Skip to main content
Log in

Good weasel hunting

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The ‘indispensability argument’ for the existence of mathematical objects appeals to the role mathematics plays in science. In a series of publications, Joseph Melia has offered a distinctive reply to the indispensability argument. The purpose of this paper is to clarify Melia’s response to the indispensability argument and to advise Melia and his critics on how best to carry forward the debate. We will begin by presenting Melia’s response and diagnosing some recent misunderstandings of it. Then we will discuss four avenues for replying to Melia. We will argue that the three replies pursued in the literature so far are unpromising. We will then propose one new reply that is much more powerful, and—in the light of this—advise participants in the debate where to focus their energies.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Audi, P. (2012). Grounding: Towards a theory of the in-virtue-of relation. Journal of Philosophy, 109, 685–711.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Azzouni, J. (2004). Deflating existential consequence: A case for nominalism. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Azzouni, J. (2009). Evading truth commitments: The problem reanalyzed. Logique & Analyse, 206, 139–176.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baker, A. (2005). Are there genuine mathematical explanations of physical phenomena? Mind, 114, 223–238.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baker, A. (2009). Mathematical explanation in science. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 60, 611–633.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Balaguer, M. (1998). Platonism and anti-platonism in mathematics. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Balaguer, M. (2011). Fictionalism in the philosophy of mathematics. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.) Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Fall 2011 ed.). URL http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2011/entries/fictionalism-mathematics/

  • Bangu, S. (2012). The applicability of mathematics in science: Indispensability and ontology. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Colyvan, M. (2001). The indispensability of mathematics. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Colyvan, M. (2010). There is no easy road to nominalism. Mind, 119, 285–306.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Colyvan, M. (2012). Road work ahead: heavy machinery on the easy road. Mind, 121, 1031–1046.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Crane, T. (1990). An alleged analogy between numbers and propositions. Analysis, 50, 224–230.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Daly, C., & Langford, S. (2009). Mathematical explanation and indispensability arguments. Philosophical Quarterly, 59, 641–658.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Field, H. (1980). Science without numbers: A defence of nominalism. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Field, H. (1989). Realism, mathematics and modality. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Glymour, C. (1980). Theory and evidence. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, F., & Pettit, P. (1990). Program explanation: A general perspective. Analysis, 50, 107–117.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Knowles, R. forthcoming. Heavy duty platonism. Erkenntnis.

  • Leng, M. (2010). Mathematics and reality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Liggins, D. (2008). Quine, Putnam, and the “Quine-Putnam indispensability argument”. Erkenntnis, 68, 113–127.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Liggins, D. (2012). Weaseling and the content of science. Mind, 121, 997–1005.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Liggins, D. (2014). Abstract expressionism and the communication problem. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 65, 599–620.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lyon, A., & Colyvan, M. (2008). The explanatory power of phase spaces. Philosophia Mathematica, 16, 227–243.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lyon, A. (2012). Mathematical explanations of empirical facts, and mathematical realism. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 90, 559–578.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • MacBride, F. (1999). Listening to fictions: A study of Fieldian nominalism. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 50, 431–455.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maddy, P. (2005). Three forms of naturalism. In S. Shapiro (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of philosophy of mathematics and logic (pp. 437–459). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Marcus, R. (2014). The holistic presumptions of the indispensability argument. Synthese, 191, 3575–3594.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Melia, J. (1992). An alleged disanalogy between numbers and propositions. Analysis, 52, 46–48.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Melia, J. (1995). On what there’s not. Analysis, 55, 223–229.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Melia, J. (1998). Field’s programme: Some interference. Analysis, 58, 63–71.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Melia, J. (2000). Weaseling away the indispensability argument. Mind, 109, 455–479.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Melia, J. (2002). Response to Colyvan. Mind, 111, 75–78.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Melia, J. (2003). Review of Colyvan’s The indispensability of mathematics. Metascience, 12, 55–58.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Melia, J. (2008). A world of concrete particulars. Oxford Studies in Metaphysics, 4, 99–124.

    Google Scholar 

  • Melia, J. (2011). Response to Daly and Langford. Mind, 119, 1117–1121.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morrison, J. (2012). Evidential holism and indispensability arguments. Erkenntnis, 76, 263–278.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morrison, M. (2007). Spin: All is not what it seems. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 38, 529–557.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Penrose, R. (1990). The emperor’s new mind: Concerning computers, minds, and the laws of physics. London: Vintage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pincock, C. (2007). A role for mathematics in the physical sciences. Noûs, 41, 253–275.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pincock, C. (2012). Mathematics and scientific representation. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Raley, Y. (2012). Why the weasel fails. Philosophia Mathematica, 20, 339–345.

  • Resnik, M. (1997). Mathematics as a science of patterns. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rizza, D. (2011). Magicicada, mathematical explanation, and mathematical realism. Erkenntnis, 74, 101–114.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rosen, G. (1994). What is constructive empiricism? Philosophical Studies, 74, 143–178.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Saatsi, J. (2011). The enhanced indispensability argument: Representational versus explanatory role of mathematics in science. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 62, 143–154.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Saatsi, J. (2012). Mathematics and program explanations. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 90, 579–584.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Saatsi, J. forthcoming. On the ‘indispensable explanatory role’ of mathematics. Mind.

  • Scott, M., & Brown, P. (2012). Pragmatic antirealism: a new antirealist strategy. Philosophical Studies, 161, 349–366.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sober, E. (1993). Mathematics and indispensability. Philosophical Review, 102, 35–57.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stalnaker, R. (1978). Assertion. Syntax and Semantics, 9, 315–332.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stanley, J. (2001). Hermeneutic fictionalism. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 25, 36–71.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Turner, J. (2011). Review of Yablo’s Things: Philosophical Papers (Vol. 2). URL http://ndpr.nd.edu/news/25473-things-philosophical-papers-volume-2/.

  • Walton, K. L. (1993). Metaphor and prop-oriented make-believe. European Journal of Philosophy, 1, 39–57.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Yablo, S. (2000). A paradox of existence. In A. Everett & T. Hofweber (Eds.), Empty names, fiction and the puzzles of non-existence (pp. 275–312). Stanford: CSLI Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yablo, S. (2001). Go figure: A path through fictionalism. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 25, 72–102.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Yablo, S. (2002). Abstract objects: A case study. Philosophical Issues, 12, 220–240.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

We would like to thank Chris Daly, Joe Morrison, Leo Tarasov, and two anonymous referees for their comments on earlier drafts. Rob Knowles gratefully acknowledges the award of a Jacobsen Studentship by the Royal Institute of Philosophy, which supported the work presented here.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to David Liggins.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Knowles, R., Liggins, D. Good weasel hunting. Synthese 192, 3397–3412 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-015-0711-7

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-015-0711-7

Keywords

Navigation