Skip to main content
Log in

Deflationism and the Dependence of Truth on Reality

  • Original Article
  • Published:
Erkenntnis Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

A common objection against deflationism is that it cannot account for the fact that truth depends on reality. Consider the question ‘On what does the truth of the proposition that snow is white depend?’ An obvious answer is that it depends on whether snow is white. Now, consider what answer, if any, a deflationist can offer. The problem is as follows. A typical deflationary analysis of truth consists of biconditionals of the form ‘The proposition that p is true iff p’. Such biconditionals tell us nothing about what the truth of the proposition that p might depend on. Therefore, it seems that a typical deflationist cannot give an answer. Since we know that an answer is available, this throws doubt over the adequacy of deflationism as an account of truth. Articulated here is a defence of deflationism against this objection. It is argued that although biconditionals of the sort mentioned do not explicitly state a dependency between truth and reality, they nevertheless convey one. The reason is that, given the context in which a deflationist invokes the biconditionals, such a dependency is implicated. A potential problem with this defence is that it leaves the deflationist still unable to give an account of what it is for truth to depend on reality. One might think that a deflationist can offer such an account by appealing to truthmaker theory but, it is argued below, truthmaker theory is unavailable to a deflationist. Instead, the deflationist should question the assumption that an account is available.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Angle-brackets denote propositions. The instances of E are typically restricted to those that do not give rise to paradox, and supplemented by the extra axiom ‘(For all x)(x is true → x is a proposition)’ (e.g. Horwich 1998, pp. 40–42 and p. 23, fn. 7). For ease of expression, I won’t repeat this in the rest of this paper.

  2. See, for instance, Horwich 1998, pp. 2–5 and Williams 2002, p. 148.

  3. I do not mean to imply that such an explanation consists merely of the instances of E. Indeed, in the following example one must also introduce a quantifier to obtain ‘Every proposition of the form <Everything is F or not F> is true’. The point is that the explanation does not require a substantive theory of truth.

  4. For instance, Davidson argues that truth has a role in explaining meaningfulness, and Putnam argues that truth has a causal role (Davidson 1996; Putnam 1978, pp. 100–103).

  5. Vision 2005 and Newman 2002, pp. 34–37 are examples of those who raise this objection; Hill 2002, Horwich 1998, Chap. 7 and McGrath 2003 are examples of those who defend deflationism against it.

  6. For a more formal treatment of the dependence of truth (particularly in relation to the semantic paradoxes) see Yablo 1982; Leitgeb 2005; and Fine 2010. I am grateful to an anonymous referee for bringing these papers to my attention.

  7. A similar line of reasoning is found in Rodriguez-Pereyra 2005, p. 27 and Künne 2003, p. 152.

  8. Künne articulates this criticism of Quine on p. 152 of his 2003. See also Vision 2005, pp. 366–367.

  9. The reason is as follows. Jack has articulated a conditional (i.e. the conditional ‘If Fred gives money away then there’s something in it for him’), and a true conditional does not guarantee a dependency between the antecedent and consequent (e.g. ‘If Fred gives money away then 2 + 2 = 4’ is true, but 2 + 2 equalling 4 does not depend on Fred giving money away). If a true conditional does not guarantee a dependency between the antecedent and consequent, it cannot be the case that in articulating a conditional one says that there is such a dependency. Similarly for biconditionals.

  10. The other conditions are twofold. The first is that the speaker is presumed to be observing the conversational maxims. The second concerns the supposition that q is required to make a’s saying that p consistent with the presumption that a is observing the conversational maxims: it is the condition that “the speaker thinks (and would expect the hearer to think that the speaker thinks) that it is within the competence of the hearer to work out, or grasp intuitively, that the supposition [mentioned at the beginning of this sentence] is required.” (Grice 1975, pp. 30–31).

  11. Although all three scenarios above involve spoken conversations, this is not necessary for an implicature to be generated. Grice himself gives the example of a testimonial written about a student who is a candidate for a philosophy job. In virtue of the fact that the writer purposely flouts the maxim ‘quantity’, he manages to implicate what he is unwilling to write down. (Ibid. p. 33).

  12. One might wonder what sort of dependency is implicated here. What can be said is that the implicated dependency between the truth of <Snow is white> and snow’s being white is such that the latter explains the former (in this sense, one could term it an ‘explanatory dependency’). This is unsurprising, because the response ‘Well, <Snow is white> is true just in case snow is white’ is uttered in the context of a request for an explanation of the truth of <Snow is white>. (Similarly for the implicated dependency between Fred’s giving money away and there being something in it for him; and between the Royal Standard’s flying from Victoria Tower and the Monarch’s being present in the Palace of Westminster.).

  13. For instance, ‘<Snow is white> is true iff snow is white’ is offered in the context of an explanation of the truth of <Snow is white>, not in the context of an explanation of snow’s being white.

  14. In light of this, it ought to be agreed that there is a sense in which it is incompatible with TD that truth does not depend on reality. Kent Bach distinguishes between the semantic content of a sentence and the content of an utterance of that sentence (2005, pp. 9–11). The truth-value of the former does not depend on the truth-value of any implicatures, but the truth-value of the latter does. Thus, for instance, although it is consistent with the content of ‘I saw Bill with a woman’ that the woman in question was his wife, it can still be incompatible with the content of an utterance of that sentence (if, say, that content includes the implicature that the woman was not his wife). Similarly, one can distinguish between the semantic content of (2), and what is conveyed when (2) is taken in the context of an explanation of truth. Since the latter includes the implicature that the truth of <Snow is white> depends on whether snow is white, in this sense it is incompatible with TD that the truth of <Snow is white> does not depend on reality.

  15. See, for instance, Rodriguez-Pereyra 2005, p. 27.

  16. For an example of a deflationist complaining about the tendency to use too many ontological resources in analysing truth, see Quine: facts “are projected from true sentences for the sake of correspondence” (1987, p. 213). See also David on the deflationists' attitude towards the conceptual resources employed by the correspondence theory of truth: “…the deflationist will charge that the notion of correspondence … is also a fabrication—that it has been invented for the sole purpose of binding the invented facts to the true sentences” (1994, p. 24).

  17. See, for instance, Horwich 1998, pp. 1–5.

  18. Liggins also questions why one must suppose that there is such an account (2008, p. 188 fn. 9).

References

  • Bach, K. (2005). The top 10 misconceptions about implicature. In B. Birner & G. Ward (Eds.), Festschrift for Larry Horn. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.

    Google Scholar 

  • David, M. (1994). Correspondence and disquotation: An essay on the nature of truth. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1996). The folly of trying to define truth. Journal of Philosophy, 93, 263–278.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fine, K. (2010). Some puzzles of ground. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 51, 97–118.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grice, H. P. (1975). Logic and conversation. In H. P. Grice (Ed.), Studies in the ways of words. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Reprinted.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hill, C. (2002). The marriage of heaven and hell: Reconciling deflationary semantics with correspondence intuitions. Philosophical Studies, 104, 291–321.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Horwich, P. (1998). Truth (2nd ed.). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Künne, W. (2003). Conceptions of truth. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Leitgeb, H. (2005). What truth depends on. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 34, 155–192.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (2001). Forget about the correspondence theory of truth. Analysis, 61, 275–280.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Liggins, D. (2008). Truthmakers and the groundedness of truth. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 108, 177–196.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McGrath, M. (2003). What the deflationist may say about truthmaking. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 66, 666–688.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Newman, A. (2002). The correspondence theory of truth. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1978). Meaning and the moral sciences. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. V. O. (1970). Philosophy of logic. Hemel Hempstead: Prentice-Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. V. O. (1987). Quiddities: An intermittently philosophical dictionary. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rodriguez-Pereyra, G. (2005). Why truthmakers. In J. Dodd & H. Beebee (Eds.), Truthmakers. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tarski, A. (1944). The semantic conception of truth. In M. Lynch (Ed.), The nature of truth. MIT: Cambridge, MA. Reprinted.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vision, G. (2005). Deflationary truthmaking. European Journal of Philosophy, 13, 364–380.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williams, M. (2002). On some critics of deflationism. In R. Schantz (Ed.), What is truth? Berlin: Walter de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yablo, S. (1982). Grounding, dependence, and paradox. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 11, 117–137.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

Thanks to David Liggins, Rosanna Keefe and two anonymous referees for helpful comments.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Andrew Thomas.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Thomas, A. Deflationism and the Dependence of Truth on Reality. Erkenn 75, 113–122 (2011). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-011-9277-z

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-011-9277-z

Keywords

Navigation