Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Adorno, Freedom and Criminal Law: The ‘Determinist Challenge’ Revitalised

  • Published:
Law and Critique Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This article argues—against the present compatibilist orthodoxy in the philosophy of criminal law—for the contemporary relevance of a kind of critique of criminal law known as the ‘determinist challenge’, through a reconstruction of Theodor Adorno’s thought on freedom and determinism. The article begins by considering traditional forms of the determinist challenge, which expressed a widespread intuition that it is irrational or inappropriate for the criminal law to hold people responsible for actions that are causally determined by social and psychological forces in such a way that they cannot be said to have acted freely. Yet as traditionally presented it was possible for its opponents to interpret this challenge as an incompatibilist position within the traditional free will/determinism debate, and to present compatibilist arguments against it—in particular, that the determinist challenge is unmotivated and has implausible implications. It is argued that these compatibilist objections hold only on a certain interpretation of the determinist challenge, but that this interpretation is not the only one available. Adorno’s distinctive position on freedom and determinism is presented as an alternative version of the challenge, which cannot be assimilated to the terms of the traditional compatibilist/incompatibilist disputes. This novel, ‘metacritical’ version of the determinist challenge is essentially a social–historical, not metaphysical, thesis about the moral significance of the freedom-undermining effects of modern social forms. As such, it is argued, it is invulnerable to the usual compatibilist objections, and presents a serious challenge to our criminal legal institutions.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Even ‘hard incompatibilists’ like Pereboom (2014) accept the premise.

  2. Adorno is often cited by critical legal theorists (Kelman 1987; Cornell 1993; Cotterrell 1995; Douzinas 2000; Bowring 2002), but rarely receives more than passing mention (one exception is Norrie 2005, ch. 9); in the Adorno literature, issues of criminal justice are again only addressed occasionally and briefly (e.g. Freyenhagen 2013, pp. 95–100).

  3. This is admittedly a controversial interpretation of Adorno. I first began to explore it in my article (Reeves 2009a).

  4. For an instructive recent discussion see Hinshelwood (2013).

  5. Jutten is, in my view, too quick to defend Kant against Adorno on this issue (2010, pp. 561–564).

  6. For discussion see Freyenhagen 2013, pp. 255–270.

  7. On the thought of the space of life being a distinctive metaphysical space, see Thompson (2008).

  8. Steward’s argument that agency is proper to animal life generally (2012, Ch. 4) lends support to Adorno’s thought here.

  9. C.f. Freyenhagen (2013, pp. 266–270), who sees that Adorno rejects the causal theory of action, but remains non-committal over Adorno’s stance regarding the positivistic metaphysics of event-causalism that underpins and motivates it.

  10. For a detailed discussion of this claim, see Freyenhagen 2013.

  11. As contemporary constructivist Kantians tend to put it (e.g. Korsgaard 1996).

  12. See Wiggins (2008).

  13. The thought is already there in Freud (1961), but has been corroborated by the now vast bodies of research in the object relations and attachment traditions.

  14. The translation is Freyenhagen’s (2013, p. 76).

  15. See also Cook (2011), pp. 55–57; O’Connor (2013).

References

  • Adorno, Theodor. 1973. Negative dialectics. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Adorno, Theodor. 1974. Minima moralia. London: New Left Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Adorno, Theodor. 1993. Hegel: Three studies. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Adorno, Theodor. 2000. Problems of moral philosophy. Cambridge: Polity.

    Google Scholar 

  • Adorno, Theodor. 2005. Critical models. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Adorno, Theodor. 2006a. History and freedom. Cambridge: Polity.

    Google Scholar 

  • Adorno, Theodor. 2006b. The idea of natural-history. In Things beyond resemblance, ed. Robert Hullot-Kentor. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Anscombe, Elizabeth. 1981. Causality and determination. In Metaphysics and the philosophy of mind. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

  • Aristotle. 1986. De Anima. In H. Lawson-Tancred (ed. and trans.). London: Penguin.

  • Austin, John L. 1956. A plea for excuses. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 57: 1–30.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bhaskar, Roy. 1975. A realist theory of science. Brighton: Harvester Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bowring, Bill. 2002. Book Review, Punishment, responsibility and justice by Alan Norrie. Journal of Law and Society 29(3): 521–527.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright, Nancy. 1999. The dappled world. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Chitty, Andrew. 1993. The early Marx on needs. Radical Philosophy 64.

  • Cook, Deborah. 2011. Adorno on nature. Durham: Acumen.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cornell, Drucilla. 1993. Transformations. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cotterrell, Roger. 1995. Law’s community. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dews, Peter. 2008. The idea of evil. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Douzinas, Costas. 2000. The end of human rights. Oxford: Hart.

    Google Scholar 

  • Duff, R.A. 1993. Choice, character and criminal liability. Law and Philosophy 12(4): 345–383.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Duff, R.A. 2007. Answering for crime. Oxford: Hart.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ellis, Brian. 2001. Scientific essentialism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ellis, Brian. 2013. The Power of Agency. In Powers and capacities in philosophy: The New Aristotelianism, ed. Ruth Groff, and John Greco. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Freud, Sigmund. 1961. The ego and the id. In J. Strachey (ed. and trans.) The standard edition of the complete psychological works of Sigmund Freud (Vol. 19, pp. 3–66). London: Hogarth Press.

  • Freyenhagen, Fabian. 2008. Moral philosophy. In Adorno: Key concepts, ed. D. Cook. Acumen: Stocksfield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Freyenhagen, Fabian. 2013. Adorno’s practical philosophy: Living less wrongly. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gardner, John. 1998. On the general part of the criminal law. In Philosophy and the criminal law, ed. R.A. Duff. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Groff, Ruth. 2004. Critical realism, post-positivism and the possibility of knowledge. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Groff, Ruth. 2013. Ontology revisited. Abingdon: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Groff, Ruth, and John Greco (eds.). 2013. Powers and capacities in philosophy: The New Aristotelianism. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harre, Rom, and E.H. Madden. 1975. Causal powers. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hinshelwood, Alec. 2013. The relations between agency, identification and alienation. Philosophical Explorations 16(3): 243–258.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Horder, Jeremy. 1996. Criminal law: Between determinism, liberalism and criminal justice. Current Legal Problems 49(1): 159–186.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Horder, Jeremy. 2004. Excusing crime. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Horkheimer, Max, and Theodor Adorno. 2002. Dialectic of enlightenment (trans: Jephcott, E.). Stanford: Stanford University Press.

  • Jutten, Timo. 2010. Adorno on Kant, freedom and determinism. European Journal of Philosophy 20(4): 548–574.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kant, Immanuel. 1929. Critique of pure reason (trans: Smith, Kemp). London: MacMillan.

  • Kant, Immanuel. 1993. Critique of practical reason (trans: Beck, White). New Jersey: Prentice-Hall.

  • Kelman, Mark. 1987. A guide to critical legal studies. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Korsgaard, Christine. 1996. The sources of normativity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Lacey, Nicola. 2001. Responsibility and modernity in criminal law. Journal of Political Philosophy 9(3): 249–276.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lear, Jonathon. 2014. Integrating the non-rational soul. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 114(1.1): 75–101.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lowe, Edward J. 1998. The possibility of metaphysics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lowe, Edward J. 2006. The four-category ontology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lowe, Edward J. 2008. Personal agency. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lowe, Edward J. 2013. The will as a rational free power. In Powers and capacities in philosophy: The New Aristotelianism, ed. Ruth Groff, and John Greco. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mackie, J.L. 1977. Ethics: Inventing right and wrong. London: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marx, Karl. 1992. Early writings. London: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mayr, Erasmus. 2011. Understanding human agency. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Moore, Michael. 1997. Placing blame. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Morris, Herbert. 1976. On guilt and innocence: Essays in legal philosophy and moral psychology. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Morse, Stephen. 2007. The non-problem of free will in forensic psychiatry and psychology. Behavioural Sciences and the Law 25: 203–220.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morse, Stephen. 2008. Determinism and the death of folk psychology: Two challenges to responsibility from neuroscience. Faculty Scholarship. Paper 531. http://scholarship.law.upenn.edu/faculty_scholarship/531.

  • Mumford, Stephen. 1998. Dispositions. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Murphy, Jeffrie. 1979. Retribution, justice and therapy. Dordrecht: D. Reidel Publishing.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Norrie, Alan. 1991. Law, punishment and ideology. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Norrie, Alan. 2000. Punishment, responsibility and justice. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Norrie, Alan. 2005. Law and the beautiful soul. London: Glasshouse.

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Connor, Brian. 2005. Adorno’s negative dialectic. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Connor, Brian. 2013. Freedom within nature: Adorno on the idea of reason’s autonomy. In The impact of idealism: The legacy of post-Kantian German thought, ed. N. Boyle, et al. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pereboom, Derk. 2014. Free will, agency and meaning in life. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Reeves, Craig. 2009a. Causality and critical theory: Nature’s order in Adorno, Cartwright and Bhaskar. Journal of Critical Realism 8(3): 316–342.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reeves, Craig. 2009b. ‘Exploding the limits of law': Judgment and freedom in Arendt and Adorno. Res Publica 15(2): 137–164.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Steward, Helen. 2012. A metaphysics for freedom. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Strawson, Peter. 1962. Freedom and resentment. Proceedings of the British Academy 48: 1–25. (Reprinted in Fischer and Ravizza 1993).

  • Tadros, Victor. 2005. Criminal responsibility. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tadros, Victor. 2009. Poverty and criminal responsibility. Journal of Value Inquiry 43: 391–413.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, R. 1973. Action and purpose. New Jersey: Humanities Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, Michael. 2008. Life and action. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Velleman, David. 1992. What happens when someone acts? Mind 101: 461–481. (Reprinted in Fischerand Ravizza 1993).

  • Wallace, R. Jay. 1994. Responsibility and the moral sentiments. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wellmer, Albrecht. 1998. Endgames. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Westen, Peter. 2005. Getting the fly out of the bottle: The false problem of free will and determinism. Buffalo Criminal Law Review 8: 599–652.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Whitebook, Joel. 1995. Perversion and utopia. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Whitebook, Joel. 2004. Weighty objects. In The Cambridge companion to Adorno, ed. T. Huhn. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wiggins, David. 2008. Solidarity and the root of the ethical. The Lindley Lecture, University of Kansas.

Download references

Acknowledgments

I would like to express my gratitude to the following friends and colleagues who read and commented on earlier drafts, for their invaluable criticism, advice and encouragement: Peter Ramsay, Henrique Carvalho, Alan Norrie, Liat Levanon, Jaakko Immonen, Daniella Lock, and Alec Hinshelwood. I also thank the editors and reviewers for Law and Critique for their helpful comments.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Craig Reeves.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Reeves, C. Adorno, Freedom and Criminal Law: The ‘Determinist Challenge’ Revitalised. Law Critique 27, 323–348 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10978-015-9171-y

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10978-015-9171-y

Keywords

Navigation