Skip to main content
Log in

Laws of nature and the reality of the wave function

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In this paper I review three different positions on the wave function, namely: nomological realism, dispositionalism, and configuration space realism by regarding as essential their capacity to account for the world of our experience. I conclude that the first two positions are committed to regard the wave function as an abstract entity. The third position will be shown to be a merely speculative attempt to derive a primitive ontology from a reified mathematical space. Without entering any discussion about nominalism, I conclude that the elimination of abstract entities from one’s ontology commits one to instrumentalism about the wave function, a position that therefore is not as unmotivated as it has seemed to be to many philosophers.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Of course, this neglect is compatible with a natural ontological attitude towards endorsing the existence of elementary particles (Fine 1984).

  2. Born’s original attitude towards his own rule explicitly mentioned probability of measurement outcomes, a claim that in turn depended on Bohr’s view that in quantum physics measurement is a primitive and fundamental notion. See Cushing (1994).

  3. For an assessment of these latter elements, see Dorato (2013). For a general exposition of Rovelli’s philosophy of quantum theory, see Laudisa and Rovelli (2013).

  4. While these authors may be interpreted as being neutral with respect to the question whether laws are its or bits (to use Callender’s (2014) felicitous expression), I will argue that in their texts they seem to defend the former option.

  5. An informative case-study vis à vis these options is in Belot (2012). Many-worlds realism about \(\varPsi \) will be discussed within the view of configuration space realism (Vaidman 2012).

  6. For an account of “abstract”, see next page.

  7. This dilemma was presented already in Dorato and Laudisa (2014).

  8. This aim involves the commitment both to the claim that well-confirmed physical theories are at least approximately true given the evidence (the epistemological claim) and to the claim that they purport to describe a mind-independent, non-directly observable world (the metaphysical claim). These claims are obviously related.

  9. For an early defense of piecemeal realism, see Miller (1987).

  10. It could be objected that in the absence of a Bohmian theory of quantum gravity, it is meaningless to attribute a wave function to the universe. This objection however, would be unfair, since here we are trying to fathom the metaphysical consequences of non-relativistic Bohmian mechanics, so that the arena that we need to presuppose to formulate the theory is Newtonian spacetime (or for relativistic extensions, Minkowski spacetime with the addition of a privileged foliation).

  11. The word in square parentheses is my addition.

  12. Note once again that the disjunctive definition of abstract given in the previous section allows for such a possibility.

  13. Also Callender (2014) raises this question for the relation between Bohmian particles and the guiding-law, when the latter is regarded as an “it” rather than a “bit”.

  14. This reading was applied by Dorato and Esfeld (2010) to GRW-type theories.

  15. See Dorato (2005).

  16. How this reference should be understood will be discussed below.

  17. As is well known, in Bohmian mechanics the particles cannot back-react on the field.

  18. Recall that the hypothesis that \(\varPsi \) is causally active has been rejected before.

  19. Recall that the view that the universal wave function lives in a 3\(N\) dimensional, physical configuration space (Albert 1996) will be discussed in a later section.

  20. This view is explored but not fully endorsed by Norsen (2010).

  21. For the following objections, see Dorato and Esfeld (2015) and Dorato and Laudisa (2014).

  22. I owe this objection to Albert Solé.

  23. For a sketch of argument against an identification of the two modal views of laws, which pertains to the explanatory power of dispositionalism, see Dorato and Esfeld (2015).

  24. Darby (2012) also defends a global approach to supervenience, which turns the Humean mosaic into a lawlike feature of the universe, that is, a property of the universe as such.

  25. See also Wallace (2013b, pp. 48–52).

References

  • Albert, D. Z. (1996). Elementary quantum metaphysics. In J. T. Cushing, A. Fine, & S. Goldstein (Eds.), Bohmian mechanics and quantum theory: An appraisal (pp. 277–284). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Albert, D. Z. (2013). Wave function realism. In A. Ney & D. Albert (Eds.), The wave function (pp. 52–57). Cambridge: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Allori, V. (2013). Primitive ontology and the structure of fundamental physical theories. In A. Ney & D. Albert (Eds.), The wave function (pp. 58–75). Cambridge: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Allori, V., Goldstein, S., Tumulka, R., & Zanghì, N. (2008). On the common structure of Bohmian mechanics and the Ghirardi–Rimini–Weber theory. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 59, 353–389.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bell, J. S. (1997). Speakable and unspeakable in quantum mechanics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Belot, G. (2012). Quantum states for primitive ontologists. A case study. European Journal for Philosophy of Science, 2, 67–83.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Butterfield, J., & Isham, C. (1999). The emergence of time in quantum gravity. In J. Butterfield (Ed.), The arguments of time (pp. 111–168). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Callender, C. (2014). One world, one beable, (draft).

  • Carroll, J. (1994). Laws of nature. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright, N. (1983). How the laws of physics lie. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Chakravarrty, A. (2007). A metaphysics for scientific realism: Knowing the unobservable. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cushing, J. (1994). Quantum mechanics. Historical contingency and the Copenhagen hegemony. Chicago: Chicago University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Darby, G. (2012). Relational holism and Humean supervenience. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 63(4), 773–788.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. (1991). Real patterns. Journal of Philosophy, 88, 27–51.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dürr, D., Goldstein, S., & Zanghì, N. (1997). Bohmian mechanics and the meaning of the wave function. In R. S. Cohen, M. Horne, & J. Stachel (Eds.), Experimental metaphysics: Quantum mechanical studies for Abner Shimony; Boston studies in the philosophy of science 193 (pp. 25–38). Boston: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dorato, M. (2005). The software of the universe. An introduction to the history and philosophy of laws of nature. Aldershot: Asgate Publishing Limited.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dorato, M. (2007). Dispositions, relational properties and the quantum world. In M. Kistler & B. Gnassonou (Eds.), Dispositions and causal powers (pp. 249–270). Farnham: Ashgate.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dorato, M., & Esfeld, M. (2010). GRW as an ontology of dispositions. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 41(1), 41–49.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dorato, & Laudisa, (2014). Realism and instrumentalism about the wave function. How should we choose? In Gao Shan (Ed.), Protective measurements and quantum reality: Toward a new understanding of quantum mechanics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. (pp. to be added).

    Google Scholar 

  • Dorato, M. (2013). Rovelli’s relational quantum mechanics, monism and quantum becoming. http://arxiv.org/abs/1309.0132

  • Dorato, M., & Esfeld, M. (2015). The metaphysics of laws: Dispositionalism versus primitivism. In C. Wutrich & T. Bigaj (Eds.), Poznan studies in the philosophy of science. Oxford: EOLSS.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dürr, et al. (1992). Quantum equilibrium and the origin of the origin of absolute uncertainty. Journal of Statistical Physics, 67, 843–907.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Esfeld, M., Lazarovici, D., Hubert, M., & Dürr, D. (2013). The ontology of Bohmian mechanics. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 64. doi:10.1093/bjps/axt019. http://philsci-archive.pitt.edu/9381/

  • Esfeld M., Lazarovici D., Lam V., & Hubert M. (2015). The physics and metaphysics of primitive stuff. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science. doi:10.1093/bjps/axt053

  • Ellis, B. (2001). Scientific essentialism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldstein, S., & Zanghì, N. (2013). Reality and the role of the wave function in quantum theory. In A. Ney & D. Albert (Eds.), The wave function (pp. 96–109). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fine, A. (1984). The natural ontological attitude. In J. Leplin (Ed.), Scientific realism (pp. 83–107). Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fine, A. (1991). Piecemeal realism. Philosophical Studies, 61, 79–96.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • French, S. (2013). Whither wave function realism? In A. Ney & D. Albert (Eds.), The wave function (pp. 76–90). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Giere, R. (1988). Explaining science., A cognitive approach Chicago: Chicago University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hacking, I. (1983). Representing and intervening. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Harré, R., & Madden, E. (1975). Causal powers: A theory of natural necessity. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Healey, R. (2013). Physical composition. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 44, 48–62.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kiefer, Claus. (2007). Quantum gravity (2nd ed.). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ladyman, J. (2014). Structural realism. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2014 Edition) (forthcoming). URL: http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2014/entries/structural-realism/

  • Ladyman, J., Ross, D., Spurrett, D., & Collier, J. (2007). Every thing must go: Metaphysics naturalized. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lam, V., & Esfeld, M. (2013). A dilemma for the emergence of spacetime in canonical quantum gravity. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 44, 286–293.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Laudisa, F., & Rovelli, C. (2013). Relational quantum mechanics. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2013 Edition). URL: http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2013/entries/qm-relational/

  • Lange, M. (2002). An introduction to the philosophy of physics. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Loewer, B. (1996). Humean supervenience. Philosophical Topics, 24, 101–127.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maudlin, T. (2007). The metaphysics within physics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Maudlin, T. (2013). The nature of the quantum state. In A. Ney & D. Albert (Eds.), The wave function (pp. 126–154). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • McMullin, E. (1984). A case for scientific realism. In J. Leplin (Ed.), Scientific realism (pp. 8–40). Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McMullin, E. (1991). Comment: Selective antirealism. Philosophical Studies, 61, 97–108.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Miller, R. W. (1987). Fact and method. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Monton, B. (2006). Quantum mechanics and 3-N dimensional space. Philosophy of Science, 75(5), 778–789.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morgan, M., & Morrison, M. (Eds.). (1999). Models as mediators. Perspectives on natural and social sciences. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mumford, S. (2004). Laws in nature. London: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mumford, S., & Anjum, L. (2011). Getting causes from powers. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ney, A. (2013). Ontological reduction and the wave function ontology. In A. Ney & D. Albert (Eds.), The wave function (pp. 168–183). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Ney, A., & Albert, D. (Eds.). (2013). The wave function. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Norsen, T. (2010). The theory of exclusively local beables. Foundations of Physics, 40, 1858–1884.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • North, J. (2013). The structure of a quantum world. In A. Ney & D. Albert (Eds.), The wave function (pp. 184–202). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Psillos, S. (2006). Review symposium, looking for laws. Metascience, 15, 452–464.

    Google Scholar 

  • Psillos, S. (2011). Living with the abstract. Synthese, 180(1), 3–17.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pusey, M., Barrett, J., & Rudolph, T. (2012). On the reality of the quantum state. Nature Physics, 8, 475–478.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rosen, G. (2014). Abstract objects. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2014 Edition). URL: http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2014/entries/abstract-objects/

  • Rovelli, C. (1996). Relational quantum mechanics. International Journal of Theoretical Physics, 35, 1637.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schlosshauer, M., & Fine, A. (2012). Implications of the Pusey–Barrett–Rudolph quantum No–Go theorem. Physical Review Letters, 108, 260404.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Suárez, M. (2004). On quantum propensities: Two arguments revisited. Erkenntnis, 61, 1–16.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Suárez, M. (2007). Quantum propensities. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 38B, 418–438.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vaidman, L. (2012). Probability in the Many-Worlds Interpretation of quantum mechanics. In Y. Ben-Menahem & H. Hemmo (Eds.), Probability in physics (pp. 299–311)., The frontiers collection XII New York: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Van Fraassen, B. (2002). The empirical stance. London: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Fraassen, (2006). Structure: Its shadow and substance. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 57, 275–307.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wallace, D. (2004). Protecting cognitive science from quantum theory. Behavioral and Brain science, 27, 636–637.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wallace, D. (2013a). A prolegomenon to the ontology of the Everett interpretation. In A. Ney & D. Albert (Eds.), The wave function. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Wallace, D. (2013b). The emergent multiverse. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Download references

Acknowledgments

Thanks to Albert Solé and to two other anonymous referee for their comments and criticism.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Mauro Dorato.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Dorato, M. Laws of nature and the reality of the wave function. Synthese 192, 3179–3201 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-015-0696-2

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-015-0696-2

Keywords

Navigation