Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

The feeling of agency hypothesis: a critique

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

A dominant view in contemporary cognitive neuroscience is that low-level, comparator-based mechanisms of motor control produce a distinctive experience often called the feeling of agency (the FoA-hypothesis). An opposing view is that comparator-based motor control is largely non-conscious and not associated with any particular type of distinctive phenomenology (the simple hypothesis). In this paper, I critically evaluate the nature of the empirical evidence researchers commonly take to support FoA-hypothesis. The aim of this paper is not only to scrutinize the FoA-hypothesis and data supposed to support it; it is equally to argue that experimentalists supporting the FoA-hypothesis fail to establish that the experimental outcomes are more probable given the FoA-hypothesis than given the simpler hypothesis.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For similar statements, see (Chambon and Haggard (2013), p. 359), and (Kühn et al. (2013), p. 1936): “We can, and frequently do, make instrumental actions where we have a definite background feeling or buzz of being in control.”

  2. One referee wrote that the argument presented in this paper generalizes to other models of the phenomenal sense of agency, such as optimal cue integration (Synofzik et al. 2008) and some versions of Wegner’s inferential model (e.g. Wegner 2004). Another referee insisted, however, that my arguments only have a limited scope and leave other models untouched. I will leave these issues of scope up to the reader.

  3. See also (Haggard and Tsakiris (2009), p. 243), and (Wenke et al. (2010), p. 35).

  4. It should be noted that the “classical” comparator model of motor control is not unchallenged. See, for example, Friston (2011).

  5. Similar functional stories could be told with respect to the other comparator-based accounts of the feeling of agency.

  6. By “intention” I mean a personal-level state, which is often the outcome of the agent’s practical decision-making. It is a state governed by particular normative and rational constraints. As such, this state is very different from the kind of functional state sometimes referred to by the term “motor intention”. For discussion of this point, see Butterfill and Sinigaglia (2014).

  7. See, e.g., (Tsakiris and Haggard (2005), p. 387).

  8. See also Bayne and Pacherie (2007): “agentive judgments are typically grounded in and justified by agentive experiences. In the normal case, we judge that we are the agent of a particular movement on the grounds that we enjoy an agentive experience with respect to it; here, our agentive judgments are simply endorsements of our agentive experiences” (p. 477).

  9. How does my use of the term “feeling of agency” relate to the more frequent use of the term “sense of agency” that we see in the literature? It is hard to give a clear answer because of the often ambiguous and loose terminology. Often the two terms appear to be simply synonymous but at other times not. According to one prominent way to use “sense of agency”, it refers to a more complex phenomenon involving both low-level phenomenal states and high-level cognitive evaluations and judgements [see Synofzik et al. (2008), Pacherie (2008), and Gallagher (2012), for comparable complex models]. In order to distinguish the target of my critique from this type of more global, complex model, I will stick to the term “feeling of agency”. On some versions of the complex model, something like the FoA-hypothesis is an element.

  10. As has been thoroughly documented by Jeannerod (1997, 2006).

  11. I thank a reviewer for providing me with this sentence.

  12. See Farrer et al. (2003): “[the feeling of agency] is the feeling that leads us to attribute an action to ourselves rather than to another person (p. 324)”.

  13. \(p\)(data|FoA-hypothesis) \(=\) \(p\)(data|simpler hypothesis).

  14. The experimental evidence for this claim is Spence et al. (1997).

  15. Frith & Johnstone (Frith and Johnstone (2003), pp. 137–138) describe these odd experiences as “unexpected sensations” “that indicate that we are not fully in control of our movements” and that “might feel like unpredictable passive movements”.

  16. This seems to be the explanation offered by Frith and Done (1988), and Stirling et al. (1998). Notice that Daprati et al. did not find that patients with delusions of alien control were worse at action-recognition that patients experiencing hallucinations.

  17. It is an open question whether introspective reports are best understood as a judgement about one’s experience or as an expression of one’s experience (see, e.g., Bar-On 2004). This dispute has no implications for the present argument.

  18. As Wegner writes: “Although the proper experiments have not yet been done to test this, it seems likely that people could discriminate the feeling of doing from other feelings, knowing by the sheer quality of the experience just what has happened” (Wegner 2004, p. 658).

  19. \(p\)(data|FoA-hypothesis) \(>p\)(data|simpler hypothesis).

  20. For example, after an interval, the inability to report a stimulus cannot be taken as proof of absence of experience because the subject could simply have forgotten. See, for instance, discussions about overflow of conscious experience in the Sperling-paradigm (Sperling 1960; Block 2011; Phillips 2011).

  21. One reviewer suggested that better cases to discuss would be Wegner’s cases of automatisms (Wegner 2002, Chap. 1 & 4). These are cases where an apparent voluntary movement is performed without any explicit intention or even with explicit disavowal of intention. These are, however, also cases performed without any feeling of agency, if any such exist. Since intentions and feeling of agency disappear together in these cases, they cannot serve as evidence for an intention-free feeling of agency. Furthermore, most of the descriptions are anecdotal. The subjective reports vastly underdetermine our choice of phenomenological description.

  22. The neurocognitive approach to psychopathology is of course not universally accepted. For another influential but fundamentally conflicting approach, see Bovet and Parnas (1993), Parnas (1999), and Parnas et al. (2005).

  23. A similar view is endorsed by (Coltheart et al. (2010), p. 264) (in an explanation of Capgras delusion): “the first delusion-relevant event of which the patient is aware is the belief”.

  24. Similar view is expressed by (Coltheart (2005), p. 155) : “Only when a prediction fails does consciousness get involved; the unconscious system makes some kind of report to consciousness to instigate some intelligent conscious problem-solving behavior that will discover what’s wrong.”

  25. The argument works by exclusion. Maybe there are contrast cases I have not considered that are genuinely informative. Some authors also use the case of Anarchic Hand Syndrome (e.g. Bayne 2011). This type of case can easily be dismissed. Since both intention and (alleged) feeling of agency are missing in AHS, they are not informative with respect to an intention-free feeling of agency. See, for example, (Cheyne et al. (2009), p. 481): “[...] the intentions do not seem to be their concurrent intentions and hence agency is transferred from self to hand. Such patients have experienced not merely a loss, but an active alienation, of agency for the anarchic actions”. See also, Kritikos et al. (2005), and Della Sala (2005).

  26. See (Pacherie (2001), p. 174): “our ordinary experience of agency may simply be a rather diffuse sense of a coherent ongoing flow of anticipations and sensory feedback.” Also (Hohwy and Frith (2004), p. 185).

  27. See Grünbaum (2011), for an argument in support of the idea that perception often has a distinctive, epistemic function in agents’ knowledge of their own actions.

References

  • Bar-On, D. (2004). Speaking my mind: Expression and self-knowledge. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bayne, T. (2011). The sense of agency. In F. Macpherson (Ed.), The senses. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bayne, T., & Levy, N. (2006). The feeling of doing: Deconstructing the phenomenology of agency. In N. Sebanz & W. Prinz (Eds.), Disorders of volition. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bayne, T., & Pacherie, E. (2007). Narrators and comparators: The architecture of agentive self-awareness. Synthese, 15(3), 475–491.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blakemore, S. J., Wolpert, D. M., & Frith, C. D. (1998). Central cancellation of self-produced tickle sensation. Nature Neuroscience, 1(7), 635–640.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Block, N. (2011). Perceptual consciousness overflows cognitive access. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 15(12), 567–575.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bovet, P., & Parnas, J. (1993). Schizophrenic delusions: A phenomenological approach. Schizophrenia Bulletin, 19(3), 579.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Butterfill, S. A., & Sinigaglia, C. (2014). Intention and motor representation in purposive action. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 88, 119–145.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carruthers, G. (2012). The case for the comparator model as an explanation of the sense of agency and its breakdowns. Consciousness and Cognition, 21(1), 30–45.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chambon, V., & Haggard, P. (2013). Premotor or ideomotor: How does the experience of action come about? In W. Prinz, M. Beisert, & A. Herwig (Eds.), Action science: Foundations of an emerging discipline. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chambon, V., Wenke, D., Fleming, S. M., Prinz, W., & Haggard, P. (2013). An online neural substrate for sense of agency. Cerebral Cortex, 23(5), 1031–1037.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cheyne, J. A., Carriere, J. S., & Smilek, D. (2009). Absent minds and absent agents: Attention-lapse induced alienation of agency. Consciousness and Cognition, 18(2), 481–493.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Coltheart, M. (2005). Conscious experience and delusional belief. Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology, 12(2), 153–157.

    Google Scholar 

  • Coltheart, M. (2007). Cognitive neuropsychiatry and delusional belief. The Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology, 60(8), 1041–1062.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Coltheart, M., Menzies, P., & Sutton, J. (2010). Abductive inference and delusional belief. Cognitive Neuropsychiatry, 15(1–3), 261–287.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Coltheart, M., Langdon, R., & McKay, R. (2011). Delusional belief. Annual Review of Psychology, 62, 271–298.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Daprati, E., Franck, N., Georgieff, N., Proust, J., Pacherie, E., Dalery, J., et al. (1997). Looking for the agent. An investigation into consciousness of action and self-consciousness in schizophrenic patients. Cognition, 65, 71–86.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Daprati, E., Wriessnegger, S., & Lacquaniti, F. (2007). Kinematic cues and recognition of self-generated actions. Experimental Brain Research, 177(1), 31–44.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Della Sala, S. (2005). The anarchic hand. The Psychologist, 18(10), 606–609.

    Google Scholar 

  • Falvey, K. (2000). Knowledge in Intention. Philosophical Studies, 99, 21–44.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Farrer, C., Franck, N., Georgieff, N., Frith, C. D., Decety, J., & Jeannerod, M. (2003). Modulating the experience of agency: A positron emission tomography study. Neuroimage, 18(2), 324–333.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Farrer, C., Frey, S. H., Van Horn, J. D., Tunik, E., Turk, D., Inati, S., et al. (2008). The angular gyrus computes action awareness representations. Cerebral Cortex, 18(2), 254–261.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fourneret, P., & Jeannerod, M. (1998). Limited conscious monitoring of motor performance in normal subjects. Neuropsychologia, 36(11), 1133–1140.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frith, C. D., & Done, D. J. (1988). Towards a neuropsychology of schizophrenia. The British Journal of Psychiatry, 153(4), 437–443.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frith, C., & Johnstone, E. (2003). Schizophrenia. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Friston, K. (2011). What is optimal about motor control? Neuron, 72(3), 488–498.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2000). Philosophical conceptions of the self: Implications for cognitive science. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 4(1), 14–21.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2012). Multiple aspects in the sense of agency. New Ideas in Psychology, 30(1), 15–31.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grünbaum, T. (2011). Perception and non-inferential knowledge of action. Philosophical Explorations, 14(2), 153–167.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haggard, P., & Johnson, H. (2003). Experiences of voluntary action. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 10(9–10), 72–84.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haggard, P., & Chambon, V. (2012). Sense of agency. Current Biology, 22(10), R390–R392.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haggard, P., & Tsakiris, M. (2009). The experience of agency feelings, judgments, and responsibility. Current Directions in Psychological Science, 18(4), 242–246.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hohwy, J. (2007). The sense of self in the phenomenology of agency and perception. Psyche, 13(1), 1–20.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hohwy, J., & Frith, C. (2004). Studies of the neural correlates of consciousness can do better, but are on the right track. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 11(1), 45–51.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jeannerod, M. (1997). The cognitive neuroscience of action. Oxford: Blackwell Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jeannerod, M. (2006). Motor cognition: What actions tell the self. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Jeannerod, M. (2009). The sense of agency and its disturbances in schizophrenia: A reappraisal. Experimental Brain Research, 192(3), 527–532.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jensen, M., Vagnoni, E., Overgaard, M., & Haggard, P. (2013). Experience of action depends on intention, not body movement: An experiment on memory for mens rea. Neuropsychologia, 55, 122–127.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kritikos, A., Breen, N., & Mattingly, J. B. (2005). Anarchic hand syndrome: Bimanual coordination and sensitivity to irrelevant information in unimanual reaches. Cognitive Brain Research, 24, 634–647.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kühn, S., Brass, M., & Haggard, P. (2013). Feeling in control: Neural correlates of experience of agency. Cortex, 49(7), 1935–1942.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Machery, E. (2013). In defence of reverse inference. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 65, 251–267.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Metcalfe, J., & Greene, M. J. (2007). Metacognition of agency. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 136(2), 184–199.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moore, J., & Haggard, P. (2008). Awareness of action: Inference and prediction. Consciousness and Cognition, 17(1), 136–144.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pacherie, E. (2001). Agency lost and found: A commentary on Spence. Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology, 8(2), 173–176.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pacherie, E. (2008). The phenomenology of action: A conceptual framework. Cognition, 107(1), 179–217.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Parnas, J. (1999). From predisposition to psychosis: Progression of symptoms in schizophrenia. Acta Psychiatrica Scandinavica, 99(s395), 20–29.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Parnas, J., Handest, P., Jansson, L., & Sæbye, D. (2005). Anomalous subjective experience among first-admitted schizophrenia spectrum patients: Empirical investigation. Psychopathology, 38(5), 259–267.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Phillips, I. B. (2011). Perception and iconic memory: What sperling doesn’t show. Mind & Language, 26(4), 381–411.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Prinz, J. (2007). All consciousness is perceptual. In B. McLaughlin & J. Cohen (Eds.), Contemporary debates in philosophy of mind (pp. 335–357). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ritterband-Rosenbaum, A., Christensen, M. S., Kliim-Due, M., Petersen, L. Z., Rasmussen, B., & Nielsen, J. B. (2011). Altered sense of Agency in children with spastic cerebral palsy. BMC Neurology, 11(1), 150.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sato, A. (2009). Both motor prediction and conceptual congruency between preview and action-effect contribute to explicit judgment of agency. Cognition, 110(1), 74–83.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sato, A., & Yasuda, A. (2005). Illusion of sense of self-agency: Discrepancy between the predicted and actual sensory consequences of actions modulates the sense of self-agency, but not the sense of self-ownership. Cognition, 94(3), 241–255.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sober, E. (1999). Testability. In Proceedings and addresses of the American Philosophical Association (Vol. 73( 2), pp. 47–76). Newark, DE: American Philosophical Association.

  • Sober, E. (2008). Evidence and evolution: The logic behind the science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Spence, S. A., Brooks, D. J., Hirsch, S. R., Liddle, P. F., Meehan, J., & Grasby, P. M. (1997). A PET study of voluntary movement in schizophrenic patients experiencing passivity phenomena (delusions of alien control). Brain, 120(11), 1997–2011.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sperling, G. (1960). The information available in brief visual presentations. Psychological monographs: General and applied, 74(11), 1–29.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stephens, G. L., & Graham, G. (2000). When self-consciousness breaks: Alien voices and inserted thoughts. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stirling, J. D., Hellewell, J. S., & Quraishi, N. (1998). Self-monitoring dysfunction and the schizophrenic symptoms of alien control. Psychological Medicine, 28(3), 675–683.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Synofzik, M., Vosgerau, G., & Newen, A. (2008). Beyond the comparator model: A multifactorial two-step account of agency. Consciousness and Cognition, 17(1), 219–239.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tsakiris, M., & Haggard, P. (2005). Experimenting with the acting self. Cognitive Neuropsychology, 22(3–4), 387–407.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tsakiris, M., Haggard, P., Franck, N., Mainy, N., & Sirigu, A. (2005). A specific role for efferent information in self-recognition. Cognition, 96(3), 215–231.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van Den Bos, E., & Jeannerod, M. (2002). Sense of body and sense of action both contribute to self-recognition. Cognition, 85(2), 177–187.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vinding, M. C., Pedersen, M. N., & Overgaard, M. (2013). Unravelling intention: Distal intentions increase the subjective sense of agency. Consciousness and Cognition, 22(3), 810–815.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wegner, D. M. (2002). The illusion of conscious will. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wegner, D. M. (2004). Précis of the illusion of conscious will. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 27(5), 649–659.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wegner, D., & Wheatley, T. (1999). Apparent mental causation: Sources of the experience of will. American Psychologist, 54(7), 480–492.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wegner, D. M., Sparrow, B., & Winerman, L. (2004). Vicarious agency: Experiencing control over the movements of others. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 86(6), 838–848.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wenke, D., Fleming, S. M., & Haggard, P. (2010). Subliminal priming of actions influences sense of control over effects of action. Cognition, 115(1), 26.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wong, H. Y. (2012). A measure of my agency? Consciousness and Cognition, 21, 48–51.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I am grateful to Adrian Alsmith, Glenn Carruthers, Mark Schram Christensen, Ophelia Deroy, Frederique de Vignemont, Mads Jensen, John Michael, Krisztina Orban, Barry Smith, Mikkel C. Vinding, Martin Voss, Hong Yu Wong, and a number of anonymous reviewers for their helpful comments to earlier versions of the manuscript. The material has been presented at workshops and conferences in Aarhus, Antwerp, Copenhagen, Granada, London, and Tübingen, and I have received many helpful comments and suggestions. Research for this paper was funded by a grant from the Danish Research Council, FKK, project “Phenomenal Consciousness and Cognitive Motor Control”.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Thor Grünbaum.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Grünbaum, T. The feeling of agency hypothesis: a critique. Synthese 192, 3313–3337 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-015-0704-6

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-015-0704-6

Keywords

Navigation