Skip to main content
Log in

The subject matter of phenomenological research: existentials, modes, and prejudices

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In this essay I address the question, “What is the subject matter of phenomenological research?” I argue that in spite of the increasing popularity of phenomenology, the answers to this question have been brief and cursory. As a result, contemporary phenomenologists lack a clear framework within which to articulate the aims and results of their research, and cannot easily engage each other in constructive and critical discourse. Examining the literature on phenomenology’s identity, I show how the question of phenomenology’s subject matter has been systematically neglected. It has been overshadowed by an unending concern with phenomenology’s methodological identity. However, an examination of recent contributions to this literature reveals that a concern with articulating phenomenology’s subject matter has gradually increased, although such articulations remain preliminary. In light of this, I delineate, define, and illustrate three layers of phenomenological research, which I term “existentials,” “modes,” and “prejudices.” While the delineation of these layers is drawn primarily from classical phenomenological texts, they are defined and illustrated through the use of more contemporary literature. Following the articulation of this subject matter, I briefly consider some of the debates—both foundational and applied—that can be facilitated by the adoption of this framework.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. These terms are translated from the German: “existential” [Existenzial], “existentials” [Existenzialien], “mode” [Modus], “modes” [Modi], “prejudice” [Vorurteil], and “prejudices” [Vorurteile].

  2. In one text, Zahavi says that the future prospects of phenomenology will depend upon the phenomenologist’s “ability to articulate and strengthen what is common to the phenomenological enterprise instead of getting involved in the sectarian trench warfare that has regrettably plagued the history of phenomenology” (Zahavi 2008, p. 684). I want to stress that when I speak of facilitating and increasing debate within phenomenology, I do not have in mind the kind of “trench warfare” that Zahavi remarks on here—insofar as this analogy brings to mind a debate in which everyone’s positions have been staked out in advance. Rather, my primary concern in this essay is to offer a shared framework that supports constructive debate, driving the discipline forward as a whole.

  3. I do not mean this as a methodological priority. There are many examples in the phenomenological canon where the study of particular meaningful objects or events sheds light on the structure whereby such meaningful objects are disclosed.

  4. I follow Stambaugh in translating Existenzial and Existenzialien as “existential” and “existentials,” respectively (rather than the more awkward “existentiale” and “existentialia” employed in the Macquarrie and Robinson translation).

  5. In the Macquarrie and Robinson translation of Being and Time, Befindlichkeit is translated as “state-of-mind.” This translation is widely accepted as inaccurate and misleading. In light of this, it is common to use alternative translations, including “affectedness” (Crowell 2013), “sofindingness” (Haugeland 2013), and “situatedness” (Guignon 2003). Throughout this essay I use the latter term, modifying quotations from Heidegger’s work where appropriate.

  6. In another case, Heidegger speaks of three modes that, taken together, make up the “existential mode” that he refers to as falling. These are idle talk (a mode of the existential of discourse), curiosity (a mode of the existential of situatedness), and ambiguity (a mode of the existential of understanding). In light of this, it seems that even when the term “mode” is used to refer to a modality of human existence as a whole, it can still be more finely delineated into the modal changes within individual existentials.

  7. This distinction—between existentials and modes—is often missed, in many cases leading to incoherent interpretations of phenomenological texts. One example of this kind is found in an article by Rudi Visker (1994). He argues that, according to Heidegger, certain existentials (specifically, falling and the “they”) can disappear—which seems to be a strange or counterintuitive notion. The trouble with this interpretation, and one that Visker fails to notice, is that falling and the “they” are simply not existentials—they are modes. As such, they are just some of the ways a world can be made available to us, and there is nothing especially intriguing about their absence.

  8. Examples of this kind of preparatory work are found in Sect. 1 of his introduction, where he offers a careful analysis of the concept of “sensation” in philosophy and the sciences (Merleau-Ponty 2012, pp. 3–12), as well as the introductory remarks in the final chapter on freedom (Merleau-Ponty 2012, pp. 458–483).

References

  • Ahmed, S. (2006). Queer phenomenology: Orientations, objects, others. Durham: Duke University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Aho, J., & Aho, K. (2009). Body matters: A phenomenology of sickness, disease, and illness. Lanham: Lexington Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alcoff, L. M. (2006). Visible identities: Race, gender, and the self. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Brown, C. S., & Toadvine, T. (Eds.). (2003). Eco-phenomenology: Back to the earth itself. Albany: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carel, H. (2014). Illness: The cry of the flesh. Durham: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Crowell, S. (2002). Is there a phenomenological research program? Synthese, 131(3), 419–444.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Crowell, S. (2013). Normativity and phenomenology in Husserl and Heidegger. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • D’Amico, R. (1999). Contemporary continental philosophy. Boulder: Westview Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dummett, M. (1978). Truth and other enigmas. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fernandez, A. V. (2014). Depression as existential feeling or de-situatedness? Distinguishing structure from mode in psychopathology. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 13(4), 595–612.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fernandez, A. V. (2015). Contaminating the transcendental: Toward a phenomenological naturalism. Journal of Speculative Philosophy, 29(3), 291–301.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gadamer, H. G. (2008). On the scope and function of hermeneutical reflection. In D. E. Linge (Ed.), Philosophical hermeneutics. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Guignon, C. (2003). Moods in Heidegger’s being and time. In R. Solomon (Ed.), What is an emotion? Classic and contemporary readings (2nd ed., pp. 181–190). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haugeland, J. (2013). Dasein disclosed. In J. Rouse (Ed.), Dasein disclosed: John Haugeland’s Heidegger. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M. (1962). Being and time (J. Macquarrie & E. Robinson, Trans.). New York: Harper Perennial Modern Classics.

  • Heidegger, M. (2001). The fundamental concepts of metaphysics: World, finitude solitude (W. McNeill, N. Walker, Trans.). Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

  • Heidegger, M. (2008). Basic writings. New York: Harper Perennial Modern Classics.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M. (2010). Being and time: A Revised Edition of the Stambaugh Translation (J. Stambaugh, Trans.). Albany: State University of New York Press.

  • Heinämaa, S., Hartimo, M., & Miettinen, T. (Eds.). (2014). Phenomenology and the transcendental. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Henry, M. (2002). I am the truth: Toward a philosophy of christianity (S. Emanuel, Trans.). Stanford, California: Stanford University Press.

  • Husserl, E. (1970). The crisis of european sciences and transcendental phenomenology: An introduction to phenomenological philosophy (D. Carr, Trans.). Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

  • Husserl, E. (1989). Ideas pertaining to a pure phenomenology and to a phenomenological philosophy: Second book: Studies in the phenomenology of constitution (R. Rojcewicz, A. Schuwer, Trans.). Boston: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

  • Husserl, E. (2014). Ideas for a pure phenomenology and phenomenological philosophy: First book: General introduction to pure phenomenology (D. O. Dahlstrom, Trans.). Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company Inc.

  • James, S. P. (2009). The presence of nature: A study in phenomenology and environmental philosophy. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lee, E. S. (Ed.). (2014). Living alterities: Phenomenology, embodiment, and race. Albany: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Luft, S., & Overgaard, S. (2011). Introduction. In S. Luft & S. Overgaard (Eds.), The Routledge companion to phenomenology (pp. 1–14). Hoboken: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marion, J.-L. (2012). God without being: Hors-Texte (2nd ed.) (T. A. Carlson, Trans.). Chicago: University Of Chicago Press.

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (2012). Phenomenology of perception (D. Landes, Trans.). New York: Routledge.

  • Moran, D. (2000). Introduction to phenomenology. New York: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Oksala, J. (2006). A phenomenology of gender. Continental Philosophy Review, 39(3), 229–244.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Oksala, J. (2016). Feminist experiences: Foucauldian and phenomenological investigations. Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Patočka, J. (1970). Der Subjektivismus Der Husserlschen Und Die Möglichkeit Einer ‘Asubjektiven’ Phänomenologie. Perspektiven Der Philosophie, 2, 317.

    Google Scholar 

  • Petitot, J., Varela, F. J., Pachoud, B., & Roy, J.-M. (Eds.). (1999). Naturalizing phenomenology: Issues in contemporary phenomenology and cognitive science. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ratcliffe, M. (2015). Experiences of depression: A study in phenomenology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sokolowski, R. (2000). Introduction to phenomenology. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spiegelberg, H. (1981). The phenomenological movement: A historical introduction. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stanghellini, G., & Rosfort, R. (2014). Emotions and personhood: Exploring fragility, making sense of vulnerability. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Steinbock, J. (2007). Phenomenology and mysticism: The verticality of religious experience. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Straus, E. W. (1966). Phenomenological psychology: The selected papers of Erwin W. Straus: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Toadvine, T. (2014). The elemental past. Research in phenomenology, 44(2), 262–279.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Visker, R. (1994). Dropping: The ‘Subject’ of Authenticity. Being and time on disappearing existentials and true friendship with being. Research in Phenomenology, 24, 133–158.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wieseler, C. (2012). Phenomenology, feminist philosophy, and the impairment/disability distinction: Incorporating the lived body into the social model of disability. Kinesis, 39(1), 4–17.

    Google Scholar 

  • Withy, K. (2015). Heidegger on being uncanny. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Young, I. M. (2005). On female body experience: “Throwing Like a Girl” and other essays. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi, D. (2008). Phenomenology. In D. Moran (Ed.), The routledge companion to twentieth-century philosophy (pp. 661–692). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi, D. (2012). Introduction. In D. Zahavi (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of contemporary phenomenology (pp. 1–4). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi, D. (2013). Naturalized phenomenology: A desideratum or a category mistake? Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement, 72(July), 23–42.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi, D. (2015). Self and other: Exploring subjectivity, empathy, and shame. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

In working out and clarifying the conceptual distinctions in this article, I benefited from discussions with Kevin Aho, Charles Guignon, and Giovanni Stanghellini. I would also like to thank Josh Bergamin, Simon James, Alex Levine, Harry Lewendon-Evans, Louis Sass, Sarah Wieten, and the members of the Applied Phenomenology Research Cluster at Durham University for their helpful comments on earlier drafts of this article.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Anthony Vincent Fernandez.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Fernandez, A.V. The subject matter of phenomenological research: existentials, modes, and prejudices. Synthese 194, 3543–3562 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-016-1106-0

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-016-1106-0

Keywords

Navigation