Skip to main content
Log in

Conventionalism, consistency, and consistency sentences

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Conventionalism about mathematics claims that mathematical truths are true by linguistic convention. This is often spelled out by appealing to facts concerning rules of inference and formal systems, but this leads to a problem: since the incompleteness theorems we’ve known that syntactic notions can be expressed using arithmetical sentences. There is serious prima facie tension here: how can mathematics be a matter of convention and syntax a matter of fact given the arithmetization of syntax? This challenge has been pressed in the literature by Hilary Putnam and Peter Koellner. In this paper I (i) sketch a conventionalist theory of mathematics, (ii) show that this conventionalist theory can meet the challenge just raised (this is done by considering how arithmetical coding works in non-standard models of arithmetic), and (iii) clarify the type of mathematical pluralism endorsed by the conventionalist by introducing the notion of a semantic counterpart. The paper’s aim is an improved understanding of conventionalism, pluralism, and the relationship between them.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See Carnap (1934) and (1939).

  2. Something like logical inferentialism was first endorsed in Carnap (1934) and Wittgenstein (1974).

  3. The focus on introduction and elimination rules in natural deduction systems derives from the work of Gentzen (1935). It should be noted that standard single conclusion natural deduction treatments of the logical constants fail to determine truth-functional meanings for most of the connectives; this was first noticed and patched in Carnap (1943).

  4. See Prior (1960).

  5. I defend unrestricted inferentialism from the challenge of tonk in my “Talking with Tonkers”, currently under review.

  6. Unless otherwise indicated, when I say “Peano Arithmetic” I’ll always be talking about the first-order version of the Peano Axioms.

  7. Dedekind (1888) and Peano (1889).

  8. These axioms are, \((i)\, \forall x(x+0=x), (ii)\, \forall x\forall y(x+s(y)=s(a+b)), (iii)\, \forall y(y\times 0=0)\), and \((iv)\, \forall y\forall z(y\times s(z)=y\times z+y)\). They could each be added in rule form to be more in keeping with inferentialism about arithmetic.

  9. Adding these rules to a standard system of first-order logic results in a non-conservative extension, i.e., we can prove sentences without any arithmetical vocabulary using the Peano rules when these sentences are not provable using only the non-arithmetical rules. To see this, simply note that every counting sentence (there are at least \(n\) things): (i) can be formulated using only standard logical vocabulary, (ii) is not a logical theorem, and (iii) can be proved using the Peano rules. This means that restricting the \(\mathbf {MRC}\) so as to apply only to rules that conservatively extend our base theory blocks the extension of inferentialism from logic to mathematics.

  10. Some historical conventionalists have been ontological realists, e.g., Carnap (1950). It is important to note that my term “ontological realist” has nothing to do with any claims of substantive philosophical ontology such as one finds in Sider (2009) under the same name.

  11. See Quine (1948).

  12. See Quine (1936) and the discussion of what I call “the master argument against conventinalism” in my Warren (2014a).

  13. There are other objections specifically aimed at mathematical conventionalism that I won’t directly address here, e.g., see Gödel (1953/1959) and Pollock (1967). Both logical and mathematical conventionalism are developed and defended at length in my forthcoming book, Syntactic Shadows: A Linguistic Theory of Logic and Mathematics.

  14. Arithmetization was introduced in Gödel (1931).

  15. Actually, care must be taken here: there are some seemingly natural ways of expressing the consistency of \(PA\) that are provable in \(PA\). Hilbert and Bernays (1939) gave three conditions on the provability predicate used in formulating the consistency sentence that, if satisfied, suffice for Gödel’s second theorem to hold for the associated consistency sentence. The conditions were later given in a more perspicuous form by Löb (1955): for theory \(T\), let \(\square \phi =\exists xPRF_{T}(x,y)\) (see below for an explanation of this relation) then the conditions are: \((i)\) if \(T\vdash \phi \) then \(T\vdash \square \phi \); \((ii)\, T\vdash \square (\phi \rightarrow \psi )\rightarrow (\square \phi \rightarrow \square \psi )\); \((iii)\, T\vdash \square \phi \rightarrow \square \square \phi \).

  16. In Sect. 1 I didn’t offer a sufficient condition for mathematical truth, but however the conventionalist fleshes out the story of mathematical truth, truth will have to be owed to convention in some sense.

  17. I am neglecting to use corners when employing quasi-quotation because I will later use corners for Gödel numbers.

  18. Page 501 of Putnam (1994)’s reprint of Putnam (1979).

  19. Page 84 in Koellner (2009).

  20. This might naturally be combined with the Putnam characterization since it seems like a stipulation or practice can be neither true nor false.

  21. Ayer (1936) endorsed the non-cognitivist version of conventionalism, but Ayer (1946) moves back to a cognitivist version.

  22. I am focusing on \(PA\) both for definiteness and because it is the case relevant to the theory of arithmetic given above, but of course we can apply arithmetization to theories other than \(PA\).

  23. Throughout I’ll be assuming that “\(PRF_{PA}(x,y)\)” is the standard or canonical provability relation required for proofs of the second incompleteness theorem; this is necessary because there are other provability relations that won’t allow us to form consistency sentences for which the second incompleteness theorem holds see Feferman (1960). For helpful discussion of this, see Smith (2013), Sects. 36.1 and 36.2.

  24. I have abbreviated “\(s(\hat{0})\)” as “\(\hat{1}\)”, I will continue to do this without comment below.

  25. Recall once again the warning about provable “consistency” sentences.

  26. I’m extrapolating a bit here, but I think Koellner would endorse this claim.

  27. As noted above, it isn’t literally correct to claim that our arithmetical language’s rules include nothing beyond the Peano Rules. In addition to needing to add rules for addition and multiplication, our arithmetical practice includes various bridge laws that allow us to apply arithmetic to the world. I’ll be ignoring these complications here.

  28. N.B., when a set of sentences appears on the left of the semantic turnstile (“\(\models \)”) the claim should be read as saying that any model in which the set of sentences on the left are all true is a model in which the sentence on the right is also true, i.e., the sentence on the right is a logical consequence of the set of sentences on the left.

  29. In fact, because of the way these consistency sentences are constructed, if a theory \(S\) extends a theory \(T\) then \(\vdash CON_{S}\rightarrow CON_{T}\), so contrapose for our result.

  30. This observation is related to an interpretation of some of Wittgenstein’s remarks on Gödel’s theorems offered in Floyd and Putnam (2000).

  31. This shows that the provability predicate for \(PA\) so formed is not primitive recursive, despite its being expressed by a \(\Sigma _{1}^{0}\)-formula.

  32. The type of logical pluralism entailed by conventionalism is different than the logical pluralism of Beall and Restall (2006) which concerns there being indeterminacy within our language about what counts as a legitimate means of making precise the “truth-preservation in all cases” core of our concept of consequence.

  33. See Lewis (1968); in a full treatment, I would actually slightly generalize the notion of counterpart used in theories like Lewis’s so as to allow even greater flexibility in the intra-language case.

  34. \(ZFC\) is Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory with the axiom of choice; this is the standard axiomatic set theory familiar from textbook presentations such as Kunen (1980); \(NF\) set theory is the non-standard set theory presented in Quine (1937).

  35. Of course, in some cases, we may resolve to split the relevant semantic role in two and switch back and forth between the “competing” theories whenever it suits us.

  36. For a proof of this latter claim in addition to some discussion of equivalence claims in metaphysics, see the appendix to my Warren (2014b).

  37. Here I’m just defining an “arithmetical” theory as one that can do enough arithmetic for Gödel’s results to hold. Although Gödel’s original proof was applied to the language of Principia Mathematica, subsequent work has shown that very weak arithmetical theories suffice for this.

  38. In actual historical fact, Carnap’s base theory here is something like the weak theory Primitive Recursive Arithmetic.

  39. In fact, this holds even for adding the \(\omega \)-rule to a weak arithmetical theory like Robinson Arithmetic.

  40. Carnap also has another procedure which, from the modern point of view, can be seen as a convoluted variant of Tarski’s theory of truth.

  41. I address this issue in work under review, especially my “The Determinacy of Arithmetic: The Puzzle and Its Solution”, where the problem is addressed in a way congenial to conventionalists but without assuming conventionalism.

  42. Thanks to an audience at NYU and two referees.

References

  • Ayer, A. J. (1936). Truth by convention: A symposium. Analysis, 4(2/3), 17–22.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ayer, A. J. (1946). Language, truth and logic (2nd ed.). London: Victor Gollancz Ltd.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beall, J. C., & Restall, G. (2006). Logical pluralism. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, R. (1934). The logical syntax of language. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, R. (1939). Foundations of logic and mathematics. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, R. (1943). Formalization of logic. London: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, R. (1950). Empiricism, semantics, and ontology. Revue Internaitonale de Philosophie, 4, 20–40.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dedekind, R. (1888). Was sind und was sollen die Zahlen?. Braunschweig: Sohn.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feferman, S. (1960). Arithmetization of metamathematics in a general setting. Fundamenta Mathematicae, 49, 35–92.

    Google Scholar 

  • Floyd, J., & Putnam, H. (2000). A note on Wittgenstein’s “notorious paragraph” about the Gödel theorem. Journal of Philosophy, 97(11), 624–632.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gentzen, G. (1935). Untersuchungen über das logische Schließen. Mathematische Zeitschrift, 39, 176–210.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gödel, K. (1931). On Formally Undecidable Propositions of Principia Mathematica and Related Systems I. Monatshefte für Mathematik und Physik, 38, 173–198.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gödel, K. (1953/1959). Is mathematics syntax of language? In: Collected works III: Unpublished essays and lectures. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Hilbert, D., & Bernays, P. (1939). Grundlagen der Mathmatik (Vol. II). Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Koellner, P. (2009). Truth in mathematics: The question of pluralism. In: New waves in philosophy of mathematics. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.

  • Kunen, K. (1980). Set theory: An introduction to independence proofs. Amsterdam: Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1968). Counterpart theory and quantified modal logic. Journal of Philosophy, 65, 113–126.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Löb, M. H. (1955). Solution of a problem of Leon Henkin. Journal of Symbolic Logic, 20, 115–118.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peano, G. (1889). Arithmetices principia, nova methodo exposita. reprinted in English translation in van Heijenoort (1967).

  • Pollock, J. (1967). Mathematical proof. American Philosophical Quarterly, 4, 238–244.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prior, A. N. (1960). The runabout inference-ticket. Analysis, 21, 2.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1979). Philosophy of mathematics: Why nothing works. In: Words and life. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

  • Putnam, H. (1994). Words and life. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. V. O. (1936). Truth by convention. In Philosophical essays for Alfred North Whitehead. New York: Longmans, Green & Company.

  • Quine, W. V. O. (1937). New foundations for mathematical logic. American Mathematical Monthly, 44, 70–80.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. V. O. (1948). On what there is. Revue of Metaphysics, 2, 21–38.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sider, T. (2009). Ontological realism. In D. Chalmers, D. Manley, & R. Wasserman (Eds.), Metametaphysics. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, P. (2013). An introduction to Gödel’s theorems (2nd ed.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1974). Philosophical grammar. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Warren, J. (2014a). The possibility of truth by convention. The Philosophical Quarterly. doi:10.1093/pq/pqu051

  • Warren, J. (2014b). Quantifier variance and the collapse argument. The Philosophical Quarterly. doi:10.1093/pq/pqu080.

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Jared Warren.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Warren, J. Conventionalism, consistency, and consistency sentences. Synthese 192, 1351–1371 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-014-0626-8

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-014-0626-8

Keywords

Navigation