Skip to main content
Log in

How (not) to think about idealisation and ceteris paribus-laws

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Semantic dispositionalism is the theory that a speaker’s meaning something by a given linguistic symbol is determined by her dispositions to use the symbol in a certain way. According to an objection by Kripke, further elaborated in Kusch (Analysis 65(2):156–163, 2005), semantic dispositionalism involves ceteris paribus-clauses and idealisations, such as unbounded memory, that deviate from standard scientific methodology. I argue that Kusch misrepresents both ceteris paribus-laws and idealisation, neither of which factually approximate the behaviour of agents or the course of events, but, rather, identify and isolate nature’s component parts and processes. An analysis of current results in cognitive psychology vindicates the idealisations involved and certain counterfactual assumptions in science generally. In particular, results suggest that there can be causal continuity between the dispositional structure of actual objects and that of highly idealised objects. I conclude by suggesting that we can assimilate ceteris paribus-laws with disposition ascriptions insofar as they involve identical idealising assumptions.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Ashcraft M.H. (1982). The development of mental arithmetic: A chronometric approach. Developmental Review, 2: 213–236

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ashcraft M.H. and Fierman B.A. (1982). Mental addition in third, fourth and sixth graders. Journal of Experimental Child Psychology, 33: 216–234

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baddeley A.D. (1986). Working memory. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Baddeley A.D. (2000). The episodic buffer: A new component of working memory?. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 4: 417–423

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bisanz J. and LeFevre J.-A. (1990). Strategic and nonstrategic processing in the development of mathematical cognition. In: Bjorklund, D.F. (eds) Children’s strategies: Contemporary views of cognitive development. Erlbaum, Hillsdale, NJ

    Google Scholar 

  • Brainerd C.J. (1983). Young children’s mental arithmetic errors: A working-memory analysis. Child Development, 54(4): 812–830

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carnap R. (1936). Testability and meaning. Philosophy of Science, 3(4): 419–471

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright N. (1983). How the laws of physics lie. Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright N. (1989). Nature’s capacities and their measurement. Clarendon Oxford Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright N. (1999). The dappled world. A study of the boundaries of science. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright N. (2002). In favor of laws that are not ceteris paribus after all. Erkenntnis, 57(3): 425–439

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky N. (1965). Aspects of the theory of syntax. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Earman J. and Roberts J. (1999). Ceteris paribus, there is no problem of provisos. Synthese, 118(3): 439–478

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Earman J. and Roberts J. et al. (2002). Ceteris paribus lost. Erkenntnis, 57: 281–301

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Elgin M. and Sober E. (2002). Cartwright on explanation and idealization. Erkenntnis, 57(3): 441–450

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fodor J.A. (1990). A theory of content II. A theory of content and other essays. MIT Press, Cambridge, Masachusetts

    Google Scholar 

  • Groen G.J. and Parkman J.M. (1972). A chronometric analysis of simple addition. Psychological Review, 79: 329–343

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Holyoak K.J., Morrison R.G. (Eds.) (2005). The Cambridge handbook of thinking and reasoning. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Kripke S.A. (1982). Wittgenstein on rules and private language. Blackwell, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Kusch M. (2005). Fodor V. Kripke: Semantic dispositionalism, idealization and ceteris paribus clauses. Analysis, 65(2): 156–163

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kusch M. (2006). A sceptical guide to meaning and rules: defending Kripke’s Wittgenstein. Acumen & McGill-Queen’s University Press.

  • Lange M. (2002). Who’s afraid of ceteris-paribus laws? or: How I learned to stop worrying and love them. Erkenntnis, 57: 407–423

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Laymon, R. (1985). Idealizations and the testing of theories by experimentation. Observation, experiment, and hypothesis. In Achinstein P.& Hannaway O. (Eds.), Modern physical science. Cambridge, Massachusetts: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laymon R. (1987). Using scott domains to replicate the notions of approximate and idealized data. Philosophy of Science, 54: 194–221

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Laymon, R. (1998). Idealizations. In E. Craig (Ed.), Routledge encyclopedia of philosophy online (http://www.rep.routledge.com/). Routledge: Taylor & Francis Group.

  • LeFevre J.-A. and Sadesky G.S. et al. (1996). Selection of procedures in mental addition: Reassessing the problem size effect in adults. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory and Cognition, 22(1): 216–230

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lemaire P. and Abdi H. et al. (1996). The role of working memory resources in cognitive arithmetic. European Journal of Cognitive Psychology, 8(1): 73–103

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lipton P. (1999). All else being equal. Philosophy, 74(288): 155–168

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Liu C. (1999). Approximation, idealization and laws of nature. Synthese, 118(2): 229–256

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Liu C. (2004a). Approximations, idealizations and models in statistical mechanics. Erkenntnis, 60(2): 235–263

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Liu C. (2004b). Laws and models in a theory of idealization. Synthese, 138(3): 363–385

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Martin C.B. (1994). Dispositions and conditionals. Philosophical Quarterly, 44(174): 1–8

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Martin, C. B., & Heil, J. (1997). Rules and powers. Language, Mind, and Ontology, 12, 283–311. Cambridge: Blackwell.

  • McMullin E. (1985). Galilean idealization. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 16: 247–273

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mellor D.H. (1974). In defense of dispositions. Philosophical Review, 83: 157–181

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mellor D.H. (2000). The semantics and ontology of dispositions. Mind, 109(436): 757–780

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morrison R.G. (2005). Thinking in Working Memory. In: Holyoak, K.J. and Morrison, R.G. (eds) The Cambridge handbook of thinking and reasoning. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Mott P. (1992). Fodor and ceteris paribus laws. Mind, 101(402): 335–346

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mumford S. (1998). Dispositions. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Mumford S. (2006). The ungrounded argument. Synthese, 149(3): 471–489

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nowak L. (1980). The structure of idealization. Reidel, Dordrecht

    Google Scholar 

  • Penner-Wilger M. and Leth-Steensen C. et al. (2002). Decomposing the problem-size effect: A comparison of response time distributions across cultures. Memory & Cognition, 30(7): 1160–1167

    Google Scholar 

  • Rivera S.M. and Reiss A.L. et al. (2005). Developmental changes in mental arithmetic: Evidence for increased functional Specialization in the left inferior parietal cortex. Cerebral Cortex, 15: 1779–1790

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Robinson K.M. and Ninowski J.E. (2003). Adults’ understanding of inversion concepts: How does performance on addition and subtraction inversion problems compare to performance on multiplication and division inversion problems?. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 57(4): 321–330

    Google Scholar 

  • Schiffer S. (1991). Ceteris paribus laws. Mind, 100: 1–17

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van Inwagen P. (1992). There is no such thing as addition. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 17: 138–159

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Robert Kowalenko.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Kowalenko, R. How (not) to think about idealisation and ceteris paribus-laws. Synthese 167, 183–201 (2009). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-008-9310-1

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-008-9310-1

Keywords

Navigation