Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Mapping the mind: bridge laws and the psycho-neural interface

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Recent advancements in the brain sciences have enabled researchers to determine, with increasing accuracy, patterns and locations of neural activation associated with various psychological functions. These techniques have revived a longstanding debate regarding the relation between the mind and the brain: while many authors claim that neuroscientific data can be employed to advance theories of higher cognition, others defend the so-called ‘autonomy’ of psychology. Settling this significant issue requires understanding the nature of the bridge laws used at the psycho-neural interface. While these laws have been the topic of extensive discussion, such debates have mostly focused on a particular type of link: reductive laws. Reductive laws are problematic: they face notorious philosophical objections and they are too scarce to substantiate current research at the intersection of psychology and neuroscience. The aim of this article is to provide a systematic analysis of a different kind of bridge laws—associative laws—which play a central, albeit overlooked role in scientific practice.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. As Fodor notes, reductive bridge laws express a stronger position than token physicalism, the view that all events that fall under the laws of some special science are physical events. Statements such as \(R_1\) and \(R_2\) presuppose type physicalism, according to which every kind that figures in the laws of a science is type-identical to a physical kind. Since our focus is not on physicalism per se; the relevant claim is whether the kinds of one science can be reduced to the kinds of a more fundamental science, not necessarily to physics.

  2. However, it has been persuasively argued that any form of bona fide reductionism requires some kind of bridge laws (Marras 2002; Fazekas 2009).

  3. In an influential discussion, Marr (1982) argued that information-processing systems should be investigated at three complementary levels. Hypotheses at Marr-level 1 pose the computational problem: they state the task computed by the system. Hypotheses at Marr-level-2 state the algorithm used to compute Marr-level 1 functions: they specify the basic representations and operations of the system. Finally, hypotheses at Marr-level 3 specify how Marr-level 2 algorithms are implemented in the brain: they purport to explain how these basic representations and operations are realized at the neural level.

  4. In general, the amygdala is critically involved in conditioned and unconditioned fear response in animals, including humans. For example, patients with selective damage to the amygdala show no physiological response to a previously fear-conditioned stimulus, although they can explicitly remember the conditioning experience (Kandel et al. 2013, Ch. 48).

  5. Miller and Cohen (2001) present several studies that support the key role of the DLPFC in cognitive control and rule-guided processes. A relevant set of experiments are based on the famous Stroop task, in which subjects are instructed to name the color of the ink of words as they appear on a screen. Famously, reaction times and error rates increase dramatically when subjects read color-terms that differ from the color of their ink. Miller and Cohen present imaging studies which show that, in the misleading cases, subjects who manage to follow the correct rule and name the word’s ink color showed increased activation in DLPFC, compared to subjects who fail the task.

  6. In the classic version of the trolley problem, personal cases are exemplified by the ‘footbridge’ scenario, where five people are saved by throwing a corpulent person on the track. Impersonal cases are exemplified by the ‘switch’ scenario, where five people are saved by pulling a lever that diverts the trolley onto a parallel track where it will kill a single person.

  7. We surmise that the task relativity of reverse inferences is systematically overlooked because methodological discussions (e.g., Poldrack 2006; Phelps 2006) often consider only arbitrary ‘empty’ tasks which do not eliminate any processing possibilities (that is, any bridge laws) for the brain region of interest. Hence, reverse inferences seem intuitively weak. However, once we consider the tasks relevant to each reverse inference, we can eliminate some subset of bridge laws which cover the brain regions of interest, thereby increasing their strength.

  8. An alternative is to reformulate reverse inference in likelihoodist terms (Machery 2014). Consider two competing cognitive hypotheses \(m_1\) and \(m_2\) and neural activation data \(n_1\). On this view, \(n_1\) favors \(m_1\) over \(m_2\) if and only if \(P(n_1|m_1)>P(n_1|m_2)\). In a likelihoodist framework, one only compares cognitive hypotheses that are under dispute, treating reverse inference as an inherently comparative technique that tells us which among the competing hypotheses is favored by some neural evidence. One drawback of this suggestion is that evidence becomes purely comparative. On the other hand, the advantage of this approach is that the relevant likelihoods can be calculated without having to determine the base rates of activation of the brain regions involved. We should note that the main reason why Machery prefers this likelihoodist approach to reverse inference over the Bayesian account is that Eq. 1 cannot, in general, be computed. This is because neuroscientists rarely know the base rates of activation of particular brain regions of interest. It is not clear whether Machery thinks this is still a serious problem for Huzler’s refined Eq. 2, since he does not directly consider that option. However, we should also note that there is a substantial literature on Bayesianism and imprecise probabilities that can be used to address Machery’s concern (Joyce 2011).

  9. Cases where classifiers cannot perform significantly above chance can still be interesting, albeit for different reasons. Suppose that, in task \(t\), a classifier underperforms when using data sets taken from some region \(n_1\), but performs significantly above chance when using data from region \(n_2\). This provides evidence that \(n_2\) carries information relevant to performing \(t\), whereas \(n_1\) does not.

  10. Of course, this does not mean that there are no difficulties in using this method. Appropriate experimental design is crucial, especially since pattern classifiers are designed to use whatever information is available to make better predictions. In addition, there is still a question whether we can extend the reliability of classifiers obtained from the testing phase to cases in which the experiments cannot determine the engagement of the psychological variables, since the latter inevitably involve some variation on the task. There are various studies which suggest that classifiers perform well under task variations. For example, in one study pattern classifiers were used to predict phonemes. The classifiers were still successful when presented with data from voices which were not presented in the learning phase (Formisano et al. 2008). Hence, at least this much variation in the task does not affect performance. In a study of visual working memory, classifiers were trained on data elicited by unattended gratings, and then tested on whether they could also predict which of two orientations was maintained on working memory when subjects were viewing a blank screen. Again, their reliability was maintained despite the substantial difference in stimulus and task (Harrison and Tong 2009). Indeed, testing for this kind of robustness relative to stimuli/task variation is usually taken as evidence that the brain region from which the data was obtained really does provide information about the function of interest (Tong and Pratte 2012).

References

  • Anderson, M. (2010). Review of neuroeconomics: Decision making and the brain, eds. Glimcher, Camerer, Fehr, and Poldrack. Journal of Economic Psychology, 31, 151–154.

  • Bechtel, W., & Mundale, J. (1999). Multiple realizability revisited: Linking cognitive and neural states. Philosophy of Science, 66, 175–207.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bickle, J. (1998). Psychoneural reduction: The new wave. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bickle, J. (2003). Philosophy and neuroscience: A ruthlessly reductive account. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bourget, D., & Chalmers, D. (2013). What do philosophers believe? Philosophical Studies, 3, 1–36.

    Google Scholar 

  • Camerer, C. F., Loewenstein, G., & Prelec, D. (2005). Neuroeconomics: How neuroscience can inform economics. Journal of Economic Literature, 43, 9–64.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Churchland, P. (1986). Neurophilosophy. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Churchland, P. M. (1981). Eliminative materialism and the propositional attitudes. The Journal of Philosophy, 78(2), 67–90.

    Google Scholar 

  • Coltheart, M. (2013). How can functional neuroimaging inform cognitive theories? Perspectives on Psychological Science, 8(1), 98–103.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Del Pinal, G., & Nathan, M. J. (2013). There and up again: On the uses and misuses of neuroimaging in psychology. Cognitive Neuropsychology, 30(4), 233–252.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Enç, B. (1983). In defense of identity theory. The Journal of Philosophy, 80, 279–298.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fazekas, P. (2009). Reconsidering the role of bridge laws in inter-theoretic relations. Erkenntnis, 71, 303–322.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. (1974). Special sciences (Or: The disunity of science as a working hypothesis). Synthese, 28, 97–115.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. A. (1997). Special sciences: Still autonomous after all these years. Nous, 31, 149–163.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J.A. (1999). Let your brain alone. London Review of Books 21.

  • Formisano, E., De Martino, F., Bonte, M., & Goebel, R. (2008). ‘Who’ is saying ‘what’? Brain-based decoding of human voice and speech. Science, 322, 970–973.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallistel, C. R. (2009). The neural mechanisms that underlie decision making. In P. W. Glimcher, C. F. Camerer, E. Fehr, & R. A. Poldrack (Eds.), Neuroeconomics: Decision Theory and the Brain (pp. 419–424). New York: Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gazzaniga, M. S. (Ed.). (2009). The cognitive neurosciences (4th ed.). Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Glimcher, P. W., & Fehr, E. (Eds.). (2014). Neuroeconomics: Decision making and the brain (2nd ed.). Burlington: Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Greene, J. (2009). The cognitive neuroscience of moral judgment. In M. S. Gazzaniga (Ed.), The cognitive neurosciences. chap 68 (4th ed., pp. 987–999). Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Greene, J., Sommerville, R., Nystrom, L., Darley, J., & Cohen, J. (2001). An fMRI investigation of emotional engagement in moral judgment. Science, 293, 2105–2108.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harrison, S. A., & Tong, F. (2009). Decoding reveals the contents of visual working memory in early visual areas. Nature, 458, 632–635.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Henson, R. (2005). What can functional neuroimaging tell the experimental psychologist? Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology, 58A, 193–233.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hooker, C. A. (1981). Towards a general theory of reduction. Part III: Cross-categorical reductions. Dialogue, 20, 496–529.

    Google Scholar 

  • Horst, S. (2007). Beyond reduction: Philosophy of mind and post-reductionist philosophy of science. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hutzler, F. (2014). Reverse inference is not a fallacy per se: Cognitive processes can be inferred from functional imaging data. Neuroimage, 84, 1061–1069.

  • Joyce, J. (2011). A defense of imprecise credences in inference and decision making. In T. Szabo Gendler & J. Hawthorne (Eds.), Oxford studies in epistemology. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kandel, E., Schwartz, J., Jessell, T., & Siegelbaum, S. (2013). Principles of naural science (5th ed.). New York: McGraw-Hill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kim, J. (1992). Multiple realization and the metaphysics of reduction. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 52, 1–26.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kim, J. (1999). Mind in a physical world. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kim, J. (2005). Physicalism, or something near enough. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kim, J. (2006). Emergence: Core ideas and issues. Synthese, 151, 547–559.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Klein, C. (2009). Reduction without reductionism: A defense of Nagel on connectability. The Philosophical Quarterly, 59(234), 39–53.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Klein, C. (2011). The dual track theory of moral decision-making: A critique of the neuroimaging evidence. Neuroethics, 4, 143–162.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Knutson, B., Wimmer, E. G., Rick, S., Hollon, N. G., Prelec, D., & Loewenstein, G. (2008). Neural antecedents and the endowment effect. Neuron, 58, 814–822.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, T. S. (1977). Objectivity, value judgment, and theory choice. The essential tension: Selected studies in scientific tradition and change (pp. 320–339). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Legrenzi, P., & Umilta, C. (2011). Neuromania. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. K. (1969). Review of art, mind, and religion. The Journal of Philosophy, 66, 23–35.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lindquist, K. A., Wager, T. D., Kober, H., Bliss-Moreau, E., & Barrett, L. F. (2012). The brain basis of emotion: A meta-analytic review. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 35, 121–202.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Machery, E. (2014). In defense of reverse inference. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 65(2), 251–267.

  • Marr, D. (1982). Vision: A computational investigation into the human representation and processing of visual information. New York: Freeman.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marras, A. (2002). Kim on reduction. Erkenntnis, 57, 231–257.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mather, M., Cacioppo, J.T., Kanwisher, N. (eds) (2013) 20 Years of fMRI—What has it done for understanding cognition, vol 8. Perspectives on Psychological Science.

  • Miller, E. K., & Cohen, J. D. (2001). An integrative theory of prefrontal cortex function. Annual Review of Neuroscience, 24, 167–202.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Miller, G. (2008). Growing pains for fMRI. Science, 320, 1412–1414.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, E. (1961). The structure of science. New York: Harcourt Brace.

    Google Scholar 

  • Norman, K., Quamme, J., & Newman, E. (2009). Multivariate methods for tracking cognitive states. In C. Ranganath, B. Roder, & R. Kluwe (Eds.), Rosler K. Neuroimaging of human memory: Linking cognitive processes to neural systems. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Norman, K., Quamme, J., & Weiss, D. (2010). Listening for recollection: A multi-voxel pattern analysis of recognition memory retrieval strategies. Frontiers in Human Neuroscience, 4, 1–12.

    Google Scholar 

  • Phelps, E. (2006). Emotion and cognition: Insights from studies of the human amygdala. Annual Review of Psychology, 57, 27–53.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Phelps, E. (2009). The study of emotion in neuroeconomics. In P. W. Glimcher, C. F. Camerer, E. Fehr, & R. A. Poldrack (Eds.), Neuroeconomics: Decision making and the brain, chap 16 (pp. 233–250). London: Academic Press.

  • Poldrack, R. A. (2006). Can cognitive processes be inferred from neuroimaging data? Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 10(2), 59–63.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Poldrack, R. A. (2008). The role of fmri is cognitive neuroscience: Where do we stand? Current Opinion in Neurobiology, 18, 223–227.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Poldrack, R. A. (2011). Inferring mental states from neuroimaging data: From reverse inferences to large-scale decoding. Neuron, 72, 692–697.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1967). Psychological predicates. In W. Capitan & D. Merrill (Eds.), Art, mind, and religion (pp. 37–48). Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Recanati, F. (2011). Truth-conditional pragmatics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ross, D. (2008). Two styles of neuroeconomics. Economics and Philosophy, 24, 473–483.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Satel, S., & Lilienfeld, S. (2013). Brainwashed: The seductive appeal of mindless neuroscience. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro, L. A. (2000). Multiple realizations. The Journal of Philosophy, 97(12), 635–654.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stanley, J. (2000). Context and logical form. Linguistics and Philosophy, 23, 391–434.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tong, F., & Pratte, M. S. (2012). Decoding patterns of human brain activity. Annual Review of Psychology, 63, 438–509.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Uttal, W. R. (2001). The new phrenology: The limits of localizing cognitive processes. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Uttal, W. R. (2002). Precis of the new phrenology: The limits of localizing cognitive processes in the brain. Brain and Mind, 3(2), 221–228.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van Orden, G. C., & Paap, K. R. (1997). Functional neuroimages fail to discover pieces of mind in the parts of the brain. Philosophy of Science, 64, S85–S94.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

We are grateful to Max Coltheart, Kateri McRae, Bruce Pennington, and three anonymous reviewers for constructive comments on various versions of this essay. Some of the ideas developed here were presented at the Neuroscience Research Group at the University of Denver, at the 2014 Annual Conference in History and Philosophy of Science at the University of Colorado at Boulder, and at the 2014 Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association in Chicago: all audiences provided helpful feedback.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Marco J. Nathan.

Additional information

Marco J. Nathan and Guillermo Del Pinal contributed equally to this work.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Nathan, M.J., Del Pinal, G. Mapping the mind: bridge laws and the psycho-neural interface. Synthese 193, 637–657 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-015-0769-2

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-015-0769-2

Keywords

Navigation