Skip to main content
Log in

Autonomy, Liberalism, and Anti-Perfectionism

  • Published:
Res Publica Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

John Christman has recently objected to substantive conceptions of autonomy on the grounds that they introduce unwanted perfectionism into political thinking. I defend substantive conceptions of autonomy against Christman’s critique on two fronts. First, I defend substantive conceptions of autonomy against the charge that their utilisation in political theory would result in the inappropriate exclusion from democratic respect of individuals in oppressive relations. Second, I defend substantive conceptions of autonomy from the charge that they fail the ‘endorsement constraint’, i.e. that incorporating a substantive conception of autonomy into the concept of the person at the heart of a political theory would be alienating for citizens.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. C.f. Nussbaum (2011). One of the most common examples of a perfectionist liberalism is Raz (1986).

  2. This is not to say that I contest the broader claims Christman (2009) develops, such as his socio-historical model of the self, or his vision of democratic justice. Neither should it be taken as a defence of substantive theories of autonomy per se. My goal in this paper is solely to show that Christman’s arguments for rejecting substantive theories of autonomy are unsuccessful.

  3. For related theories which restrict the content of autonomous agents’ beliefs or values, see Charles (2010) and Kristinsson (2000).

  4. Christman does not engage with the recent suggestion by Benson (2005) that a middle way can be found through ‘weakly substantive’ views. Since such views still incorporate restrictions on the content of an agent’s beliefs or values, I will be assuming that Christman would object to such views on the same grounds as for strongly substantive accounts.

  5. It may be noted that the overarching problem of excluding non-autonomous persons from the political realm will remain despite with this solution. This is the kind of objection that Nussbaum (2006) has raised against social contract theories in general, with respect to the severely disabled. Such problems are beyond the scope of this paper.

  6. It should be noted, though, that not all feminist accounts of autonomy are substantive (e.g. Friedman 2003), and likewise not all substantive accounts are explicitly feminist (e.g. Wolf 1993).

  7. Specifying which social conditions compromise autonomy will inevitably be a controversial undertaking, as will the related task of determining an appropriate political response to those conditions. For liberals of all stripes, there will be a justificatory gap between identifying a practice as autonomy-undermining and restricting that practice.

  8. I discuss a similar problem, and suggest a similar solution, with respect to the concept of dignity (see Killmister 2010). Thanks to Sally Haslanger for useful discussion on this point.

  9. Mackenzie (2008, p. 523) makes a similar observation regarding the inevitability of exclusion on Christman’s own account. Indeed, it is plausible that the exclusions required by Christman’s account will be even more substantial than those required by some substantive accounts. According to Christman (2005a, pp. 348–349), a citizen cannot make a value claim as part of the deliberative process unless that claim meets two conditions: (1) there is an inferential relationship between the value and the agent’s other beliefs and values; (2) those values are expressed consistently. Compared, say, to Paul Benson’s recent condition that the agent take herself to be authorised to speak for her actions, Christman’s account appears significantly more stringent, and would thus exclude more individuals from the deliberative process.

  10. Dianna Meyers (1989) was influential in bringing about this shift in perspective.

  11. It is important not to follow the common assumption that proceduralist theories as a rule are less demanding than substantive theories. For a convincing rebuttal of this assumption, see Schwartz (2005).

  12. One further point is worth stressing. In this paper I defend substantive accounts of autonomy such as Stoljar’s and Oshana’s from Christman’s objections. This should not be taken to mean that I believe such conceptions to be the best accounts of autonomy available, or even that such conceptions are ultimately compatible with political liberalism. What I seek do here is simply show that Christman’s objection do not suffice to rule out substantive accounts, as a class, from the perspective of political liberalism.

  13. It should be stressed here that this reflexive use of legitimacy is not necessarily shared by other political liberals. Legitimacy could also be justified in terms of respect for persons, where that is taken to be a value that is prior to (and justifies) the search for overlapping consensus, rather than being subject to overlapping consensus. Thanks to two anonymous reviewers for this journal for pushing me on this point.

  14. As an anonymous reviewer for this journal has pointed out, Christman’s version of political liberalism is not necessarily shared by others who adopt this label.

  15. Estlund (1998) makes a similar point with respect to Rawls’ use of the reasonable.

References

  • Benson, Paul. 2005. Feminist intuitions and the normative substance of autonomy. In Personal autonomy: New essays on personal autonomy and its role in contemporary moral philosophy, ed. James Stacey Taylor, 124–142. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Bratman, Michael. 2000. Reflection, planning, and temporally extended agency. The Philosophical Review 109: 35–61.

    Google Scholar 

  • Charles, Sonya. 2010. How should feminist autonomy theorists respond to the problem of internalized oppression? Social Theory and Practice 36: 409–428.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Christman, John. 1991. Autonomy and personal history. Canadian Journal of Philosophy 21: 1–24.

    Google Scholar 

  • Christman, John. 2004. Relational autonomy, liberal individualism, and the social constitution of selves. Philosophical Studies 117: 143–164.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Christman, John. 2005a. Autonomy, self-knowledge, and liberal legitimacy. In Autonomy and the challenges to liberalism: New essays, ed. John Christman, and Joel Anderson, 330–357. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Christman, John. 2005b. Procedural autonomy and liberal legitimacy. In Personal autonomy: New essays on personal autonomy and its role in contemporary moral philosopy, ed. James Stacey Taylor, 277–298. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Christman, John. 2009. The politics of persons: Individual autonomy and socio-historical selves. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ekstrom, Laura. 1993. A coherence theory of autonomy. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 53: 599–616.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Estlund, David. 1998. The insularity of the reasonable: Why political liberalism must admit the truth. Ethics 108: 252–275.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frankfurt, Harry. 1971. Freedom of the will and the concept of a person. The Journal of Philosophy 68: 5–20.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frankfurt, Harry. 1988. The importance of what we care about. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, Marilyn. 2003. Autonomy, gender, politics. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Killmister, Suzy. 2010. Dignity: Not such a useless concept. Journal of Medical Ethics 36: 160–164.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kristinsson, Sigurdur. 2000. The limits of neutrality: Toward a weakly substantive account of autonomy. Canadian Journal of Philosophy 30: 257–286.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mackenzie, Catriona. 2008. Relational autonomy, normative authority and perfectionism. Journal of Social Philosophy 39: 512–533.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mackenzie, Catriona, and Natalie Stoljar. 2000. Relational autonomy: Feminist perspectives on automony, agency, and the social self. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Meyers, Diana Tietjens. 1989. Self, society, and personal choice. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum, Martha. 1992. Human functioning and social justice: In defense of aristotelian essentialism. Political Theory 20: 202–246.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum, Martha. 2000. Women and human development: The capabilities approach. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum, Martha. 2006. Frontiers of justice: Disability, nationality, species membership. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum, Martha. 2011. Perfectionist liberalism and political liberalism. Philosophy & Public Affairs 39: 3–45.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Oshana, Marina. 1998. Personal autonomy and society. Journal of Social Philosophy 29: 81–102.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, John. 2005. Political liberalism. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Raz, Joseph. 1986. The morality of freedom. New York: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schwartz, Andrew W. 2005. Autonomy and oppression: Beyond the substantive and content-neutral debate. The Journal of Value Inquiry 39: 443–457.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stoljar, Natalie. 2000. Autonomy and the feminist intuition. In Relational autonomy: Feminist perspectives on autonomy, agency, and the social self, ed. Catriona Mackenzie, and Natalie Stoljar, 94–111. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wolf, Susan. 1993. Freedom within reason. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I would like to thanktwo anonymous referees for this journal, as well as participants in the Workshop on Gender and Philosophy at MIT, and the Mentoring Project at UMass, for helpful feedback on earlier drafts.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Suzy Killmister.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Killmister, S. Autonomy, Liberalism, and Anti-Perfectionism. Res Publica 19, 353–369 (2013). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11158-013-9229-3

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11158-013-9229-3

Keywords

Navigation