Skip to main content
Log in

On the Distinction Between Law Schemata and Causal Laws

  • Published:
Acta Analytica Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The paper argues against the widely accepted assumption that the causal laws of (completed) physics, in contrast to those of the special sciences, are essentially strict. This claim played an important role already in debates about the anomalousness of the mental, and it currently experiences a renaissance in various discussions about mental causation, projectability of special science laws, and the nature of physical laws. By illustrating the distinction with some paradigmatic physical laws, the paper demonstrates that only law schemata are strict whereas causal laws are generally non-strict. Several potential replies to this argument are discussed and rejected as unsound.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. If there is such a thing as instantaneous causation as some claim to have located it in quantum systems (cf. Esfeld 2010b), it should we viewed as a very different kind of causation incomparable to the one we encounter in the special sciences and in physics outside quantum theory.

  2. If one rejects deterministic causation in favor of physical causal laws as irreducibly probabilistic, the conditional takes the form “\(\forall x(\phi x \rightarrow _{[P(\psi |\phi )]} \exists y(\psi y \wedge Rxy))\)”. In words: “For all individuals x, if x instantiates the property \(\phi \), then to probability \(P(\psi |\phi )\) there is an individual y which instantiates property \(\psi \) and to which x stands in the relation R.” \(P(\psi |\phi )\) is the probability of y instantiating \(\psi \) conditional upon x’s instantiation of \(\phi \). Of course, if one thinks of physical causal laws as irreducibly probabilistic, Davidson’s “perfect predictability under the terms of the system” (2001/1970, 218) does not hold in any case, and the falsity of PSL is immediately accepted. This is the reason why we restrict our discussion to the existence of deterministic and reducibly probabilistic physical causal laws.

  3. A system that is coupled to a heat bath is a system that is in good thermal contact with a much larger system (the heat bath) with a given temperature. The system and the heat bath can exchange heat and energy freely and since the heat bath is (ideally, infinitely) larger then the system, the temperature of the heat bath stays constant at all times. If the system and the heat bath are both in equilibrium the temperature of the system equals the temperature of the heat bath.

  4. A reversible change to the system is a slow change in time through which the system remains in equilibrium (or very close to it).

  5. It would have to use a formula such as: “\(\forall x(Gnx \wedge Vx \wedge Px \wedge F_{V'}x \rightarrow \exists y(Gny \wedge P'y \wedge (P'=\frac {nRT}{V^{\prime }}) \wedge Rxy))\)”. In words: “For all spacetime regions x, if they host n moles of gas in a container of volume V, such that the gas the gas acts onto the walls of the container with pressure P and such that a particular force \(F_{V'}x\) is applied to the container eventually altering it to volume \(V'\), then there is a second spacetime region y that is distinct from, but proximate to, x that hosts n moles of gas in a container such that the pressure of the gas equals \(\frac {nRT}{V^{\prime }}\)”. The length of this expression makes clear why using the compact string of symbols of Eq. 1 is very useful to state certain causal laws in physics.

  6. Note that the term “law schema” is foreign to the language of physics, which accesses the distinction from context or by describing Eq. 1 as an “idealization”. Obviously, the terminology used to capture the distinctions is of secondary importance to the capturing of the distinctions itself.

References

  • Anscombe, G. (1971). Causality and determination: An inaugural lecture. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baumgartner, M. (2008). Regularity theories reassessed. Philosophia, 36(3), 327–354.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Burge, T. (1992). Philosophy of language and mind: 1950–1990. The Philosophical Review, 101(1), 3–51.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright, N. (1983). How the laws of physics lie. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright, N. (1994). Nature’s capacities and their measurement. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright, N. (1999). The dappled world: A study of the boundaries of science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Crane, T. (1995). The mental causation debate. In Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society (pp. 211–236). The Aristotelian Society.

  • Davidson, D. (1967). Causal relations. The Journal of Philosophy, 64(21), 691–703.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1993). Thinking causes. See Heil and Mele (1993), pp 3–18.

  • Davidson, D. (1995). Laws and cause. Dialectica, 49(2–4), 263–280.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (2001/1970). Mental events. In D. Davidson (Ed.), Essays on actions and events (pp. 207–225). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Earman, J., & Roberts, J. (1999). Ceteris paribus, there is no problem of provisos. Synthese, 118(3), 439–478.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Earman, J., Roberts, J., Smith, S. (2002). Ceteris paribus post. Erkenntnis, 57(3), 281–301.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Esfeld, M. (2010a). Causal overdetermination for humeans? Metaphysica, 11(2), 1–6.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Esfeld, M. (2010b). Physics and causation. Foundations of Physics, 40(9–10), 1597–1610.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. (1989). Making mind matter more. Philosophical Topics, 17, 59–79.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. (1997). Special sciences: Still autonomous after all these years. Noûs 31 Supplement: Philosophical Perspectives, Mind, Causation, and World (Vol. 11, pp. 149–163).

  • Heil, J., & Mele, A. (1993). Mental causation. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Honderich, T. (1982). The argument for anomalous monism. Analysis, 42(1), 59–64.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hornsby, J. (1980). Which mental events are physical events? In Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society (Vol. 35, pp. 73–92).

  • Hume, D. (2000/1748). An enquiry concerning human understanding: A critical edition. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kim, J. (1989). The myth of nonreductive materialism. Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association, 63, 31–47.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kim, J. (1992). Multiple realization and the metaphysics of reduction. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 52(1), 1–26.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kim, J. (1993). Can supervenience and ’non-strict laws’ save anamalous monism. See Heil and Mele (1993), pp. 19–26.

  • Lewis, D. (1973). Causation. The Journal of Philosophy, 70(17), 556–567.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McLaughlin, B. (1993). On davidson’s response to the charge of epiphenomenalism. See Heil and Mele (1993), pp. 27–40.

  • Smith, S. (2002). Violated laws, ceteris paribus clauses, and capacities. Synthese, 130(2), 235–264.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sosa, E. (1984). Mind-body interaction and supervenient causation. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 9(1), 271–281.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Jens Harbecke.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Harbecke, J. On the Distinction Between Law Schemata and Causal Laws. Acta Anal 28, 423–434 (2013). https://doi.org/10.1007/s12136-013-0185-5

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s12136-013-0185-5

Keywords

Navigation