Skip to main content
Log in

How agency can solve interventionism’s problem of circularity

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Woodward’s interventionist theory of causation is beset by a problem of circularity: the analysis of causes is in terms of interventions, and the analysis of interventions is in terms of causes. This is not in itself an argument against the correctness of the analysis. But by requiring us to have causal knowledge prior to making any judgements about causation, Woodward’s theory does make it mysterious how we can ever start acquiring causal knowledge. We present a solution to this problem by showing how the interventionist notion of causation can be rationally generated from a more primitive agency notion of causation. The agency notion is easily and non-circularly applicable, but fails when we attempt to capture causal relations between non-actions. We show that the interventionist notion of causation serves as an appropriate generalisation of the agency notion. Furthermore, the causal judgements based on the latter generally remain true when rephrased in terms of the former, which allows one to use the causal knowledge gained by applying the agency notion as a basis for applying Woodward’s interventionist theory. We then present an overview of relevant empirical evidence from developmental psychology which shows that our proposed rational reconstruction lines up neatly with the actual development of causal reasoning in children. This gives additional plausibility to our proposal. The article thus provides a solution to one of the main problems of interventionism while keeping Woodward’s analysis intact.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Throughout this paper, we will assume that analyses of the concept of causation can be ranked as better and worse on pragmatic grounds, without the need for a theory-neutral set of intuitions underlying them. We also assume that it is possible to see intellectual progress from a worse to a better theory from a purely internal perspective, without the need for a further point of view that is neutral with respect to the two theories. A defence of these assumptions falls outside the scope of the current paper.

  2. We are not committing ourselves to Bayesianism here: other theories of confirmation would yield the same verdict.

  3. From an anthropological perspective, one can speculate that animism—the ascription of personhood to natural objects—is the temporary result of such a development, where causation has been placed outside of human actions, but has not yet lost its connection to action completely. We are not competent to develop this suggestion.

  4. The difference between perceiving correlations between external events (stage i) and understanding \(\hbox {causal}_{1}\) relations between another agent’s actions and their effects (stage ii) resembles the difference between classical and instrumental conditioning. In classical conditioning, the agent learns about a predictive relation between two events that are outside of her control, whereas in instrumental conditioning what is learned is a predictive relation between an action of the agent and its effect. Woodward (2007) argues that, from an interventionist perspective, instrumental learning has a ‘cause-like’ flavor. Although we agree that instrumental learning has this cause-like flavor, we think this is better explained using an agency perspective on causation.

References

  • Barr, R., Dowden, A., & Hayne, H. (1996). Developmental changes in deferred imitation by 6- to 24-month-old infants. Infant Behavior and Development, 19, 159–170.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baumgartner, M. (2009). Interdefining causation and intervention. Dialectica, 63, 175–194.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beebee, H., Hitchcock, C., & Menzies, P. (2009). The Oxford handbook of causation. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bonawitz, E., Ferranti, E., Saxe, R., Gopnik, A., Meltzoff, A. N., Woodward, J., et al. (2010). Just do it? Investigating the gap between prediction and action in toddlers’ causal inferences. Cognition, 115, 104–117.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright, N. (1994). Nature’s capacities and their measurement. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Collingwood, P. G. (1940). An essay on metaphysics. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • de Regt, H. (2004). Review of James Woodward, making things happen. Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews. http://ndpr.nd.edu/news/23818-making-things-happen-a-theory-of-causal-explanation/

  • Elsner, B., & Hommel, B. (2001). Effect anticipation and action control. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance, 27, 229–240.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallese, V., & Sinigaglia, C. (2011). What is so special about embodied simulation? Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 15(11), 512–519.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Georgieff, N., & Jeannerod, M. (1998). Beyond consciousness of external reality: A “Who” system for consciousness and action and self-consciousness. Consciousness & Cognition, 7, 465–487.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gergely, G., Bekkering, H., & Király, I. (2002). Rational imitation in preverbal infants. Nature, 415, 755.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Glymour, C. (2004). Critical notice of James Woodward, making things happen. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 55, 779–790.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hommel, B., & Elsner, B. (2009). Acquisition, representation, and control of action. In E. Morsella, J. A. Bargh, & P. M. Gollwitzer (Eds.), Oxford handbook of human action (pp. 371–398). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kovács, A., Teglas, E., & Endress, A. (2010). The social sense: Susceptibility to others’ beliefs in human infants and adults. Science, 330, 1830–1834.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leslie, A. M. (1995). A theory of agency. In D. Sperber, D. Premack, & A. J. Premack (Eds.), Causal cognition (pp. 121–141). Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leslie, A. M., & Keeble, S. (1987). Do six-month-old infants perceive causality? Cognition, 25, 265–288.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Meltzoff, A. N. (1988). Infant imitation after a 1-week delay: Long-term memory for novel acts and multiple stimuli. Developmental Psychology, 24, 470–476.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Meltzoff, A. N. (2004). Imitation and other minds: The “like me” hypothesis. In S. Hurley & N. Chater (Eds.), Perspectives on imitation: From neuroscience to social science (Vol. II, pp. 55–77). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Meltzoff, A. N. (2006). The “like me” framework for recognizing and becoming an intentional agent. Acta Psychologica, 124, 26–43.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Meltzoff, A. N., & Brooks, R. (2001). ‘Like me’ as a building block for understanding other minds: Bodily acts, attention, and intention. In B. F. Malle, L. J. Moses, & D. A. Baldwin (Eds.), Intentions and intentionality: Foundations of social cognition (pp. 171–191). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Meltzoff, A. N., & Moore, M. K. (1977). Imitation of facial and manual gestures by human neonates. Science, 198, 75–78.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Meltzoff, A. N., & Moore, M. K. (1994). Imitation, memory, and the representation of persons. Infant Behavior and Development, 17, 83–99.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Menzies, P., & Price, H. (1993). Causation as a secondary quality. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 44, 187–203.

    Google Scholar 

  • Michotte, A. E. (1963). The perception of causality (T. R. Miles & E. Miles, Trans.). London: Methuen (original work published 1946).

  • Psillos, S. (2002). Causation & explanation. Montreal: McGill-Queen’s University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rizzolati, G., & Craighero, L. (2004). The mirror–neuron system. Annual Review of Neuroscience, 27, 169–192.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schlottmann, A., & Surian, L. (1999). Do 9-month-olds perceive causation-at-a-distance? Perception, 28, 1105–1113.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sommerville, J. A., Hildebrand, E. A., & Crane, C. C. (2008). Experience matters: The impact of doing versus watching on infants’ subsequent perception of tool use events. Developmental Psychology, 44, 1249–1256.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sosa, E., & Tooley, M. (1993). Causation. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tomasello, M., & Call, J. (1997). Primate cognition. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Verschoor, S. A., Weidema, M., Biro, S., & Hommel, B. (2010). Where do action goals come from? Evidence for spontaneous action-effect binding in infants. Frontiers in Psychology, 1, 201.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Von Wright, G. (1971). Explanation and understanding. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, R. A., & Markman, E. M. (2006). Precision of imitation as a function of preschoolers’ understanding of the goal of the demonstration. Developmental Psychology, 42, 723–731.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, A. L. (2003a). Infants’ developing understanding of the link between looker and object. Developmental Science, 6, 297–311.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, J. (2003b). Making things happen. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, J. (2007). Interventionist theories of causation in psychological perspective. In A. Gopnik & L. Schulz (Eds.), Causal learning: Psychology, philosophy and computation (pp. 19–36). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, J. (2008a). Causation and manipulability. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (winter 2008 edition). http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2008/entries/causation-mani/.

  • Woodward, J. (2008b). Response to Strevens. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, LXXVII, 193–212.

  • Woodward, J. (2009). Agency and interventionist theories. In H. Beebee, C. Hitchcock, & P. Menzies, P (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of causation (pp. 234–262). New York: Oxford University Press.

Download references

Acknowledgments

We would like to thank two anonymous referees, Lena Kästner, and Markus Eronen for their valuable comments and suggestions. We would also like to thank the audience of the Zentrum für interdisziplinäre Forschung workshop ‘Agents and Causes’, and the HPS group of Leiden University’s Institute of Philosophy, for their feedback on a related paper presentation.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Victor Gijsbers.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Gijsbers, V., de Bruin, L. How agency can solve interventionism’s problem of circularity. Synthese 191, 1775–1791 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-013-0366-1

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-013-0366-1

Keywords

Navigation