Skip to main content
Log in

Abstract

Autopoietic theory is increasingly seen as a candidate for a radical theory of law, both in relation to its theoretical credentials and its relevance in terms of new and emerging forms of law. An aspect of the theory that has remained less developed, however, is its material side, and more concretely the theory’s accommodation of bodies, space, objects and their claim to legal agency. The present article reads Luhmann’s theory of autopoietic systems in a radical and material manner, linking it on the one hand to current post-structural theorisations of law and society, and on the other hand extending its ambit to accommodate the influx of material considerations that have been working their way through various other disciplines. The latter comprises both a materialisation of the theory itself and ways of conceptualising the legal system as material through and through. This I do by further developing what I have called Critical Autopoiesis, namely an acentric, topological, post-ecological and posthuman understanding of Luhmann’s theory, that draws on Deleuzian thought, feminist theory, geography, non-representational theory, and new material and object-oriented ontologies. These are combined with some well-rehearsed autopoietic concepts, such as distinction, environment and boundaries; Luhmann’s earlier work on materiality continuum; more recent work on bodies and space; as well as his work on form and medium in relation to art. The article concludes with five suggestions for an understanding of what critical autopoietic materiality might mean for law.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See indicatively [7, 45, 20, 28].

  2. e.g., [12, 59, 65].

  3. e.g., [67, 60].

  4. My response to these issues can be found in [51].

  5. [52].

  6. [39: 1117]. To put it simply, third-order or critical knowledge would be seeing oneself through the eyes of another in a social interaction. In systemic language this would translate in the untranslatable ‘observing oneself observing oneself while observing and being observed by another’.

  7. This is reminiscent of Nicola [29: 195], description of feminist legal critique, itself taking place from within and at the law: “to question, unsettle and expose to careful scrutiny not only current laws and their organisation but also the claims to authority and legitimacy which legal officials, law-makers, legal practices and theories express on law’s behalf.”.

  8. [39: 889].

  9. This is the reason for which I have described one of the basic tenets of Luhmann’s theory, namely structural coupling between social systems, as a coupling of environments, of contingencies rather than illusions of knowledge and simplification. See [51].

  10. [19: 28].

  11. This is a not-so-covert reference to Deleuzian/Guattarian rhizomatics [15].

  12. [51].

  13. Luhmann has referred to Deleuze more and more in his later texts. Luhmann’s use of the concept of meaning is a point in case, also analysed below: Luhmann moved away from an initial Husserlian understanding of Sinn and towards a Deleuzian Sens. This marks an open rupture of autopoiesis with phenomenology and even a concession to a potential access to ontology.

  14. [54, 5, 9, 56].

  15. Felicitous exceptions are not infrequent. See indicatively [64, 61, 63, 12, 59], amongst others.

  16. [44].

  17. [41: 73].

  18. [39: 76].

  19. [33: 178].

  20. [10].

  21. [45].

  22. Calm [13: 73] parallels the effect of communication to that of Freudian unconscious: just as “the concept of the Unconscious anonymized the psychic entity, transforming it in a bundle of processes governed by a complex affectual economy”, communication inaugurates a grand ontological reversal “as an inaugurative performance endowing sociology with its proper object: the social.”

  23. [41: 235].

  24. [69].

  25. [23, 42, 46].

  26. [50].

  27. [6, 55].

  28. More concretely, through the mechanism of re-entry, which is the internal systemic reproduction of the difference between the specific system and its environment.

  29. [39].

  30. “only in exceptional cases (i.e., on different levels of reality, irritated by environmental factors), can [the system] start reverberating, can it be set in motion. This is the case we designate as resonance.” [34: 15].

  31. [16].

  32. [16: 59].

  33. One of which I have developed in my 2010 book on Niklas Luhmann, which revolves around a critical reading of Luhmann in line with other, poststructuralist theories.

  34. Autopoiesis “should not be conceived as the production of a determinate form (Gestalt). Rather, it is important to be conceptualised as the production of a difference between system and environment” [39: 66].

  35. [41: 84, n. 19].

  36. [38: 412].

  37. A boundary of an interaction system is defined along the notion of presence: “they include everything that can be treated as present and are able, if need be, to decide who, among those who happen to be present, is to be treated as present and who not.” [38: 412].

  38. [37: 380].

  39. This is what Luhmann following [43] calls structural coupling.

  40. [7, 47, 10].

  41. See my 2008 contribution on this.

  42. Luhmannian ‘nature’ is helpfully defined by [27: 8] in the following terms: “Nature extends from biological phenomena, such as events in the human body or in the natural world of plants and animals, to stars, planets, atoms and nuclei, to natural catastrophes such as earthquakes or global warming.”.

  43. [35: 75–76].

  44. See e.g., [39].

  45. Luhmann, following Parsons, calls it interpenetration. Interpenetration allows such associations, since it “presupposes the capacity for connecting different kinds of autopoiesis -here, organic life, consciousness, and communication” [38: 219]. Interpretation is the reciprocal availability of complexities, which, however, remain peculiar to the original systems; there can be no fundamental common ground among systems [38: 35]. Indeed, it has not been named interpenetration lightly: “the boundaries of one system can be included in the operational domain of the other…Every system that participates in interpenetration realizes the other within itself as the other’s difference between system and environment, without destroying its own system/environment difference” [38: 217]. Consequently, [37: 380], defines socialisation as “the process that, by interpenetration, forms the psychic system and the bodily behavior of human beings that it controls.” See also [68].

  46. Thus [37: 381]: “Communication operates with an unspecific reference to the participating state of mind; it is especially unspecific as to perception. It cannot copy states of mind, cannot imitate them, cannot represent them.” And further, [38: 408]: “Society is the all-encompassing social system that includes everything that is social and therefore does not admit a social environment.” And also, [38: 409]: “For [society] there are no environmental contacts on the level of its own functioning…It is completely and without exception a closed system.”

  47. [34].

  48. Admittedly, Luhmann accepts that autopoiesis is just one of the ways in which society can be described. But one gets the distinct impression that he seems to think it is also the most adequate one.

  49. [39: 18]. The acknowledgment of medium is as far as Luhmann goes in terms of explicit ‘corporeal’ and material relevance; forms remain dematerialised and incorporeal.

  50. [17: 108].

  51. [40: 106].

  52. [17: 108].

  53. [17: 10].

  54. [17: 12].

  55. [17: 10].

  56. [17: 13].

  57. [17: 25].

  58. [17: 78].

  59. [39: 54].

  60. Note, however, the fact that in his earlier book on law, 1985a, Luhmann refers to the ‘material dimension’ of expectations which is the acknowledgement of the necessary community of the world in order for expectations to exist. This appears in the form of the need for a fictional consensus on which the reciprocal confirmation and limitation of expectations is exercised. This consensus is material in the strict sense of the word: as [11: 124], writes, it consists of “a commonality of events, visible action and symbols for the invisible.”.

  61. “Forms are generated in a medium via a tight coupling of its elements…” [40: 104].

  62. [36: 141].

  63. [62: 3].

  64. [45: 76].

  65. In the context of linguistic priority, Catherine Hayles [26: 192] notes for example: “one contemporary belief likely to stupefy future generations is the postmodern orthodoxy that the body is primarily, if not entirely, a linguistic construction.”.

  66. [53].

  67. [24, 1, 25, 30].

  68. See [26] on this.

  69. My contribution to the discussion can be found in [51].

  70. See [49], also [3].

  71. [40: 106].

  72. [40: 103].

  73. [40: 106].

  74. [44: 106].

  75. [2: 319].

  76. [51].

  77. The system’s (and Luhmann’s) attempts at excluding matter are another reassertion of environmental affirmation. A readily available example of such present absence is the way Luhmann deals with ecology. Thus, he writes, “if anywhere, it is in ecological communication that society places itself in question.” [34: 142]. If one were to go even further, one would see that the entirely material, strictly topological terminology employed by autopoietic theory is nothing but a memento of the absence of materiality, and as such, a successful strategy to render materiality always present.

  78. [9].

  79. [9: 160].

  80. [9: 21].

  81. [18: 451].

  82. [18: 408].

  83. [18: 420].

  84. [18: 421].

  85. [18: 409].

  86. See [2: 319]: “to think outside the postenlightenment bifurcation of matter into primary and secondary qualities that underpin the distinction between materialism and idealism (and entangled distinctions such as matter/form, material/immaterial, actual/virtual, material/discursive, mind/matter). Instead, questions are asked around the complexity, and indeterminacy, of matter and about how qualities of liveliness are internal to, rather than in supplement or opposition to, the taking place of matter and materiality.”

  87. [32: 3–4].

  88. [58].

  89. [58: 169].

  90. [22: 255].

  91. [4].

  92. See [48, 8, 46].

  93. [57].

  94. Philippopoulos-Mihalopoulos [52, 53].

  95. [4: 31–32].

  96. [66].

  97. [4].

  98. [14: 16].

  99. [21].

  100. See http://www.nzherald.co.nz/nz/news/article.cfm?c_id=1&objectid=10830586 for the agreement between the Crown and the local community of the Whanganui river in New Zealand, recognising the latter as having legal agency with all its “physical and metaphysical elements”.

  101. [58].

  102. [31: 81].

  103. [41: 460] (translation modified).

  104. [18: 451].

  105. [40: 119].

References

  1. Akestrom Andersen, N., and I.J. Sand (eds.). 2011. Hybrid forms of governance: Self-suspension of power. London: Palgrave.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Anderson, B., and J. Wylie. 2009. On geography and materiality. Environment and Planning A 41: 318–335.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  3. Ben-Dor, O. (ed.). 2011. Law and art: Justice, ethics and aesthetics. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Bennett, J. 2010. Vibrant matter: A political ecology of things. Durham, NC: Duke University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Berressen, H. 2009. Structural couplings: Radical constructivism and a Deleuzian Ecologics. In Deleuze|Guattari and ecology, ed. B. Herzongerath. Basingstoke: Palgrave.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Borch, C. 2008. Foam architecture: Managing co-isolated associations. Economy and Society 37(4): 548–571.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  7. Borch, C. 2011. Key sociologists: Niklas Luhmann. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Bottomley, A. 2009. They shall be simple in their homes…the many dimensions of co-operative housing. In Changing contours of domestic life, family and law: Caring and sharing ed. A. Bottomley, & S. Wong, 49-66. Oxford: Hart—Oñati International Series in Law and Society.

  9. Bryant, L. 2011. The democracy of objects. Ann Arbor, MI: Open Humanities Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  10. Cesaratto, T. 2013. Luhmann, all too Luhmann: Nietzsche, Luhmann and the human. In Luhmann observed: Radical theoretical encounters, ed. A. la Cour, and A. Philippopoulos-Mihalopoulos. Basingstoke: Palgrave.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Christodoulidis, E. 1998. Law and reflexive politics. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  12. Clam, J. 1997. Droit et société chez Luhmann: La contingence des norms. Paris: Presses Universitaires de France.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Clam, J. 2000. System's sole constituent, the operation: Clarifying a central concept of Luhmannian theory. Acta Sociologica 43(1): 63–79.

    Google Scholar 

  14. De Landa, M. 1997. A thousand years of nonlinear history. New York: Zone.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Deleuze, G. 1988. Foucault (trans: Hand, S). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

  16. Deleuze, G. 2004a. Difference and repetition (trans: Patton, P). London: Continuum.

  17. Deleuze, G. 2004b. The logic of sense (trans: Lester, M with Stivale, C). London: Continuum.

  18. Deleuze, G., and F. Guattari. 1988. A thousand plateaus: Capitalism and Schizophrenia (trans: Massumi, B). London: Continuum.

  19. Deleuze, G., and F. Guattari. 1994. What is philosophy? (trans: Tomlinson, H and Burchell, G). Columbia University Press: New York.

  20. Fischer-Lescano, A. 2012. Critical systems theory. Philosophy and Social Criticism 38(1): 3–23.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  21. Grear, A. 2010. Redirecting human rights: Facing the challenge of corporate legal humanity. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  22. Guggenheim, M. 2011. (Un)building social systems: The concrete foundations of society. In Comunicaciones, Semanticas y Redes: Usos y Desviaciones de la Sociologia de Niklas Luhmann, ed. I. Farias, and J. Ossandon. México: Universidad Iberoamericana.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Haldar, P. 1999. Edifice Lex: The logic and function of ornament in court buildings. Journal of Social Change and Critical Inquiry 1(1): 1–19.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Hansen, M.B.N. 2009. System-environment hybrids. In Emergence and embodiment. New essays on second-order cybernetics eds Clarke, B. and Hansen, M.B.N. Durham: Duke UP.

  25. Haraway, D. 2004. The haraway reader. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  26. Hayles, K. 1999. How we became Posthuman: Virtual bodies in cybernetics, literature, and informatics. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  27. King, M., and C. Thornhill. 2003. Niklas Luhmann’s theory of politics and law. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  28. la Cour, A., and A. Philippopoulos-Mihalopoulos (eds.). 2013. Luhmann observed: Radical theoretical encounters. Basingstoke: Palgrave.

    Google Scholar 

  29. Lacey, N. 1993. Closure and critique in feminist jurisprudence. In Closure or critique, ed. A. Norrie. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  30. Latour, B. 1993. We have never been modern (trans: Porter, C) Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

  31. Latour, B. 2004. The making of law: An ethnography of the Conseil d’Etat. Cambridge: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  32. Law, J. 1999. After ANT: Complexity, naming and complexity. In Actor network theory and after, ed. J. Law, and J. Hassard. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Luhmann, N. 1982. The differentiation of society (trans: Holmes, S., and Larmore, C). New York: Columbia University Press.

  34. Luhmann, N. 1989. Ecological communication (trans: Bednarz, J Jr). Cambridge: Polity Press.

  35. Luhmann, N. 1992. The concept of society. Thesis Eleven 31: 67–80.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  36. Luhmann, N. 1992. Closure and structural coupling. Cardozo Law Review 13(5): 1419–1442.

    Google Scholar 

  37. Luhmann, N. 1994. How can the mind participate in communication? In Materialities of communication ed. Gumbrecht, H.U., and Pfeiffer, K.L., (trans: Whobrey, W). Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.

  38. Luhmann, N. 1995. Social systems (trans: Bednarz, J Jr.) Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.

  39. Luhmann, N. 1997. Die Gesellschaft der Gesellschaft. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.

    Google Scholar 

  40. Luhmann, N. 2000. Art as a social system (trans: Knodt, E) Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.

  41. Luhmann, N. 2004. Law as a social system ed. Kastner, F., Nobles, R., Schiff, D., and Ziegert, R (trans: Ziegert, K). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  42. Marrani, D. 2010. Confronting the symbolic position of the Judge in Western Europeans legal traditions, a comparative essay. European Journal of Legal Studies 3(1): 31–49.

    Google Scholar 

  43. Maturana, H., and F. Varela. 1972. Autopoiesis and cognition: The realization of the living. Dordecht: Reidel Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  44. Messner, C. 2004. Observing victims: Global insecurities and the systemic imagination of justice in world society. Hart: In Imaginary Boundaries of Justice ed. R. Lippens. Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  45. Moeller, H.-G. 2012. The radical Luhmann. New York City: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  46. Mulcahy, L. 2010. Legal architecture: Justice, due process and the place of law. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  47. Paterson, J. 1996. Who is Zenon Bankowski talking to? The person in the sight of autopoiesis. In Law as communication, ed. D. Nelken. Aldershot: Dartmouth.

    Google Scholar 

  48. Persaud, S. 2013. Only connect: Luhmann and bioethics. In Luhmann observed: Radical theoretical encounters, ed. A. la Cour, and A. Philippopoulos-Mihalopoulos. Basingstoke: Palgrave.

    Google Scholar 

  49. Philippopoulos-Mihalopoulos, A. 2004. Beauty and the beast: Art and law in the hall of mirrors. Entertainment Law 2(3): 1–34.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  50. Philippopoulos-Mihalopoulos, A. (ed.). 2007. Law and the city. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  51. Philippopoulos-Mihalopoulos, A. 2010. Niklas Luhmann: Law, justice, society. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  52. Philippopoulos-Mihalopoulos, A. 2011. Critical autopoiesis: The environment of the law. In Law’s environment: Critical legal perspectives, ed. B. De Vries, and L. Francot. The Hague: Eleven International Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  53. Philippopoulos-Mihalopoulos, A. 2011. “…the sound of a breaking string”: Critical environmental law and ontological vulnerability. Journal of Environmental Law and Human Rights 2(1): 5–22.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  54. Philippopoulos-Mihalopoulos, A. 2013. Folding autopoiesis: between Luhmann and Deleuze. In Observing Luhmann: Radical theoretical encounters, ed. A. La Cour, and A. Philippopoulos-Mihalopoulos. Basingstoke: Palgrave.

    Google Scholar 

  55. Philippopoulos-Mihalopoulos, A. 2013. Atmospheres of law: Senses. Affects, Lawscapes, Emotion, Space and Society 7(2): 35–44.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  56. Pottage, A. 1998. Power as an art of contingency: Luhmann. Deleuze, Foucault, Economy and Society 27(1): 1–27.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  57. Pottage, A. 2011. Biotechnology as environmental regulation. In Law and ecology. New environmental foundations, ed. Andreas Philippopoulos-Mihalopoulos, 105–125. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  58. Pottage, A. 2012. The materiality of what? Journal of Law and Society 39(1): 167–183.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  59. Rasch, W. 2000. Niklas Luhmann’s modernity: The paradoxes of differentiation. Palo Alto, CA: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  60. Rottleuthner, H. 1988. Biological metaphors in legal thought. In Autopoietic law: A new approach to law and society, ed. G. Teubner. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  61. Schutz, A. 1996. The twilight of global polis: On losing paradigms, environing systems and observing world society. In Global law without a state, ed. G. Teubner. Aldershot: Ashgate.

    Google Scholar 

  62. Spencer Brown, G. 1969. Laws of form. London: George Allen and Unwin.

    Google Scholar 

  63. Stäheli, U. 2000. Sinnzusammenbruche: Eine dekonstruktive Lekture von Niklas Luhmanns Systemtheorie. Velbrück: Weilerswist.

    Google Scholar 

  64. Teubner, G. 2001. Alienating justice: On the surplus value of the twelfth camel. In Law’s new boundaries: The consequences of legal autopoiesis, ed. J. Pribáñ, and D. Nelken. Aldershot: Ashgate.

    Google Scholar 

  65. Teubner, G. 2006. Rights of non-humans? Electronic agents and animals as new actors in politics and law. Journal of Law and Society 33(4): 497–521.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  66. Teubner, G. 2011. Networks as connected contracts (trans: Everson, M). London: Hart.

  67. Van Zandt, D. 1992. The breath of life in the law. Cardozo Law Review 13(5): 1745–1763.

    Google Scholar 

  68. Vanderstraeten, R. 2000. Autopoiesis and socialization: On Luhmann’s reconceptualization of communication and socialization. British Journal of Sociology 51(3): 581–598.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  69. Vismann, C. 2008. Files. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

With deep gratitude for their comments to Alain Pottage; Todd Cesaratto; Hans-Georg Moeller; Christian Borch, Lynn Roseberry and Anders la Cour; the Politics department at Copenhagen Business School for their unwavering intellectual and material hospitality; and the anonymous reviewers for engaging so deeply with this text.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Andreas Philippopoulos-Mihalopoulos.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Philippopoulos-Mihalopoulos, A. Critical Autopoiesis and the Materiality of Law. Int J Semiot Law 27, 389–418 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11196-013-9328-7

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11196-013-9328-7

Keywords

Navigation