Skip to main content
Log in

Reflecting on finite additivity

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

An infinite lottery experiment seems to indicate that Bayesian conditionalization may be inconsistent when the prior credence function is finitely additive because, in that experiment, it conflicts with the principle of reflection. I will show that any other form of updating credences would produce the same conflict, and, furthermore, that the conflict is not between conditionalization and reflection but, instead, between finite additivity and reflection. A correct treatment of the infinite lottery experiment requires a careful treatment of finite additivity. I will show that the results of the experiment, paradoxical though they may be, are not inconsistent, but that they conflict with one particular version of reflection (special reflection). I will reject that version and I will propose a slight modification of a different version of reflection (general reflection) such that the modified version does maintain the mutual consistency of finite additivity, reflection and conditionalization. As a result, I will strengthen the case for finite additivity by showing that Bayesian conditionalization is fully consistent with it.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. I will refer to subjective probabilities as credences.

  2. I will often simply write ‘A’ for ‘\(\hbox {A}\otimes {\varvec{{\mathcal {N}}}}\)’ and, analogously, ‘n’ for ‘\(\{\hbox {A,B}\}\otimes {\hbox {n}}\)’, whenever there is no possibility of confusion.

  3. If \({\varvec{{\mathcal {M}}}}\) is a member of the partition of \({\varvec{{\mathcal {N}}}}, \{\hbox {A,B}\}\bigotimes {\varvec{{\mathcal {M}}}}\) is the corresponding member of the partition of \({\varvec{{\mathcal {S}}}}\). It is the union of sets {(A,n), (B,n)} with n such that q(A) equals r.

  4. “SR” is short for “Special Reflection”, van Fraassen’s name for this principle.

  5. I thank an anonymous reviewer for pointing out the necessity of considering all three principles. That such a conflict exists was already pointed out by Arntzenius et al. (2004) but these authors did not blame conditionalization.

  6. In this and subsequent sums, “j” indicates the summation variable.

  7. Or, more accurately, whether the collection of subsets of N defined by these indicator functions forms an algebra.

  8. The weaker principle that the prior credence in A equals the expectation value, with respect to the prior credence function, of the posterior credence in A is still valid.

  9. van Fraassen (1995) gives a proof of SR assuming GRP, and I will return to that proof later in this section.

  10. f is called q by van Fraassen.

References

  • Arntzenius, F., Elga, A., & Hawthorne, J. (2004). Bayesianism, infinite decisions, and binding. Mind, 113, 251–283.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Briggs, R. (2009). Distorted reflection. Philosophical Reviews, 118, 59–85.

    Google Scholar 

  • De Finetti, B. (1972). Probability, induction and statistics. London: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Howson, C. (2014). Finite additivity, another lottery paradox and conditionalisation. Synthese, 191, 989–1012.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schurz, G., & Leitgeb, H. (2008). Finitistic and frequentist approximation of probability measures with or without \(\upsigma \)-additivity. Studia Logica, 89, 257–283.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van Fraassen, B. C. (1984). Belief and the will. The Journal of Philosophy, LXXXI, 235–256.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Fraassen, B. C. (1995). Belief and the problem of Ulysses and the Sirens. Philosophical Studies, 77, 7–37.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weisberg, J. (2007). Conditionalization reflection and self-knowledge. Philosophical Studies, 135, 179–197.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Leendert Huisman.

Appendix

Appendix

Define \(\hbox {p}_\mathrm{m}\hbox {(A)} = \hbox {p}_\mathrm{m}\hbox {(B)} = 0.5, \hbox {p}_\mathrm{m}(\hbox {n}{\vert }\hbox {A}) = \hbox {p}_\mathrm{m}(\hbox {n}{\vert }\hbox {B}) = 0\) for \(\hbox {n}>\hbox {m}\), while, for \(\hbox {n}\le \hbox {m} , \hbox {p}_\mathrm{m}(\hbox {n}{\vert }\hbox {A}) = (\hbox {n}^{-1} + \hbox {n}^{-2}) / \hbox {C}_\mathrm{m}\) and \(\hbox {p}_\mathrm{m}(\hbox {n}\vert \hbox {B}) = (\hbox {n}^{-1} - \hbox {n}^{-2}) / \hbox {D}_\mathrm{m}\). \(\hbox {C}_\mathrm{m}\) and \(\hbox {D}_\mathrm{m}\) are normalization constants equal to ln(m) \(+\) terms of order 1. We are interested in the limit of m going to infinity.

First, we find that lim \(\hbox {p}_\mathrm{m}(\hbox {A}{\vert }\hbox {n}) = (1 + \hbox {n}^{-1})/2 > 0.5\). Second, let \({\varvec{{{\mathcal {E}}}}}\) be some subset of \({\varvec{{\mathcal {N}}}}\). In that case, \(\hbox {p}_\mathrm{m}(\hbox {A}{\vert }{\varvec{{{\mathcal {E}}}}}) = \hbox {p}_\mathrm{m}({\varvec{{{\mathcal {E}}}}}{\vert }\hbox {A}) / (\hbox {p}_\mathrm{m}({\varvec{{{\mathcal {E}}}}}{\vert }\hbox {A}) + \hbox {p}_\mathrm{m}({\varvec{{{\mathcal {E}}}}}{\vert }\hbox {B})) = 1 / (1 + \hbox {p}_\mathrm{m}({\varvec{{{\mathcal {E}}}}}{\vert }\hbox {B})/\hbox {p}_\mathrm{m}({\varvec{{{\mathcal {E}}}}}{\vert }\hbox {A}))\). The limit of \(\hbox {C}_\mathrm{m} / \hbox {D}_\mathrm{m}\) equals 1, so the limit of \(\hbox {p}_\mathrm{m}({\varvec{{{\mathcal {E}}}}}{\vert }\hbox {B})/\hbox {p}_\mathrm{m}({\varvec{{{\mathcal {E}}}}}{\vert }\hbox {A})\) equals

$$\begin{aligned} \lim \frac{C_m }{D_m }\frac{\sum {j^{-1}-j^{-2}} }{\sum {j^{-1}+j^{-2}} }=1-2\;\;\;\lim \frac{\sum {j^{-2}} }{\sum {j^{-1}-j^{-2}} }, \end{aligned}$$

in which the sums are taken over all j not exceeding m and in \({\varvec{{{\mathcal {E}}}}}\). This limit is less than or equal to 1 and, consequently, \(\hbox {p}_\mathrm{m}(\hbox {A}{\vert }{\varvec{{{\mathcal {E}}}}}) \ge 0.5\). Equality obtains if the complement of \({\varvec{{{\mathcal {E}}}}}\) with respect to \({\varvec{{\mathcal {N}}}}\) is finite.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Huisman, L. Reflecting on finite additivity. Synthese 192, 1785–1797 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-014-0652-6

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-014-0652-6

Keywords

Navigation