Skip to main content
Log in

A pragmatic, existentialist approach to the scientific realism debate

  • S.I.: New Thinking about Scientific Realism
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

It has become apparent that the debate between scientific realists and constructive empiricists has come to a stalemate. Neither view can reasonably claim to be the most rational philosophy of science, exclusively capable of making sense of all scientific activities. On one prominent analysis of the situation, whether we accept a realist or an anti-realist account of science actually seems to depend on which values we antecedently accept, rather than our commitment to “rationality” per se. Accordingly, several philosophers have attempted to argue in favour of scientific realism or constructive empiricism by showing that one set of values is exclusively best, for anyone and everyone, and that the downstream choice of the philosophy of science which best serves those values is therefore best, for anyone and everyone. These efforts, however, seem to have failed. In response, I suggest that philosophers of science should suspend the effort to determine which philosophy of science is best for everyone, and instead begin investigating which philosophy of science is best for specific (groups of) people, with specific values, in specific contexts. I illustrate how this might be done by briefly sketching a single case study from the history of science, which seems to show that different philosophies of science are better at motivating different forms of scientific practice.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For more detail on this point, see (Chakravartty 2007a, 2011, as well as Fine 1986a and Kukla 1998, pp. 27–42).

  2. “Epistemic risk” is here understood as the chance of developing false beliefs without any potential practical benefit, in line with the discussion in van Fraassen (2002), Ch. 3.

  3. Chakravartty (2007b, 2011) understands the relation between theories of science and epistemic stances a bit differently than I have here, seeing scientific realism and constructive empiricism as themselves epistemic stances (2011, p. 39). I think it’s important to recognize this as a simplification of the analysis, and potentially a pernicious one, for reasons that are not especially relevant to the topic at hand. In either case, his views in (2004, 2007a) are closer to the above analysis.

  4. Consider, for example, the opening question of Bertrand Russell’s Problems of Philosophy (1912), one of the most classic and basic works of modern philosophy: “Is there any knowledge in the world which is so certain that no reasonable man could doubt it?” (p. 2) Russell goes on to discuss our ordinary beliefs about the external world, our usual probabilistic inferences, and several other traditional philosophical issues, aiming to determine what position the “reasonable man” he refers to at the outset should take on these issues. The implicitly central task of philosophy, in this work as in so many others, is to determine what position is mandated by a commitment to rationality alone.

  5. It should be noted that the idea of working through the scientific realism debate on pragmatic and existentialist considerations was originally put forward, in those terms, by van Fraassen (2000, p. 273, 2002). He notes that, by taking a meta-epistemologically voluntarist perspective on the debate, “[t]he element of personal decision, values, and volition has entered and received a legitimate place in our epistemic life” while noting that “[by] itself, however, this element is no cure-all” (2002, p. 91). His account is more suggestive than the version I present here in terms of explicit, methodologically grounded assumptions for further inquiry into the connections between epistemic stances and success in certain practical activities.

  6. Even as a matter of methodology this may be an uncomfortable assumption for any philosopher used to universalizing argument, which strives to determine which position amongst an array of options should be accepted by anyone and everyone, regardless of their individual circumstances. It might even be objected that this assumption ultimately leads to a pernicious and unpalatable form of relativism, for combining an existentialist approach to the question of value selection with a voluntarist minimal epistemic stance selection means nothing less than accepting that different epistemic stances will be rational for different people, or even for the same person in different places and at different times. Such objections are misplaced. Universalizing arguments about the values informing epistemic stance choice have, to date, failed. An existentialist approach to the question of value selection is specifically meant to help us avoid that apparently fruitless mode of argument. Furthermore, justifying certain philosophical assumptions on the basis of their methodological fruitfulness is not without precedence. It is quite common in the history and sociological study of science (see Latour and Woolgar 1979), for example, where it has produced some truly fascinating results (Shapin and Schaffer 1985; Arabatzis 2006, etc.). If the existentialist assumption nevertheless proves too uncomfortable, I invite those interested in the issue of epistemic stance choice to either continue attempts to universally ground values, or to find some suitably weaker assumptions to work with. But I think it is clear that the existentialist assumption is sufficient for the purpose here intended: preventing people from arguing over the acceptability of certain values.

  7. These issues are more extensively dealt with in Fine (1984a, b, 1986a, b) as well as Kukla (1998). Both authors echo van Fraassen’s contention that anti-realism, like realism, can account for all relevant aspects of scientific practice, and that as a result the scientific realism debate cannot be decided on the basis of some scientific activities being “laden” with realist or anti-realist assumptions. Psillos (2000) gives what I consider a failed attempt to show that some scientific activities are, in fact, “realism-laden” enough to warrant our acceptance of scientific realism as the correct philosophical account of science.

  8. See van Fraassen (2004) for more detail on what it means for a philosopher to determine “adequacy criteria” operant in scientific theorizing.

  9. See Wise (1981) or Woodruff (1962) for brief but excellently detailed discussions of Weber’s program, in the context of contemporary approaches. For a shorter account, see (Buchwald 1994, Ch. 1). For an extensive account of his model of the atom, including a discussion of its relation to gravitational effects, see Assis et al. (2011).

  10. For example, see the discussion of “detection properties” in Chakravartty (2007a) for a realist understanding of scientific instruments along these lines.

  11. Sir David Gill once reminisced of Maxwell that “his experiments always failed” (Forbes 1916, p. 17). A “failed” experiment of this sort was possible mainly because Maxwell used physical experiments not to discover new phenomena, or to make precise measurements of relevant parameters, but rather only to illustrate established physical principles. His invention of the colour top to illustrate the trichromatic theory of colour, his use of a zoetrope to illustrate the motion of smoke rings traveling in the same direction, and his plaster model of Gibb’s thermodynamic surface for water all speak to the way Maxwell treated laboratory work: as a means of illustration of broader theoretical principles. Thought experiments, by contrast, were often used to a different purpose, specifically the extraction of analytic principles that could be matched to the known phenomena and, eventually, redemonstrated in the lab. But physical experiment, in the Maxwellians’ day-to-day practice, had little to no role in the process of theory-building.

  12. For more on Maxwell’s characteristic scientific methods, with emphasis on the philosophical commitments behind them, see Morrison (1992).

  13. There are other ways we might characterize the Maxwellian’s chosen epistemic stance, e.g. as a form of fictionalism. Nevertheless, since our concern in this sketch is primarily with determining the way that adopting speculative metaphysics or empiricism motivates certain forms of scientific practice, we need not dwell on determining how best to characterize the Maxwellian philosophy of science or epistemic stance. Future characterization and investigations of epistemic stances beyond the empiricism/speculative metaphysics dichotomy are certainly warranted, though outside the scope of this particular paper.

  14. For more on Helmholtz’s empiricist vision and how it affected his scientific activities, see Moulines (1981) and Turner (1977).

References

  • Arabatzis, T. (2006). Representing electrons: A biographical approach to theoretical entities. Chicago: Chicago University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Assis, A. K. T., Wolfschmidt, K. H., & Wiederkehr, G. (2011). Weber’s planetary model of the atom. Hamburg: Tredition Science.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buchwald, J. (1993). Electrodynamics in context: Object states, laboratory practice, and anti-romanticism. In D. Cahan (Ed.), Hermann von Helmholtz and the foundations of nineteenth-century science (pp. 334–373). Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buchwald, J. (1994). The creation of scientific effects. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright, N. (2007). Why be hanged for even a lamb? In B. Monton (Ed.), Images of empiricism: Essays on science and stances, with a reply from Bas van Fraassen (pp. 32–45). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Chakravartty, A. (2004). Stance relativism: Empiricism versus metaphysics. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 35, 173–184.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chakravartty, A. (2007a). A metaphysics for scientific realism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Chakravartty, A. (2007b). Six degrees of speculation: Metaphysics in empirical contexts. In B. Monton (Ed.), Images of empiricism: Essays on science and stances, with a reply from Bas C. van Fraassen (pp. 183–208). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Chakravartty, A. (2011). A puzzle about voluntarism about rational epistemic stances. Synthese, 178, 37–48.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fine, Arthur (1984a). ”The Natural Ontological Attitude” in Leplin (1984), pp. 83-107. Reprinted in Fine (1986a), pp. 112-135.

  • Fine, A. (1984b). And not antirealism either. Noûs, 18(1), 51–65.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fine, A. (1986a). The shaky game: Einstein, realism, and the quantum theory. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fine, A. (1986b). Unnatural attitudes: Realist and instrumentalist attachments to science. Mind, 96, 149–179.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Forbes, G. (1916). Memories of Sir David Gill, K.C.B, H.M. Astronomer (1879-1907) at the Cape of Good Hope. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hendry, R. (2001). Are realism and instrumentalism methodologically indifferent? Proceedings of the Philosophy of Science Association, 2001(3), S25–37.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hertz, H. (1962). Electric waves: Being researches on the propagation of electric action with finite velocity through space, 1892 (D. E. Jones, Trans.). New York: Dover Publications.

  • Hesse, M. (1966). Models and analogies in science. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Korsgaard, C. (2009). Self-constitution: Agency, identity, and integrity. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kukla, A. (1998). Studies in scientific realism. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Latour, B., & Woolgar, S. (1979). Laboratory life: The construction of scientific facts. Beverly Hills: Sage Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lipton, P. (2004). Epistemic options. Philosophical Studies, 121, 147–158.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leplin, J. (1986). Methodological realism and scientific rationality. Philosophy of Science, 53, 31–51.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maxwell, J. C. (1873). A treatise on electricity and magnetism. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Meulders, M. (2010). Helmholtz: From enlightenment to neuroscience. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Monton, B. (2007). Images of empiricism: Essays on science and stances, with a reply from Bas C. van Fraassen. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Morrison, M. (1992). A study in theory unification: The case of Maxwell’s electromagnetic theory. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 23(1), 103–145.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moulines, C. U. (1981). Hermann von Helmholtz: A physiological approach to the theory of knowledge. In H. N. Jahnke & M. Otte (Eds.), Epistemological and social problems of the sciences in the early nineteenth century (pp. 65–73). Boston: D. Reidel.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Psillos, S. (2000). Agnostic empiricism versus scientific realism: Belief in truth matters. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 14(1), 57.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Russell, B. (1912). The problems of philosophy. London: Barnes and Noble.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shapin, S., & Schaffer, S. (1985). Leviathan and the air-pump: Hobbes, Boyle, and the experimental life. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Turner, R. S. (1977). Hermann von Helmholtz and the empiricist vision. Journal of the History of the Behavioral Sciences, 13, 48–58.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van Fraassen, B. (1980). The scientific image. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Van Fraassen, B. (1991). Quantum mechanics: An empiricist view. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Van Fraassen, B. (2000). The false hopes of traditional epistemology. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, LX, 2, 253–280.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van Fraassen, B. (2002). The empirical stance. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Fraassen, B. (2004). Science as representation: Flouting the criteria. Philosophy of Science, 71, 794–804.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van Fraassen, B. (2005). Replies to discussion on the empirical stance. Philosophical Studies, 121, 171–192.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van Fraassen, B. (2008). Scientific representation: Paradoxes of perspective. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • von Helmholtz, H. (1871). Gustav Magnus in Memorandum: Address to the Leibniz Meeting of the Academy of Sciences, July 6, 1871 (H. von Helmholtz, Ed., Popular Lectures on Scientific Subjects, E. Atkinson, Trans.). London: Longmans, Green, and Co.

  • Wise, M. N. (1981). German concepts of force, energy, and the electromagnetic ether, 1845–1880. In G. N. Cantor & M. J. S. Hodge (Eds.), Conceptions of ether: Studies in the history of ether theories, 1740–1900 (pp. 269–307). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woodruff, A. E. (1962). Action at a distance in nineteenth century electrodynamics. Isis, 53(4), 439–459.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Curtis Forbes.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Forbes, C. A pragmatic, existentialist approach to the scientific realism debate. Synthese 194, 3327–3346 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-016-1015-2

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-016-1015-2

Keywords

Navigation