoring, for present purposes, a version of epistemic error theory according to which, contrary appearances, there are no reasons for belief and so, a fortiori, no reason for believing in accord with the evidence. For a defense of such a view, see Olson (2011) and Streumer (2013). For criticism, see Cuneo (2007).

  5. This is also how Schroeder (2007) characterizes universality in reasons.

  6. C.f. Kelly (2003).

  7. Here I draw on and extend an argument I make in my Sharadin (2015b).

  8. Foley (1987, p. 8).

  9. BonJour (1985, p. 7).

  10. Alston (2005, p. 29). It may be that Foley, BonJour, and Alston would each reject a characterization of their views as instrumentalist and instead view their account of the special epistemic interests agents have simply as an a la carte addition to their intrinsicalism. That is not important at present. What is important is the suggestion, made by Foley, BonJour, Alston, and others, that there are these special epistemic interests: that is the hinge on which the Special Interests Strategy on behalf of instrumentalism tries to turn. Whether or not Foley, et. al would themselves count as instrumentalists isn’t relevant. If they are right that agents have these special epistemic interests, then the instrumentalist is free to make use of those interests in responding to the Universality Challenge.

  11. See for instance Kvanvig (2003, 2005), Brogaard (2009) and Grimm (2008).

  12. Kelly (2003, p. 624). See also Lynch (2009).

  13. Kelly (2003, p. 625).

  14. C.f. David (2001, p. 155), who points out that this idea, that agents have a standing desire for true rather than false beliefs, is a “somewhat daring empirical claim about human psychology.”

  15. There is a familiar rejoinder to this worry with the Special Interests Strategy in both the epistemic and the moral case: the Constitutivist Gambit. According to the Constitutivist Gambit, contra appearance, it is impossible for there to be epistemic or moral agents of the sort described by Kelly, Hume, and Shakespeare, and this is because part of what it is to be an agent of the relevant sort involves having the relevant special interest. For examples of the Constitutivist Gambit, see Korsgaard (2009, 1999), Velleman (1989, 2000), Rosati (2003) and Smith (2013). The Gambit is subject to its own set of problems: for criticism, see Schroeder (2007), Katsafanas (2011), Tiffany (2011, Chap. 6) and Enoch (2006, 2011), and for replies, see Ferrero (2009) and Silverstein (2015). For my part, I find these criticisms convincing: I worry, with David Enoch, that the Constitutivist Gambit deprives instrumentalism of one of its most attractive features, viz., the ability to answer questions about the authority of some domain of normativity with ease. But in any case, exploring this line of argument would take me too far afield here. So I’ll leave it at that. If you’re more optimistic than I am about the prospects for constitutivism, the remainder of the paper can be read conditionally, as an exploration of what the instrumentalist should say, given that the Constitutivist Gambit can’t be made to work. This exploration is worthwhile, since a range of people on both sides of the issue—that is, intrinsicalists and instrumentalists are, like me, pessimistic about the Gambit.

  16. Here I draw on and extend an argument I make in my Sharadin (2015b).

  17. Thanks to an anonymous referee for recommending more clarity on this point.

  18. Nozick (1993, p. 68).

  19. Kornblith (1993, 2002).

  20. Kornblith (1993, pp. 370–371).

  21. Kornblith (1993, p. 373).

  22. He does come close to endorsing this strategy in the case of moral instrumentalism, though even there he is careful to hedge. See Schroeder (2007, p. 113, fn. 16).

  23. Schroeder (2007, p. 114).

  24. Schroeder (2007, pp. 113–114). Kate Nolfi pursues a modified version of this strategy in her Nolfi (2015).

  25. Schroeder (2007, p. 114).

  26. This is not meant to be a commitment to analyzing interests in terms of direction of fit, only a useful way of illustrating the point. For criticism of the direction of fit metaphor as a device for analyzing interests (and indeed beliefs), see Frost (2014).

  27. For a detailed discussion of these issues, see Achinstein (2003).

  28. What it means to ‘promote’ a desire or interest, and in particular whether promotion is always a matter of probability increasing, is a matter of some controversy. See, for example, my Sharadin (2015a, 2016), Dellsén and Sharadin (unpublished), Snedegar (2014), DiPaolo and Behrends (2015), Lin (2016), Coates (2014) and Behrends and DiPaolo (2011). But in order to have some account to be getting on with, I assume a roughly probabilistic account of promotion.

  29. A related issue, but one I can’t address here for reasons of space, is the apparent need for the instrumentalist to then go on to provide (or co-opt) some conception of evidence that is non-normative, i.e., according to which it can be the case that E is evidence that P and simultaneously the case that E is not a reason to believe P. This is an issue raised in Kelly (2007). Here, I note only that part of such a non-normative account of evidence would, if the instrumentalist takes the tack I am here recommending she take, include a non-vindicating explanation of our commitment to the normative conception of evidence. In other words, an explanation of why we are discinclined to go around denying that the fact that if something is evidence then it is also a reason to believe. Thanks to an anonymous referee for urging clarity on this point.

  30. Compare Kelly (2003, p. 624).

  31. Kelly (2003) takes this to be a point against instrumentalism.

  32. Dogramaci (2012, p. 15). In Dogramaci (2013) he goes further: according to the argument there, epistemic communism—the view that the function of our epistemic evaluative practice is to coordinative—supports a kind of epistemic conventionalism. Here I lack the space to address these arguments, and note only that the instrumentalist will disagree with this deflationary account of the requirements of epistemic rationality.

  33. Sobel (2017).

  34. Kelly (2007, 2003).

  35. Of course, intrinsicalists and instrumentalists are free to disagree on other grounds. And here, in this paper, I haven’t offered any positive argument in favor of instrumentalist against its intrinsicalist competitor.

References

  • Achinstein, P. (2003). The book of evidence. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alston, W. (2005). Beyond “justification”: Dimensions of epistemic evaluation. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Behrends, J., & DiPaolo, J. (2011). Finlay and Schroeder on promoting a desire. Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy, pp. 1–6.

  • BonJour, L. (1985). The structure of empirical knowledge. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brogaard, B. (2009). The trivial argument for epistemic value pluralism, or, how i learned to stop caring about truth. In A. Haddock, A. Millar, & D. Pritchard (Eds.), Epistemic value (pp. 284–305). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Coates, D. J. (2014). An actual-sequence theory of promotion. Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy, 8, 1–7.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cowie, C. (2014). In defence of instrumentalism about epistemic normativity. Synthese, 191(16), 4003–4017.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cuneo, T. (2007). The normative web: An argument for moral realism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • David, M. (2001). Knowledge, truth, and duty. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dellsén, F., & Sharadin, N. (unpublished). Promotion as contrastive increase in expected fit. Unpublished manuscript.

  • DiPaolo, J., & Behrends, J. (2015). Reason to promotion inferences. Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy, pp. 1–9.

  • Dogramaci, S. (2012). Reverse engineering epistemic evaluations. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 84(3), 513–530.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dogramaci, S. (2013). Communist conventions for deductive reasoning. Noûs, 49(4), 776–799.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dreier, J. (2015). Can reasons fundamentalism answer the normative question? In G. Björnsson, C. Strandberg, R. F. Olinder, J. Eriksson, & F. Bjorklund (Eds.), Motivational Internalism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Enoch, D. (2006). Agency, schmagency: Why normativity won’t come from what is constitutive of action. Philosophical Review, 115, 169–198.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Enoch, D. (2011). Schmagency revisited. In M. Brady (Ed.), New Waves in Metaethics (pp. 208–233). New York: Palgrave Mcmillan.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Ferrero, L. (2009). Constitutivism and the inescapability of agency. In R. Shafer-Landau (Ed.), Oxford Studies in Metaethics (Vol. 4, pp. 303–333). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foley, R. (1987). The theory of epistemic rationality. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Frost, K. (2014). On the very idea of direction of fit. Philosophical Review, 123(4), 429–484.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grimm, S. R. (2008). Epistemic goals and epistemic values. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 77, 725–744.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grimm, S. R. (2009). Epistemic normativity. In M. Haddock & D. Pritchard (Eds.), Epistemic value. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Katsafanas, P. (2011). Deriving ethics from action: A nietzschean version of constitutivism. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 83, 620–660.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kelly, T. (2003). Epistemic rationality as instrumental rationality: A critique. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 66(3), 612–640.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kelly, T. (2007). Evidence and normativity: Reply to Leite. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 75(2), 465–474.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kornblith, H. (1993). Epistemic normativity. Synthese, 94(3), 357–376.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kornblith, H. (2002). Knowledge and its place in nature. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Korsgaard, C. (1999). Self-constitution in the ethics of plato and kant. Journal of Ethics, 3, 1–29.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Korsgaard, C. (2009). Self-constitution: Agency, identity, and integrity. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kvanvig, J. (2003). The value of knowledge and the pursuit of understanding. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kvanvig, J. (2005). Truth is not the primary epistemic goal. In M. Steup & E. Sosa (Eds.), Contemporary debates in epistemology (pp. 285–296). Malden: Blackwell Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lin, E. (2016). Simple probabilistic promotion. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research.

  • Lynch, M. P. (2009). The values of truth and the truth of values. In A. Haddock, A. Millar, & D. Pritchard (Eds.), Epistemic value (pp. 225–242). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Nolfi, K. (2015). Why we should care about the epistemic status of our beliefs. unpublished.

  • Nozick, R. (1993). The nature of rationality. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Olson, J. (2011). Error theory and reasons for belief. In A. Reisner & A. Steglich-Petersen (Eds.), Reasons for belief. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Papineau, D. (1999). Normativity and judgment. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 73(supplementary), 17–41.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Papineau, D. (2009). There are no norms of belief. unpublished.

  • Parfit, D. (2011). On what matters (Vol. II). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rosati, C. S. (2003). Agency and the open question argument. Ethics, 113(3), 490–527.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schroeder, M. (2007). Slaves of the passions. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sharadin, N. (2015a). Problems for probabilism about promotion and an alter native. Philosophical Studies, 172(5), 1371–1386.

  • Sharadin, N. (2015b). Reasons and promotion. Philosophical Issues: A supplement to Nous, 25(1), 98–122.

  • Sharadin, N. (2016). Checking the neighborhood: A reply to DiPaolo and Behrends on promotion. Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy.

  • Silverstein, M. (2015). The shmagency question. Philosophical Studies, 172(5), 1127–1142.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, M. (2013). A constitutivist theory of reasons: Its promise and parts. Law, Ethics, and Philosophy, 1, 9–30.

    Google Scholar 

  • Snedegar, J. (2014). Contrastive reasons and promotion. Ethics, 124(1), 39–63.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sobel, D. (2017). From value to valuing: Towards a defense of subjectivism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Steglich-Petersen, A. (2006). No norm needed: On the aim of belief. The Philosophical Quarterly, 56(225), 499–516.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Steglich-Petersen, A. (2008). Does doxastic transparency support evidentialism. Dialectica, 62(4), 541–547.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stitch, S. (1990). The fragmentation of reason: Preface to a pragmatic theory of cognitive evolution. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Street, S. (2008). Constructivism about reasons. In R. Shafer-Landau (Ed.), Oxford studies in metaethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Street, S. (2009). Evolution and the normativity of epistemic reasons. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 39(1), 213–248.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Streumer, B. (2013). Can we believe the error theory? Journal of Philosophy, 110(4), 194–212.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tiffany, E. (2011). Why be an agent? Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 90(2), 223–233.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Velleman, D. (1989). Practical Reflection. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Velleman, D. (2000). The possibility of practical reason. The possibility of practical reason (pp. 170–199). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Wedgwood, R. (2007). The nature of normativity. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I thank students in my Spring 2016 graduate seminar on epistemic normativity, audiences at the University of Chicago, Virginia Tech, and the CNY Ethics Reading Group, as well as two anonymous referees for their feedback on this paper. I also thank Ben Bradley, Nykki Dular, Nikki Fortier, Ram Neta, Hille Paakkunainen, and David Sobel for fruitful discussions on the topic.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Nathaniel Sharadin.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Sharadin, N. Epistemic instrumentalism and the reason to believe in accord with the evidence. Synthese 195, 3791–3809 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-016-1245-3

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-016-1245-3

Keywords

Navigation