Skip to main content
Log in

How dimensional analysis can explain

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Dimensional analysis can offer us explanations by allowing us to answer What-if–things-had-been-different? questions rather than in virtue of, say, unifying diverse phenomena, important as that is. Additionally, it is argued that dimensional analysis is a form of modelling as it involves several of the aspects crucial in modelling, such as misrepresenting aspects of a target system. By highlighting the continuities dimensional analysis has with forms of modelling we are able to describe more precisely what makes dimensional analysis explanatory and understand otherwise puzzling aspects of dimensional reasoning, such as introducing fictitious dimensions and excluding dimensionally relevant information to characterise some systems. Finally, thinking of dimensional arguments as a form of modelling allows an explication of the role abstraction and multiple realisability; not as compatibility with other possible worlds but as compatibility with different fictional descriptions of our own world.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Stellar structure is the internal structure of stars: the composition, size, pressure gradients, and energy transport mechanisms, and how these interact to produce the properties of the star.

  2. Essentially we assume that \(\rho (\hbox {r}){/}\!<\rho >\) the density as a function of radius as a fraction of average density is independent of total mass.

  3. I am grateful to Marc Lange (private communication) for clarification of this point.

  4. Noether’s theorem is a classic example of finding independent theoretical justification for a symmetry constraint on laws. Consider a symmetry assumption that physics should be spatially translationally invariant. In other words, all things being equal, the laws of physics shouldn’t alter because we are in Leeds rather than London. Noether was able to show that conservation of linear momentum follows from translational symmetry, likewise temporal symmetry leads to the principle of conservation of energy and rotational symmetry leads to conservation of angular momentum. So when we say both Newton’s and Einstein’s laws adhere to conservation of energy and momentum, we are constraining them via a very basic symmetry assumption. Similarly dimensional explanations offer explanations by locating relational facts about the dimensional constraints inherent within a system.

References

  • Batterman, R. (2002). The devil in the details. Asymptotic reasoning in explanation, reduction, and emergence. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bokulich, A. (2008). Reexamining the quantum-classical relation: Beyond reductionism and pluralism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Butterfield, J., & Bouatta, N. (2011). Emergence and reduction combined in phase transitions. http://philsci-archive.pitt.edu/id/eprint/8554.

  • Chandrasekhar, S. (1958). An introduction to the study of stellar structure. New York: Dover. [1939].

    Google Scholar 

  • Frigg, R. (2010). Models and fiction. Synthese, 172, 251–268.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Giere, R. N. (2006). Scientific perspectivism. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hughes, R. I. G. (2010). The theoretical practices of physics: Philosophical essays. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Huntley, H. E. (1967). Dimensional analysis. New York: Dover.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. (1989). Explanatory unification and the causal structure of the world. In Kitcher & Salmon (Eds.), Scientific explanation. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Knuuttila, T., & Boon, M. (2011). How do models give us knowledge? The case of Carnot’s ideal heat engine. European Journal of Philosophy of Science, 1, 309–334.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lange, M. (2009). Dimensional explanations. Nous, 43(4), 742–775.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morrison, M. (2000). Unifying scientific theories: Physical concepts and mathematical structures. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Pexton, M. (2013). Non-causal explanation, Ph.D. Thesis University of Leeds.

  • Rayleigh, L. (1915). The principle of similitude. Nature, 95, 66–68.

    Google Scholar 

  • Riabouchinsky, D. (1915). The principle of similitude. Nature, 95, 591.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weslake, B. (2010). Explanatory depth. Philosophy of Science, 77(2), 273–294.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, J. (2003). Making things happen: A theory of causal explanation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I would like to thank Juha Saatsi without who’s supervision this work would have not been possible, and Marc Lange for helpful comments, as well as the comments of the editors and referees. This work was supported by the Arts and Humanities Research Council and Templeton Foundation.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Mark Pexton.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Pexton, M. How dimensional analysis can explain. Synthese 191, 2333–2351 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-014-0401-x

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-014-0401-x

Keywords

Navigation