Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Artificial Intelligence and Semantics through the Prism of Structural, Post-Structural and Transcendental Approaches

  • Regular Article
  • Published:
Integrative Psychological and Behavioral Science Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

There is a problem associated with contemporary studies of philosophy of mind, which focuses on the identification and convergence of human and machine intelligence. This is the problem of machine emulation of sense. In the present study, analysis of this problem is carried out based on concepts from structural and post-structural approaches that have been almost entirely overlooked by contemporary philosophy of mind. If we refer to the basic definitions of “sign” and “meaning” found in structuralism and post-structuralism, we see a fundamental difference between the capabilities of a machine and the human brain engaged in the processing of a sign. This research will exemplify and provide additional evidence to support distinctions between syntactic and semantic aspects of intelligence, an issue widely discussed by adepts of contemporary philosophy of mind. The research will demonstrate that some aspect of a number of ideas proposed in relation to semantics and semiosis in structuralism and post-structuralism are similar to those we find in contemporary analytical studies related to the theory and philosophy of artificial intelligence. The concluding part of the paper offers an interpretation of the problem of formalization of sense, connected to its metaphysical (transcendental) properties.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For example, one of the French structuralists, E. Souriau, having analyzed the entire body of European dramaturgy, reduced them to just six possible functions and to five combinations, the total number of possible combinations being 210,141 (François 1991). In turn, Propp, a Russian folklorist and philologist, who greatly influenced European structuralism, operated a significantly smaller number of potentially possible plots of fairy tales, around 2,500 stories, in accordance with the famous index of stories by Aarne-Thompson (Propp 1968, Aarne 1955–1958; 1961; Thompson 1977). Propp discovered that the components of motifs of fairy tales are not combined randomly, but are represented by a finite number of acts-functions performed by a finite number of characters and are arranged in a certain order. A total of 32 functions were identified (for example, a loss, a wedding, a presentation of an award or a restriction) and 7 characters (the Villain, the Dispatcher, the (Magical) Helper, the Princess, the Donor, the Hero, the False hero), which, combined, form the structure of the story line of a fairy tale (Propp 1968). This structure can be presented in a simplified way: the violation of a prohibition and the actions of the Villain lead to a loss, which is then restored due to the actions of the Hero in cooperation with the Donor and the Helper. The Hero then celebrates a victory over the Villain, the False Hero is exposed, and the true Hero is then rewarded with the participation of the Princess.

  2. It is noteworthy that there is a trend in the modern literature on artificial intelligence to perceive some structuralists (G. Deleuze and F. Guattari) as philosophers, whose works offer an optimistic outlook on AI (De Landa 2011; Schomaker et al. 2013). Such a perception of their works is based on their reasoning concerning automatization of the modern world and humankind (Deleuze and Guattari 1972). Meanwhile, such optimism will hardly appear grounded if we consider the results of their analysis of sense and the nature of signs.

  3. A. Greimas’ model is used in the following example, which shows that any work can be formalized through the use of 6 “actants” (Subject – Object, Addressee – Addresser, Helper – Opponent), which are related to each other through the relations of modality (“wish,” “know,” “be able to”), and which perform 20 possible functions (Greimas 1964).

References

  • Anderson, J. R. (2005). Cognitive psychology and its implications. New York: Worth Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Andreyev, A. (2010). Kompleksniy Test Tyringa. Moskva: Infra-M.

    Google Scholar 

  • Angermuller, J. (2013). Le Champ de la théorie, Essor et Déclin du structuralisme en France. Paris: Hermann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Antti, A. (1955–58). Motif-Index of Folk-Literature: A Classification of Narrative Elements in Folktales, Ballads, Myths, Fables, Mediaeval Romances, Exempla, Fabliaux, Jest-Books and Local Legends. Copenhagen, rev. ed. by Stith Thompson: Rosenkilde and Bagge.

  • Antti, A. (1961). The Types of the Folktale: A Classification and Bibliography, The Finnish Academy of Science and Letters. Helsinki.

  • Aristotle. (1995). Categories, In Barnes, Jonathan. The Complete Works of Aristotle, 2 vols. Transl. J. L. Ackrill. Princeton: Princeton University Press. pp. 3–24.

  • Baker, G., & Hacker, P. (1980). Wittgenstein: Understanding and Meaning. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bakhtin, M.M. (1979). [The] Aesthetics of Verbal Art. (Russian) Moscow: Iskusstvo.

  • Baldassi, C., Alemi-Neissi A., Pagan M., Dicarlo J. J., Zecchina R., Zoccolan D. (2013). Shape similarity, better than semantic membership, accounts for the structure of visual object representations in a population of monkey inferotemporal neurons. PLoS Comput Biol.

  • Barthes, R. (1965). Éléments de sémiologie. Paris: Denoël/Gonthier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barthes, R. (1966). Introduction à l’analyse structurale des récits. Communications, 8, 7–33.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barthes, R. (1972). La mort de l’auteur. Nouveaux essais critiques. Paris: Éditions du Seuil.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bergson, A. (2007). L’evolution créatrice. Henri and Frédéric Worms (Editor), Presses Universitaires de France - PUF. Paperback, 693 pages. Language French. Originally 1907.

  • Block, N. (2002). ‘Searle’s Arguments Against Cognitive Science’. In Preston and Bishop (eds.).

  • Boden, M. (1988). Computer Models of the Mind, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press; pp. 238–251 were excerpted and published as ‘Escaping from the Chinese Room’, in The Philosophy of Artificial Intelligence, ed M. A. Boden. New York: Oxford University Press.

  • Brachman, R. (2005). Getting Back to ‘The Very Idea’. AI Magazine, 26(4), 48–50.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bringsjord, S. (1999). The zombie attack on the computational conception of mind. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 59(1), 41–69.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bringsjord, S. (1992). What Robots Can and Can’t Be. The Netherlands: Kluwer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bringsjord, S. (1996). Computationalism is Dead; Now What? - Response to Fetzer’s “Minds Are Not Computers: (Most) Thought Processes Are Not Computational”. Resource document. http://homepages.rpi.edu/~brings/SELPAP/fetz.nash/node1.html. Accessed May.

  • Bringsjord, S. (1998). Philosophy and ‘super’ computation. In J. Moor & T. Bynam (Eds.), The digital phoenix: How computers are changing philosophy (pp. 231–252). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, R. (1956). Meaning and necessity: A study in semantics and modal logic. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. (1992). Subsymbolic Computation and the Chinese Room. In J. Dinsmore (Ed.), The Symbolic and Connectionist Paradigms: Closing the Gap. Hillsdale: Lawrence Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. (1995). Minds, machines, and mathematics, Psyche 2 (1). Resource document. http://psyche.cs.monash.edu.au/psyche/volume2-1/psyche-95-2-7-shadows-7-chalmers.html.

  • Chomsky, N. (2000). New Horizons in the Study of Language and Mind. Cambridge.

  • Chomsky, N. (1966). Cartesian linguistics: a chapter in the history of rationalist thought. New York: Harper & Row.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, N. (1968). Language and mind. New York: Harcourt. Brace & World.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, N. (1975). Reflections on Language. NY Pantheon.

  • Churchland, P., & Churchland, P. (1990). Could a machine think? Scientific American, 262(1), 32–37.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Cogburn, J., & Megill, J. (2010). Are Turing machines Platonists? Inferentialism and the Philosophy of Mind. Minds and Machines, 20(3), 423–40.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cognitive Linguistics (1999). Foundations, Scope, and Methodology. Ed. by T. Janssen and G. Redeker. Berlin-N.Y.: Mouton de Gruyter.

  • Cole, D. (1991). Artificial minds: cam on Searle. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 69, 329–33.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Copeland, J. (2002). The Chinese Room from a Logical Point of View. In Preston and Bishop (eds.), 104–122.

  • Cortazar, J. (1987). Hopscotch. Pantheon Modern Writers Series.

  • Dawson, J. W., Jr. (1993). The compactness of first-order logic: from Gödel to Lindström. History and Philosophy of Logic, 14, 15–37.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • De Landa, M. (2011). Philosophy & Simulation: The Emergence of Synthetic Reason.

  • Deleuze, G. (1973). À quoi reconnaît-on le structuralisme? Gilles Deleuze (in: Histoire de la philosophie, Idées, Doctrines. Vol. 8: Le XXe siècle, Hachette, Paris: edited by François Châtelet), pp. 299–335.

  • Deleuze, G., & Guattari F. (1972). L’Anti-dipe Capitalisme et schizophrénie. Paris: Les éditions de Minuit (coll. « Critique »), 494 p.

  • Deleuze, G. (1968). Différence et repetition. Paris: Presses Universitaires de France. 409 p.

    Google Scholar 

  • Deleuze, G. (1969). Logique du sens. Paris: Les éditions de Minuit (coll. « Critique »), 392 p.

  • Denett, D. (1998). Can machines think? ‘Brainchildren: essays on designing minds’. Cambridge.

  • Derrida, J. (1967). L’Écriture et la difference. Seuil.

  • Derrida, J. (1971). La mythologie blanche (la métaphore dans le texte philosophique). Relié.

  • Dreyfus, H.L. (1972). What Computers Can’t Do: The Limits of Artificial Intelligence.

  • Dreyfus, H.L. (1986). Mind Over Machine: The Power of Human Intuition and Expertise in the Era of the Computer.

  • Dreyfus, H.L. (1992). What Computers Still Can’t Do: A Critique of Artificial Reason.

  • Duch, W., Oentaryo, R., & Pasquier, M. (2008). Cognitive architectures: where do we go from here. Frontiers in Artificial Intelligence and Applications, 171, 122–136.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eco, U. (1975). Trattato di semiotica generale. English translation: (1978), A Theory of Semiotics. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eco, U. (1997). Kant e l’ornitorinco – English translation: Kant and the Platypus: Essays on Language and Cognition, Houghton Mifflin Harcour.

  • Edelstein, L. (1966). The Meaning of Stoicism. (Mass). Cambridge

  • Fauconnier, G. (1985). Mental spaces: Aspects of meaning construction in natural language. Cambridge: MA and London: MIT Press/Bradford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. D. (1991). Yin and Yang in the Chinese Room. In D. Rosenthal (Ed.), The Nature of Mind. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • François, D. (1991). Histoire du structuralisme. Paris: La Découverte.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frege, G. (1948). Sense and reference. The Philosophical Review, 57(3), 209–230.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frege, G. (1980). Philosophical and Mathematical Correspondence. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Funge (2004). Artificial Intelligence for Computer Games: An Introduction. A K Peters. ISBN 1-56881-208-6.

  • Gardiner, H. (1987). The mind’s new science: A history of the cognitive revolution. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Greimas, A.-J. (1964). Cours de séman-tique structurale, cours ronéotypé, VI, 5.

  • Greimas, A.-J. (1966). Sémantique structurale. P.: Larousse, p. 129 sqq.

  • Grice P.H. (1971). «Intention and Uncertainty», Proceedings of the British Academy, pp. 263–279.

  • Grice, P. H. (1969). Utterer’s meaning and intention. The Philosophical Review, 78, 147–77.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grice, P.H. (1968). ‘Further Notes on Logic and Conversation’, in Syntax and Semantics: Pragmatics, v 9, P. Cole (ed.). New York: Academic Press, Reprinted in SWW.Grice P.H., 183–97.

  • Grice, P. H. (1981). Presupposition and Conversational Implicature. In P. Cole (Ed.), Radical Pragmatics (pp. 183–97). New York: Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grice, P.H. (1982). Meaning Revisited. In Mutual Knowledge, N.V. Smith (ed), New York: Academic Press, Reprinted in SWW, 223–43.

  • Halliday, J.K. (1962). Linguistique générale et linguistique appliquée//Etudes de linguistique appliquée, № 1, p. 12.

  • Harnad, S. (1990). The symbol grounding problem. Physica D, 42, 335–346.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harnad, S. (1991). Other bodies, other minds: a machine incarnation of an old philosophical problem. Minds and Machines, 1, 43–54.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harnad, S. (1993). Grounding symbols in the analog world with neural nets: a hybrid model. Think, 2, 12–20.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harnad, S. (1994). Computation Is Just Interpretable Symbol Manipulation: Cognition Isn’t. Minds and Machines (Special Issue on “What Is Computation”) 4:379–390.

  • Harnad, S. (2001). The Mind/Body Problem is the Feeling/Function Problem: Harnad on Dennett on Chalmers. Technical Report. Department of Electronics and Computer Sciences. University of Southampton.

  • Harnad, S. (2002). Minds, Machines, and Searle2: What’s Right and Wrong about the Chinese Room Argument. In Preston and Bishop (eds.), 294–307.

  • Harnad, S. (2003). Can a machine be conscious? How? Journal of Consciousness Studies, 10(4–5), 69–75.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harnad, S. (2007). The Annotation Game: On Turing (1950) on Computing, Machinery and Intelligence. In R. Epstein & G. Peters (Eds.), The Turing Test Sourcebook: Philosophical and Methodological Issues in the Quest for the Thinking Computer. The Netherlands: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harris, Z.S. (1952). Discourse Analysis//Language, № 28, p.р. 1–30.

  • Haugeland, J. (2002). Syntax, Semantics, Physics. In Preston and Bishop (eds.), 379–392.

  • Heidegger, M. (1927). Sein und Zeit, Gesamtausgabe.

  • Hofstadter, D. (1981). ‘Reflections on Searle’. In Hofstadter & Dennett (Eds.), The Mind’s I. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hofstadter, D. R. (1979). Gödel, Escher, Bach: an Eternal Golden Braid. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Horn, L. (2004). Implicature // Handbook on Pragmatics.

  • Kant, I. (1781). Critik der reinen Vernunft. Riga.

  • Koster, J. (1996). “Saussure meets the brain”. In R. Jonkers, E. Kaan, J. K. Wiegel, eds., Language and Cognition 5, Groningen, Yearbook 1992 of the Research Group for Linguistic Theory and Knowledge Representation of the University of Groningen, pp. 115–120.

  • Kristeva, J. (1969). Séméiôtiké: recherches pour une sémanalyse. Paris: Edition du Seuil.

  • Kurzweil, R. (2000). The Age of Spiritual Machines: When Computers Exceed Human Intelligence. New York: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lakoff, G. (1987). Women, Fire, and Dangerous Things: What Categories Reveal About the Mind. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lakoff, G., & Johnson М. (1999). Philosophy in the flesh. The embodied mind and its challenge to the Western thought. New York.

  • Langacke, R.W. (1987). Foundations of Cognitive Grammar, Vol. 1. Stanford: St. Univ. Press.

  • Lcvin, Y. (1974). On Semiotics Of Truth Distortion. Informatsioimye Voprosy Semiotiki, Lingvistiki I Mashinnogo Perevoda. Moskva: VINITI.

  • Leont’eva, N. (1981). Semantics of a coherent text and units of information analysis. Technologiya I Informaciya, 17, 67–89.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levine, J. (1983). Materialism and qualia: the explanatory gap. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 64, 354–361.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lévi-Strauss, Cl. (1949). Les structures élémentaires de la parenté. Plon. Paris.

  • Lévi-Strauss, Cl. (1958). Anthropologie structurale. P.: Plon, p. 233.

  • Lewis, R. (2012). Nice Film If You Can Get It: Understanding Mulholland Drive. The Guardian. Retrieved 17.

  • Logothetis, N. K., & Sheinberg, D. L. (1996). Visual object recognition. Annual Review of Neuroscience, 19, 577–621.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Lotman, Y. (1979). The origin of plot in the light of typology. Poetics Today, 1(1–2), 161–184.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lucas, J. R. (1964). Minds, Machines and Gödel. In A. R. Anderson (Ed.), Minds and Machines. Englewood Cliffs: Prentice Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lucas, J. R. (1970). “Mechanism: A Rejoinder”, Lucas’s response to Coder (1969) and Lewis (1969). Philosophy, 45, 149–51.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lyotard, J.F. (1988). La condition postmoderne / Milorad Belančić.

  • MacDorman, K. F. (2007). Life after the symbol system metaphor. Interaction Studies, 8(1), 143–158.

  • McCall, S. (1999). Can a turing machine know that the Gödel sentence is true? Journal of Philosophy, 96(10), 525–32.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McDermott, D. (1997). Interview with Drew McDermott. May 14, New York Times.

  • McGinn, С. (1989). Can we solve the Mind--Body problem? Mind, 98(391), 349–366.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McGinn, C. (1999). Mysterious Flame: Conscious Minds in a Material World. N. Y.

  • Milner, J.C. (2002). Le Périple structural, Figures et paradigmes, coll. « La couleur des idées ». Le Seuil, Paris.

  • Moravec, H. (1999). Robot: Mere Machine to Transcendent Mind. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Müller, V. (2013). Introductore Note. Philosophy and Theory of Artificial Intelligence. New York: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Nietzsche, F.W. (1873). Über Wahrheit und Lüge im außermoralischen Sinne. http://gutenberg.spiegel.de/buch/uber-wahrheit-und-luge-im-aussermoralischen-sinne-3243/1.

  • Nute, D. (2011). ‘A Logical Hole the Chinese Room Avoids’, this is a reply to Shaffer. Minds and Machines, 21, 431–3.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Paivio, A. (1986). Mental Representations. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pask, G. (1975). Cybernetics of Human Learning and Performance. The Guide to a Theory and Research. London: Hutch in son.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peirce, S.S. (1955). Logic as Semiotic: The Theory of Signs (1898). New York: Dover. In: Justus Bucher (ed.). Philosophical Writings of Peirce, 98–119.

  • Pelletier, F.J. (1994). The Principle of Semantic Compositionality // Topoi 13.

  • Penrose, R. (1989). Shadows of the Mind: A Search for the Missing Science of Consciousness. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Penrose, R. (2002). Consciousness, Computation, and the Chinese Room. In Preston and Bishop (eds.), 226–249.

  • Pergnier, M. (2012). De Saussure à Saussure, Lausanne, l’Age d’Homme.

  • Pinker, S. (1997). How the Mind Works. New York: Norton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pinker, S. (2007). The Stuff of Thought: Language as a Window into Human Nature. London: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Plato (1925). Hippias Major, translated by W. R. M. Lamb, Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press. London: William Heinemann Ltd. From Perseus Project (Stph. p.) Vol. 9.

  • Posner, R. (1987). “Charles Morris and the Behavioral Foundations of Semiotics” Classics of Semiotics (p. 25). New York: Ed. Krampen, Plemun Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prinz, W. (1984). Modes of linkage between perception and action. In W. Prinz & A.-F. Sanders (Eds.), Cognition and motor processes (pp. 185–193). Berlin: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Propp, V. Y. (1968). Morphology of the Tale University. Austin: Texas Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pylyshyn, Z. (2003). Return of the mental image: are there really pictures in the brain? Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 7, 113–118.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Pylyshyn, Z. W. (1984). Computation and cognition. Cambridge: MIT/Bradford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rapaport, W. (2006). How Helen Keller used syntactic semantics to escape from a Chinese room. Minds and Machines, 16(4), 381–436.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Russell, B. (1905). On Denoting. Mind, 14(56), 479–493.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Saussure, de F. (1916). Cours de linguistique générale, éd. Payot, 1995, Originally.

  • Schomaker, L., Kouw, M., & Zant, T. (2013). Generative Artificial Intelligence in Müller V. Philosophy and Theory of Artificial Intelligence. New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schweizer, P. (2012). The externalist foundations of a truly total turing test. Minds and Machines, 22, 191–212.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scott, B. (2002). The Illusion of Intelligence // AI Game Programming Wisdom / Rabin, Steve. — Charles River Media, p. 19–20.

  • Searle, J. (1982). The Myth of the Computer // NewYork Review of Books, 29/7.

  • Searle, J. (1991). Minds, Brains, and Programs. The Nature of Mind, N.Y, (ed. D. Rosental).

  • Searle, J. (2007). Grice on meaning: 50 years later. Teorema, 26, 9–18.

    Google Scholar 

  • Selfridge, O. G. (1955). Pattern recognition and modern computers. Proceedings Western Joint Computer Conference, Los Angeles, California.

  • Sextus Empirikus (1976). Мoskva: Misl. Sochineniye v 2 tomakh. Tom. 2.

  • Shaffer, M. (2009). A logical hole in the Chinese room. Minds and Machines, 19(2), 229–235.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Simon, H., & Eisenstadt, S. (2002). ‘A Chinese Room that Understands’. In Preston and Bishop (eds.), 95–108.

  • Sloman, A., & Croucher, M. (1980). How to turn an information processor into an understanding. Brain and Behavioral Sciences, 3, 447–8.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sperry, R. W. (1952). Neurology and the mind-brain problem. American Scientist, 40, 291–312.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sprevak, M. (2007). Chinese rooms and program portability. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 58(4), 755–776.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Taddeo, M., & Floridi, L. (2005). The symbol grounding problem: a critical review of fifteen years of research. Journal of Experimental and Theoretical Artificial Intelligence, 17(4), 419–445.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Talmy, L. (2000). Toward a cognitive semantics. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, S. (1977). The Folktale. Berkeley: University of California Press.Todorov Tz. Les catégories du récit littéraire//Communications, № 8.

  • Turing, A. (1950). Computing machine and intelligence. Mind, 59, 433–460.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vachek, J.A. (1964). Prague School Reader in Linguistics. Indiana Univ. Press, p. 468.

  • Vescovini, G.F. (éd.) (2001). Le problème des Transcendantaux du XIVe au XVIIe siècle. Paris: Vrin, « Bibliothèque d’Histoire de la Philosophie ».

  • Weber, M. (1919). Wissenschaft als Beruf. München und Leipzig: Verlag von Duncker & Humblot.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1921). Logisch-Philosophische Abhandlung. Cambridge: Annalen der Naturphilosophie.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woolf, V. (2009). Mrs Dalloway. Oxford University Press. Print.

Download references

Acknowledgments

The article was prepared within the framework of the Academic Fund Program at the National Research University Higher School of Economics (HSE) in 2016–2017 (grant № 16-01-0032) and supported within the framework of a subsidy granted to the HSE by the Government of the Russian Federation for the implementation of the Global Competitiveness Program.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Diana Gasparyan.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Gasparyan, D. Artificial Intelligence and Semantics through the Prism of Structural, Post-Structural and Transcendental Approaches. Integr. psych. behav. 50, 704–743 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s12124-016-9344-8

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s12124-016-9344-8

Keywords

Navigation