Skip to main content
Log in

An angry young man

A close reading of Arthur Prior’s contribution to social ontology

  • S.I. : The Logic and Philosophy of A.N. Prior
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper is about one of Arthur Prior’s earliest publications in philosophy, “The Nation and the Individual” (Austral J Psychol Philos 15:394–398, 1937). Its aims are (1) to show that Prior made a remarkable contribution to social ontology in the 1930s which should be read with some attention to its historical background, which closely follows John Wisdom as to its theoretical elements, in particular the notion of a “logical construction”, but which is more clearly eliminativist with regard to nations and which is original in terms of rather bold ethical consequences; (2) to interpret Prior’s/Wisdom’s proposal as a promise of reduction by translation and to connect Prior’s/Wisdom’s ideas with John Searle’s recent work on social ontology.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Prior (1933a, b, 1935) may be said to be philosophical in nature, even though they concern theological questions. Prior (1935) might even be regarded as a paper on the philosophy of religion.

  2. For Prior’s position as a (reformed, Barthian, socialist) Christian at the time cf. the article by David Jakobsen in the present volume.

  3. Cf. [New Zealand] Ministry for Culture and Heritage (2012a): “Just over 100,000 New Zealanders served overseas in the First World War [...]. More than 18,000 died [...] and over 40,000 more were wounded. [...] The total population of New Zealand in 1914 was just over one million.”

  4. Cf. ibid., /conscientious-objection: “People could gain exemption from conscription on very limited grounds. By the end of the war only 73 objectors had been offered exemption, and 273 were in prison in New Zealand for refusing to serve. As a consequence of their actions, 2600 conscientious objectors lost their civil rights, including [...] being barred from working for government or local bodies.”

  5. Cf. [New Zealand] Ministry for Culture and Heritage (2012b): “Over 800 conscientious objectors were sent to detention camps.” In the long interview Mary Prior gave to Per Hasle, she says about the period between 1946 and 1949 (Prior 2003a, p. 294): “Returned servicemen and former conscientious objectors filled the classrooms along with people straight from school.”

  6. Cf. the website of the Imperial War Museum, London, http://www.iwm.org.uk/collections/item/object/28305.

  7. For details cf. the editors’ introductions to volumes 13 and 14 of Russell’s Collected Papers (=Russell 1988a, 1995).

  8. Cf. the excellent survey in Linsky (2012), cf. also Linsky (2007). I am grateful to Martin Pleitz for drawing my attention to it and, in general, to the importance of Russell in connection with the topic of this paper. Stebbing (1930), p. 157, and Wisdom (1931a), p. 188, are right to criticize Russell for identifying logical constructions/fictions and “incomplete symbols”. Russell’s examples (numbers, classes, desks, persons) are clearly not examples of symbols. So Linsky (2012), too, is right in not taking them to be examples of symbols, at least in general.

  9. “Nationalism, in theory, is the doctrine that men, by their sympathies and traditions, form natural groups, called ‘nations,’ each of which ought to be united under one central Government. In the main this doctrine may be conceded. [...] When an Englishman returns to Dover [...] after being on the Continent, he feels something friendly in the familiar ways: the casual porters, the shouting paper boys, the women serving bad tea, all warm his heart, and seem more ‘natural,’ more what human beings ought to be, than the foreigners with their strange habits of behaviour.” (Russell 1916, p. 30, 37). “Switzerland is a nation [...] Great Britain was one state before it was one nation; [...] Germany was one nation before it was one state. What constitutes a nation is a [...] sentiment of similarity and an instinct of belonging to the same group or herd. [...] like a milder and more extended form of family feeling. [...] There is an instinctive and usually unconscious sense of a common purpose animating the members of a nation.” (Russell 1917, Chap. 5).

  10. Coombe-Tennant’s paraphrase of these aspects of Wisdom’s papers (Coombe-Tennant 1936) is not only valuable, because it is more readable than Wisdom’s texts, but also because it makes clear that the papers are concerned in an interesting way with what today’s ontologists call granularity.

  11. I am grateful to Jørgen Albretsen for kindly providing me access to digital photographs of the context of box 11 which were taken by David Jakobsen. Numbers refer to the jpg files I used.

  12. For instance, Prior included articles on Rosa Luxemburg (467), Lenin (445) and Trotzki (437), but also on show trials in Moscow (436), as well an article by Prior’s friend Alex Miller on “Pacifism as a civic duty” which is dated on September 20, 1940 (554).

  13. Wisdom’s influence is globally acknowledged (Prior 1937, p. 294). A proper footnote would not have been out of place, but the text is easy enough to trace. For a synopsis cf. the appendix to the present paper.

  14. Systematically, the position that Prior is paraphrasing here is position (a) in Wisdom (1933b, p. 197), which, without any mention of Fascism or organicism, is characterized by the claims “England is something over and above Englishmen” and “When we say England is a monarchy we are not just speaking about Englishmen.”

  15. Note, however, that even Prior’s example is war against France, which was not on the agenda in 1937, but had been a commonplace for half a millennium and is used as such in Wisdom (1931a), 191 f., p. 215; (1933a), pp. 46–55, 65, and in Coombe-Tennant (1936), pp. 437–441.

  16. Wisdom is aware of such predicates and calls them “grammatically polygamous” (Wisdom 1931a, p. 190). Coombe-Tennant (1936, 438 f.) provides the following example: “to say that a man loved England and his friend would be like saying that he took his hat and his leave.”

  17. for an impression, cf. the appendix.

  18. One translation project that worked out remarkably well is Prior’s translation of B-series talk to talk about tensed facts in A-series idiom in Prior (2003b).

  19. Both Margaret Gilbert’s and Russell’s views (cf. Gilbert 1989 and the quote from Russell 1917, Chap. 5, in footnote 9) are, in my opinion, open to the charge of what Popper criticizes as “tribalism” (Popper 1945).

  20. From “the formation” to “his needs”.

  21. The slogan is from Marx’ Critique of the Gotha programme of the German social democratic party, written in 1875. The German original, derived from a French socialist slogan of the 1840s, reads: “Jeder nach seinen Fähigkeiten, Jedem nach seinen Bedürfnissen!” (Marx 1985, p. 15). Prior accurately quotes a widespread English translation whose author I have been unable to identify. The recent translation by Carver retains the punctuation (Marx 1996, p. 215). The context of the slogan is a vision of classless society. The German original is paratactic. Here, “Jedem” (“to each”, dative case) is not the indirect object of any sentence of which “Jeder” (nominative case) is the grammatical subject. Both the comma and the capital “J” of “Jedem” exclude this. Nothing corresponds to “from” in the English translation.

  22. Cf. footnote 12 on the date of the clipping visible in jpg file 554.

References

  • Beany, M. (2003). Susan Stebbing on Cambridge and Vienna analysis. In F. Stadler (Ed.), The Vienna circle and Logical Empiricism (pp. 339–350). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Coombe-Tennant, A. F. H. (1936). Mr. Wisdom on philosophical analysis. Mind, 45(180), 432–449.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert, M. (1989). On social facts. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jakobsen, D. Theology as an illusion somehow close to life. Revisiting A.N. Prior’s crisis of faith. In the present volume

  • Linsky, B. (2012). Logical constructions. In: E. N. Edward (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Winter 2012 Edition). http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2012/entries/logical-construction

  • Linsky, B. (2007). Logical analysis and logical construction. In M. Beaney (Ed.), The analytic turn (pp. 107–122). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marx, Karl (1985). Kritik des Gothaer Programms (1875, firstpublication: 1891). In: Marx Engels Gesamtausgabe (MEGA)[Collected Works of Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels], section I vol. 25. Berlin: Dietz

  • Marx, K. (1996). Critique of the Gotha programme. In T. Carver (Ed.), Marx. later political writings (pp. 208–226). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Ministry for Culture and Heritage [New Zealand]. (2012a). Conscientious objection in the First World War. http://www.nzhistory.net.nz/war/first-world-war. Accessed December 20, 2012

  • Ministry for Culture and Heritage [New Zealand]. (2012b). Opposition to war: Second World War overview. http://www.nzhistory.net.nz/war/second-world-war-overview/opposition. Accessed December 20, 2012

  • Prior, A. (1933a). Prayer and praise. Open Windows, 7(1), 18–19.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prior, A. (1933b). Dostoevsky. Open Windows, 7(5), 5–6.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prior, A. (1935). Logic and dogma. Open Windows, 9(5), 19.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prior, A. (1937). The Nation and the Individual. The Australasian Journal of Psychology and Philosophy, 15, 394–398.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Prior, A. (2003a). In: P. Halse, P. Øhrstrøm, T. Braüner, T. Braüner & J. Copeland (Eds.), Papers on time and tense. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Prior, Arthur (2003b). Tense logic and the logic of earlier and later [1968], In: Prior (2003a), 117–138.

  • Prior, Arthur (2003c). Egocentric logic [1968], in: Prior (2003a), 223–240.

  • Popper, K. R. (1945). The open society and its enemies. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, B. (1905). On denoting. Mind, 14, 473–493.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, B. (1916). Principles of social reconstruction. London: George Allen and Unwin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, B. (1917). Political ideals. New York: The Century Company.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Russell, B. (1986). The philosophy of logical atomism (1918). In G. John (Ed.), The collected papers of Bertrand Russell (Vol. 8). London: George Allen and Unwin: Slater.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, B. (1988a). The collected papers of Bertrand Russell. In R. Rempel, B. Frohmann, M. Lippincott, & M. Moran (Eds.), Prophecy and dissent (Vol. 13). London: Unwin Hyman.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, B. (1988b). The nature of the state in view of its external relations (1916). In: Collected papers (vol. 13, pp. 362–369)

  • Russell, B. (1995). The collected papers of Bertrand Russell. In R. Rempel, L. Greenspan, B. Haslam, A. C. Lewis, & M. Lippincott (Eds.), Pacifism and revolution (Vol. 14). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schlick, Moritz (1935a). “Über den Begriff der Ganzheit” (short version). Erkenntnis 5(1), 52–55. (MSGA [=Collected Works] I/6, 553–557).

  • Schlick, Moritz (1935b) “Über den Begriff der Ganzheit” [full version], In: Wissenschaftlicher Jahresbericht der Philosophischen Gesellschaft an der Universität zu Wien. Wien: Verlag der Philosophischen Gesellschaft 1935, 23–37 (MSGA [=Collected Works] I/6, 681–700).

  • Searle, J. (1995). The construction of social reality. New York: The Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. (2010). Making the social world. The structure of human civilization. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Searle, John/Smith, Barry (2003). The construction of social reality: An exchange. American Journal of Economics and Sociology, 62(2), 285–309. Also in: Laurence Moss/David Koepsell (eds.), Searle on the Institutions of Social Reality, Oxford: Blackwell

  • Stebbing, S. (1930). A modern introduction to logic. London: Methuen.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strobach, N. (2005). Juristische Personen. In: G. Schönrich, (Ed.), Institutionen und ihre Ontologie, (pp. 189–210). Heusenstamm bei Frankfurt a.M.: Ontos-Verlag

  • Strobach, N. (2013). Der Begriff der Ganzheit bei Moritz Schlick und heute (Moritz–Schlick Lecture 2011). In: F. O. Engler & M. Iven (Eds.), Moritz Schlick—Die Rostocker Jahre und ihr Einfluss auf die Wiener Zeit (pp. 23–66). Leipzig: Leipziger Universitätsverlag

  • Wisdom, J. (1931a). Logical constructions (I.). Mind, 40(158), 188–216.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wisdom, J. (1931b). Logical constructions (II.). Mind, 40(160), 460–475.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wisdom, J. (1932). Logical constructions (III.). Mind, 41(164), 441–464.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wisdom, J. (1933a). Logical constructions (IV.). Mind, 42(165), 43–66.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wisdom, J. (1933b). Logical constructions (V.). Mind, 42(166), 186–202.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Niko Strobach.

Additional information

This text is dedicated to my uncle Herbert Strobach, who, aged 17 in 1945, saw no point in defending a country road in northern Germany against British tanks and was lucky to escape execution.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Strobach, N. An angry young man. Synthese 193, 3417–3427 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-015-0901-3

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-015-0901-3

Keywords

Navigation