Skip to main content
Log in

Aristotelian essentialism: essence in the age of evolution

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The advent of contemporary evolutionary theory ushered in the eventual decline of the theory of Aristotelian Essentialism (Æ)—for it is widely assumed that essence does not, and cannot have any proper place in the age of evolution. This paper argues that this assumption is a mistake: if Æ can be suitably evolved, it need not face extinction. In it, I claim that if that theory’s fundamental ontology consists of dispositional properties, and if its characteristic metaphysical machinery is interpreted within the framework of contemporary evolutionary developmental biology, an evolved essentialism is available. The reformulated theory of Æ offered in this paper not only fails to fall prey to the typical collection of criticisms, but is also independently both theoretically and empirically plausible. The paper contends that, properly understood, essence belongs in the age of evolution.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. I borrow this colourful phrasing from Hacking (2007).

  2. Cf. Wilkins (2013), Devitt (2008).

  3. As Elder (2008, p. 345) notes: “If a plurality of organisms is to populate a genuine natural kind...more is needed than just that the same phenotypic traits crop up in member after member of the plurality. The same traits must recur across all the organisms for a common reason”.

  4. Cf. Lennox (2001), Pellegrin (1987), and Balme (1987).

  5. Griffiths (2002, p. 77).

  6. Cf. Okasha (2002, p. 191).

  7. This lack of evidence has arguably led to the formulation of the ‘Homeostatic Property Cluster’ view of natural kinds—see Boyd (1999), Wilson (1999), and Wilson et al. (2007).

  8. See also Griffiths (2002), Hull (1999), and Sober (1980).

  9. Cf. Wilson (1999, p. 190), and Okasha (2002, p. 197).

  10. For a general overview, see Whitman and Agrawal (2009) and Schlichting and Smith (2002).

  11. See Fusco and Minelli (2010) and West-Eberhard (2003).

  12. Dispositions are often contrasted with ‘categorical’ properties—those whose nature must be imbued with causality from higher-order laws of nature, or else some flotilla of possible worlds. For discussions of the distinction, see Ellis (2010), Oderberg (2009), and Cross (2005).

  13. Even the seemingly simple philosopher’s paragon of dispositionality—‘fragility’—is realised (in most cases) by a complex physical microstructure, and ‘breaking’ is in fact a complex, multi-stage process featuring the aligning of various micro-events that represent decreasing degrees of structural integrity.

  14. That dispositional properties are responsible for establishing this type of causal connection between two states is the basis for their ubiquitous assignment as truthmakers for subjunctive conditionals (especially counterfactuals). However, spelling out precisely what the truthmaking role is, and showing that dispositional properties play it with respect to those conditionals turns out to be exceptionally tricky. As it happens, I won’t be making use of that concept here, as I’ve no need for it. For a good discussion of the related issues, see Austin (2015b) and Eagle (2009).

  15. I’ve said “reliably and repeatedly” purposely here, as dispositional properties do not necessitate their manifestations—a fact ensured by the possibility of so-called ‘masks’, properties or processes which interrupt the causal activity of dispositional properties. See Eagle (2009), Schrenk (2010), and Mumford and Anjum (2011) for good discussions of the issue.

  16. In the dispositions literature, this fact is often referred to as dispositions being “multi-track”. See Martin (2008), Manley and Wasserman (2008), Jacobs (2011), and Vetter (2013) for fuller discussions.

  17. This is a species of the relation that Lewis (2000, p. 190) called ‘causal influence’ which forms the conceptual bedrock of Woodward’s (2003; 2010) influential theory of causation.

  18. Of course, not all dispositions are strongly goal-directed in this sense, but the ones which will concern us here—namely, those that populate the biological realm—certainly are.

  19. Nagel (1977, p. 272).

  20. See Walsh (2012), and Mayr (1992).

  21. Indeed, as many have now argued, ‘modularity’ may very well be a necessary requisite for the process of evolution: we may need variability to occur within discrete elements which doesn’t affect other elements if organisms are going to survive mutations and be subsequently subject to selection pressures. See Lewontin (1978) and Altenberg (1995).

  22. Müller (2008, p. 10).

  23. See Winther (2001), Bolker (2000), and Dassow and Munro (1999).

  24. This technique was especially prominent in Halder et al. (1995); For a general contemporary review in a particular case, see Ashery-Padan and Gruss (2001). And for an analysis of the expression patterns of modules in particular, see Raff and Sly (2000).

  25. See Wagner and Altenberg (1996).

  26. See Edelman and Gally (2001), Dassow et al. (2000), and Whitacre and Bender (2010).

  27. This is discussed with particular examples in Müller and Newman (1999), and Müller (2003).

  28. See Salazar-Ciudad and Jernvall (2013) for the concept of ‘causality horizons’ in explanations of developmental morphology.

  29. Though this general application has been made—in Wagner (2000) and Eble (2005)—, it has only been very briefly stated, and not explored in any depth.

  30. It’s plausible that there are at least four distinct “levels” of morphological organisation—see Rasskin-Gutman (2003).

  31. Thus, in the context of dynamical systems theory, the morphological structures associated with these modules are often characterised as ‘attractor-states’ which shape the “valleys” of an organisms’ epigenetic landscape, resulting in many distinct developmental pathways leading to the same end-state. See Jaeger and Monk (2014), and Striedter (1998).

  32. See Amundson (2005) for an excellent in-depth discussion of the ‘structuralist’ paradigm and its relation to that of the Modern Synthesis.

  33. Cf. Müller (2008).

  34. See West-Eberhard (2003), and Pigliucci (2001).

  35. For more on the concept of the ‘developmental hourglass’, see Galis and Metz (2001) and Kalinka et al. (2010).

  36. See Mann and Carroll (2002), Gurdon and Bourillot (2001), and Tabata (2001).

  37. See Schlichting and Smith (2002), and Aubin-Horth and Renn (2009).

  38. See Shubin et al. (2009), and Wagner (2007).

  39. Wagner (2014, pp. 92–93) argues that ‘character-identity’ determination (a) cannot be specified by positional information, given that they are variable in and among instances, and that it likewise (b) cannot be specified by downstream target genes, given not only their similar variability, but also their regulatory dependence upon upstream modules.

  40. Cf. Newman and Muller (2006), and Newman et al. (2006). For the concept of ‘morphospace’ generally, see Rasskin-Gutman (2005), and McGhee (2006).

  41. Müller (2008, p. 19).

  42. Accordingly, given our knowledge of the existence of highly conserved developmental mechanisms—such as “toolkit” genes, discussed earlier—every natural kind will share a significant proportion of their essential properties, these being ontological traces of their evolutionary origins.

  43. Davila-Velderrain et al. (2015), Huang (2012), Wang et al. (2011).

  44. For a defence of the ‘prime mover’ aspect of this claim, see Austin (2015a).

  45. Verd et al. (2014), Bhattacharya et al. (2011).

  46. Wagner (2014), Deutsch (2005).

  47. In fact, it’s for this very reason that Wagner (2014, p. 20) refers to his modelling of developmental modules as a theory of ‘variational structuralism’.

  48. According to this conception of the Aristotelian ‘natural state’, if we want to carve the world into proper natural kinds, it won’t be enough to group together organisms which share exact morphologies—rather, as evo-devo has taught us, we must look conceptually underneath those morphologies.

  49. If, as Rosenberg (2001) argues, the process of natural selection operates on function, and is rather “blind” to structure, we shouldn’t expect the essence of a natural kind, being so central to the process of ontogenic development, to be necessarily tied-up to a particular material realisation base.

  50. Jaeger and Monk (2014), Dupre (2013), Rosa and Etxeberria (2011), Gilbert and Bolker (2001).

  51. Most notably by Walsh (2006) and Boulter (2012), and to a lesser degree Devitt (2008).

  52. In the context of evo-devo, these sorts of studies may already be taking place. With respect to (a), investigating the effect of regulatory novelties on homology-generating pathways via mutation or epigenetic marking may be a viable way of discerning the arrival of novel phenomodulatory dispositions: see Wagner (2014), and Webster and Goodwin (2006). With respect to (b), the method of distinguishing two homologous modules in virtue of their non-overlapping sets of morphospace ‘character states’ may constitute an empirical method of detecting the presence of distinct phenomodulatory dispositions: see Wagner’s (2014) discussion of representing the ‘variational modalities’ of homologous structures.

References

  • Altenberg, L. (1995). Genome growth and the evolution of the genotype-phenotype map. In W. Banzhaf & F. Eeckman (Eds.), Evolution and biocomputation: Computational models of evolution (pp. 205–250). Berlin: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Amundson, R. (2005). The Changing role of the embryo in evolutionary thought: Roots of Evo-Devo. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ashery-Padan, R., & Gruss, P. (2001). Pax6 lights-up the way for eye development. Current Opinion in Cell Biology, 13(6), 706–714.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Aubin-Horth, N., & Renn, S. (2009). Genomic reaction norms: Using integrative biology to understand molecular mechanisms of phenotypic plasticity. Molecular Ecology, 18(18), 3763–3780.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Austin, C. J. (2015a). The dispositional genome: Primus inter pares. Biology and Philosophy, 30(2), 227–246.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Austin, C. J. (2015b). The truthmaking argument against dispositionalism. Ratio, 28(3), 271–285.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Balme, D. (1987). Teleology and necessity. In A. Gotthelf & J. Lennox (Eds.), Philosophical issues in Aristotle’s biology (pp. 275–285). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Bhattacharya, S., Zhang, Q., & Andersen, M. (2011). A deterministic map of Waddington’s epigenetic landscape for cell fate specification. BMC Systems Biology, 5, 1–11.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bolker, J. (2000). Modularity in development and why it matters to evo-devo. Integrative & Comparitive Biology, 40(5), 770–776.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boulter, S. J. (2012). Can evolutionary biology do without Aristotelian essentialism? Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement, 70, 83–103.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boyd, R. (1999). Homeostasis, species, and higher taxa. In R. Wilson (Ed.), Species: New interdisciplinary essays (pp. 141–186). Cambridge: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cross, T. (2005). What is a disposition? Synthese, 144(3), 321–341.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davila-Velderrain, J., Martinez-Garcia, J. C., & Alvarez-Buyila, E. R. (2015). Modeling the epigenetic attractors landscape: Toward a post-genomic mechanistic understanding of development. Frontiers in Genetics,. doi:10.3389/fgene.2015.00160.

  • Deutsch, J. (2005). Hox and wings. BioEssays, 27(7), 673–675.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Devitt, M. (2008). Resurrecting biological essentialism. Philosophy of Science, 75(3), 344–382.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dupre, J. (2013). Living causes. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society Supplementary, 87(1), 19–38.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eagle, A. (2009). Causal structuralism, dispositional actualism, and counterfactual conditionals. In T. Hanfield (Ed.), Dispositions and causes (pp. 65–99). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eble, G. (2005). Morphological modularity and macroevolution: Conceptual and empirical aspects. In W. Callebaut & D. Rasskin-Gutman (Eds.), Modularity: Understanding the Development and evolution of natural complex systems (pp. 221–239). Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Edelman, G., & Gally, J. (2001). Degeneracy and complexity in biological systems. Proceedings of the National Academy of the Sciences, 98(24), 13763–13768.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Elder, C. (2008). Biological species are natural kinds. Southern Journal of Philosophy, 46(3), 339–362.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ellis, B. (2010). Causal powers and categorical properties. In A. Marmodoro (Ed.), The metaphysics of powers: Their grounding and their manifestations (pp. 133–142). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fusco, G., & Minelli, A. (2010). Phenotypic plasticity in development and evolution: Facts and concepts. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B, 365, 547–556.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Galis, F., &  Metz, J. (2001). Testing the vulnerability of the phylotypic stage: On modularity and evolutionary conservation. Journal of Experimental Zoology, 291(2), 195–204.

  • Gilbert, S., & Bolker, J. (2001). Homologies of process and modular elements of embryonic construction. Journal of Experimental Zoology, 29(11), 1–12.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gould, S. J. (1985). The Flamingo’s smile: Reflections in natural history. New York: W.W. Norton & Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths, P. (2002). What is innateness. Monist, 85(1), 70–85.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gurdon, J., & Bourillot, P. (2001). Morphogen gradient interpretation. Nature, 413, 797–803.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hacking, I. (2007). Natural kinds: Rosy dawn, scholastic twilight. Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement, 61, 203–239.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Halder, G., Callaerts, P., & Gehring, W. (1995). Induction of ectopic eyes by targeted expression of the eyeless gene in Drosophilia. Science, 267, 1788–1792.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Huang, S. (2012). The molecular and mathematical basis of Waddington’s epigenetic landscape: A framework for post-darwinian biology? Bioessays, 34(2), 149–157.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hull, D. (1999). On the plurality of species: Questioning the party line. In R. Wilson (Ed.), Species: new interdisciplinary essays (pp. 23–48). Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jacobs, J. (2011). Powerful qualities, not pure powers. The Monist, 94, 81–102.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jaeger, J., & Monk, N. (2014). Bioattractors: Dynamical systems theory and the evolution of regulatory processes. Journal of Physiology, 592(11), 2267–2281.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kalinka, A., Varga, K., Gerrard, D., Preibisch, S., Corcoran, D., Jarrells, J., et al. (2010). Gene expression divergence recapituates the developmental hourglass model. Nature, 468(7325), 811–814.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lennox, J. G. (1987). Kinds, forms of kinds, and the more and the less in Aristotle’s biology. In A. Gotthelf & J. G. Lennox (Eds.), Philosophical issues in Aristotle’s biology (pp. 339–359). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Lennox, J. (2001). Material and formal natures in Aristotle’s de Partibus Animalium. In J. Lennox (Ed.), Aristotle’s philosophy of biology (pp. 182–204). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (2000). Causation as influence. The Journal of Philosophy, 97(4), 182–197.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewontin, R. (1978). Adaption. Scientific American, 239, 212–228.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Manley, D., & Wasserman, R. (2008). On linking dispositions and conditionals. Mind, 117, 59–84.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mann, R., & Carroll, B. (2002). Molecular mechanics of selector gene function and evolution. Current Opinion in Genetics & Development, 12(5), 592–600.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Martin, C. (2008). The mind in nature. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mayr, E. (1976). Evolution and the diversity of life. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mayr, E. (1992). The idea of teleology. Journal of the History of Ideas, 53(1), 117–135.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McGhee, G. (2006). The geometry of evolution: Adaptive landscapes and theoretical morphospaces. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Müller, G. (2003). Homology: The evolution of morphological organization. In G. B. Muller & S. A. Newman (Eds.), Origination of organismal form: Beyond the gene in developmental and evolutionary biology (pp. 51–69). Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Müller, G. (2008). Evo-devo as a discipline. In A. Minelli & G. Fusco (Eds.), Evolving pathways: Key themes in evolutionary developmental biology (pp. 3–29). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Müller, G., & Newman, S. A. (1999). Generation, integration, autonomy: Three steps in the evolution of homology. Novartis Foundation Symposia, 222, 65–73.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mumford, S., & Anjum, R. (2011). Getting causes from powers. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, E. (1977). Goal-directed processes in biology. The Journal of Philosophy, 74(5), 261–279.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Newman, S., Forgacs, G., & Muller, G. (2006). Before programs: The physical origination of multicellular forms. International Journal of Developmental Biology, 50, 289–299.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Newman, S., & Muller, G. (2006). Genes and form: Inherency in the evolution of developmental mechanisms. In E. Neumann-Held & C. Rehmann-Sutter (Eds.), Genes in development: Re-reading the molecular paradigm (pp. 38–77). Durham: Duke University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Oderberg, D. (2009). The non-identity of the categorical and dispositional. Analysis, 66(2), 677–684.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Okasha, S. (2002). Darwinian metaphysics: Species and the question of essentialism. Sythese, 131(2), 191–213.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pellegrin, P. (1987). Logical difference and biological difference: The unity of Aristotle’s thought. In A. Gotthelf & J. Lennox (Eds.), Philosophical issues in Aristotle’s biology (pp. 313–338). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Pigliucci, M. (2001). Phenotypic plasticity: Beyond nature and nurture. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Raff, R., & Sly, B. (2000). Modularity and dissociation in the evolution of gene expression territories in development. Evolution and Development, 2(2), 102–113.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rasskin-Gutman, D. (2003). Boundary constraints for the emergence of form. In G. Muller & S. Newman (Eds.), The origination of organismal form (pp. 305–322). Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rasskin-Gutman, D. (2005). Modularity: Jumping forms within morphospace. In W. Callebaut, D. Rasskin-Gutman, & H. Simon (Eds.), Modularity: Understanding the development and evolution of natural complex systems (pp. 207–219). Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosa, L., & Etxeberria, A. (2011). Pattern and process in Evo-Devo: Descriptions and explanations. In H. de Regt, S. Hartmann & S. Okasha (Eds.), EPSA Philosophy of Science: Amsterdam 2009 (pp. 263–274). Netherlands: Springer.

  • Rosenberg, A. (2001). On multiple realization and the special sciences. The Journal of Philosophy, 98(7), 365–373.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Salazar-Ciudad, I., & Jernvall, J. (2013). The causality horizon and the developmental bases of morphological evolution. Biological Theory, 8(3), 286–292.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schlichting, C., & Smith, H. (2002). Phenotypic plasticity: Linking molecular mechanisms with evolutionary outcomes. Evolutionary Ecology, 16(3), 189–211.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schrenk, M. (2010). The powerlessness of necessity. Nous, 44(4), 725–739.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shubin, N., Tabin, C., & Carroll, S. (2009). Deep homology and the origins of evolutionary novelty. Nature, 457, 818–823.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sober, E. (1980). Evolution, population thinking, and essentialism. (E. Sober, Ed.). Philosophy of Science, 47(3), 350–383.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Striedter, G. (1998). Stepping into the same river twice: Homologues as recurring attractors in epigenetic landscapes. Brain, Behavior and Evolution, 52, 218–231.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tabata, T. (2001). Genetics of morphogen gradients. Nature, 2(8), 620–630.

    Google Scholar 

  • Verd, B., Crombach, A., & Jaeger, J. (2014). Classification of transient behaviours in a time-dependent toggle switch model. BMC Systems Biology, 8(1), 1–19.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vetter, B. (2013). Multi-track dispositions. The Philosophical Quarterly, 63, 330–352.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • von Dassow, G., Meir, E., Munro, E. M., & Odell, G. M. (2000). The segment polarity network is a robust developmental module. Nature, 406, 188–192.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Von Dassow, G., & Munro, E. (1999). Modularity in animal development and evolution: Elements of a conceptual framework for evo devo. Journal of Experimental Zoology, 285(4), 307–325.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wagner, G. (2000). Characters, units and natural kinds: An introduction. In G. Wagner (Ed.), The character concept in evolutionary biology (pp. 1–10). Greenwich, CT: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wagner, G. (2007). The developmental genetics of homology. Nature Review of Genetics, 8(6), 473–479.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wagner, G. (2014). Homology, genes, and evolutionary innovation. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wagner, G., & Altenberg, L. (1996). Complex adaptations and the evolution of evolvability. Evolution, 50(3), 967–976.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Walsh, D. (2006). Evolutionary essentialism. British Journal of the Philosophy of Science, 57(2), 425–448.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Walsh, D. (2012). Mechanism and purpose: A case of natural teleology. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological Biomedical Sciences, 43(1), 173–181.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wang, J., Zhang, K., Xu, L., & Wang, E. (2011). Quantifying the Waddington landscape and biological paths for development and differentiation. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America, 108(20), 8257–8262.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Webster, G., & Goodwin, C. (2006). The origin of species: A structuralist approach. In E. Neumann-Held & C. Rehmann-Sutter (Eds.), Genes in development: Re-reading the molecular paradigm (pp. 99–134). Durham: Duke University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • West-Eberhard, M. (2003). Developmental plasticity and evolution. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Whitacre, J., & Bender, A. (2010). Networked buffering: A basic mechanism for distributed robustness in complex adaptive systems. Theoretical Biology and Medical Modelling, 7(20), 1–20.

    Google Scholar 

  • Whitman, D. W., & Agrawal, A. A. (2009). What is phenotypic plasiticty and why is it important? In T. N. Ananthakrishna & D. W. Whitman (Eds.), Phenotypic plasticity of insects: Mechanisms and consequences (pp. 1–63). Enfield: Science Publishers.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Wilkins, J. (2013). Biological essentialism and the tidal change of natural kinds. Science & Education, 22(2), 221–240.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, R. (1999). Realism, essence, and kind: resucitating species essentialism? In R. Wilson (Ed.), Species: new interdisciplinary essays (pp. 187–208). Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, R., Barker, M., & Brigandt, I. (2007). When traditional essentialism fails: Biological natural kinds. Philosophical Topics, 35, 189–215.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Winther, R. G. (2001). Varities of modules: Kinds, levels, origins, and behaviors. Journal of Experimental Zoology, 291(2), 116–129.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, J. (2003). Making things happen: A theory of causal explanation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, J. (2010). Causation in biology: Stability, specificity, and the choice of levels of explanation. Biology and Philosophy, 25(3), 287–318.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I am grateful for the generous support of the Analysis Trust.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Christopher J. Austin.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Austin, C.J. Aristotelian essentialism: essence in the age of evolution. Synthese 194, 2539–2556 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-016-1066-4

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-016-1066-4

Keywords

Navigation