Skip to main content
Log in

Antecapere ergo sum: what price knowledge?

  • 25th Anniversary Volume A Faustian Exchange: What is to be human in the era of Ubiquitous Technology?
  • Published:
AI & SOCIETY Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In the age of ubiquitous technology, humans are reshaped through each transaction they are involved in. AI-driven networks, online games, and multisensory interactive environments make up alternate realities. Within such alternate worlds, users are reshaped as deterministic agents. Technology’s focus on reducing complexity leads to a human being dependent on prediction-driven machines and behaving like them. Meaning and information are disconnected. Existence is reduced to energy processes. The immense gain in efficiency translates as prosperity. Citizens of advanced economies, hurrying in the rhythm of machine-driven interactions, feel entitled to it. Successful at the price of self-awareness, they no longer know what this means. Happiness and prosperity are not consubstantial. Lack of happiness leads to aggression. This is the image of the world as we see it, no longer looking at each other, eye to eye, but screen to screen. The questions eliminated in the process of transferring responsibility from the individual to machines will inevitably become society’s new focus. When the goal is to get everyone to behave like a machine, the Singularity hypothesis becomes self-fulfilling prophecy. If, in addition to having exhausted natural resources, society does not want to end up making the human mind superfluous, it has to seek a better understanding of what makes anticipation possible. As a definitory characteristic of the living, corresponding to its complexity, anticipation can no longer be taken for granted, while every effort is made to reduce complexity for efficiency’s sake. Awareness of the processes conducive to its expression in successful human action will position human beings as masters of their destiny, not slaves of their own making. Antecapere ergo sum might be the counterclaim to Descartes’ Dubito ergo sum. To resist being perfected into oblivion, that is, unsustainable prosperity, means to reclaim the knowledge corresponding to higher levels of complexity.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Bacon F (1620) Novum organum (the new organon) Book 1, aphorism 95 [online]. Available at: http://www.constitution.org/bacon/nov_org.htm. Accessed 16 May 2011

  • Bateson G (2000) Steps to an ecology of mind: collected essays on anthropology, psychiatry, evolution, and epistemology. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Bostrom N (2003) Are you living a computer simulation? Philos Q 53(211):243–255 http://www.simulation-argument.com/simulation.html

  • Clark A (2008) Supersizing the mind: embodiment, action, and cognitive extension. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Davies CWP (2004) John Archibald Wheeler and the clash of ideas. In: Barrow JD, Davies CWP, Harper CL (eds) Science and ultimate reality. Cambridge University Press, London, pp 3–24

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Del Rio L, Aberg J, Renner R, Dahlsten O, Vedral V (2011) The thermodynamic meaning of negative entropy. Nature 474(7349):61–63

    Google Scholar 

  • Deutsch D (1985) Quantum theory, the Church-Turing principle and the universal quantum computer. Proc R Soc Lond Series A, Math Phys Sci 400(1818):97–117

  • Deutsch D (2001) The structure of the multiverse. Proc R Soc A458(2028):2911–2923

    MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Deutsch D (2005) Our place in the cosmos [online, posted September 2006]. Lecture, TED Global 2005. http://www.ted.com/talks/david_deutsch_on_our_place_in_the_cosmos.html

  • Deutsch D, Barenco A, Ekert A (1995) Universality in quantum computation. In: Proceedings: mathematical and physical sciences (8 June) 449:1937, Royal Society Publishing, London, pp 669–677

  • Everett H (1957) Relative state formulation of quantum mechanics. Rev Mod Phys 29:454–462 (Reprinted in DeWitt BS and Graham N (1973) The many worlds interpretation of quantum mechanics. Princeton University Press, Princeton)

  • Gödel K (1931) Über formal unenscheidbare sätze der Principa Mathematica und verwandte systeme, Monatshefte für Mathematik und Physik 38:173–198. (The first incompleteness theorem originally appeared as Theorem VI, 1931)

  • Jaynes ET (1957) Information theory and statistical mechanics. Phys Rev 106(4):620–630

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Kauffman S (2004) Autonomous agents. In: Barrow JD, Davies PCW, Harper CL Jr (eds) Science and ultimate reality: quantum theory, cosmology, and complexity. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelly K (2002) God is the machine, Wired 10.12, December [online] http://www.wired.com/wired/archive/10.12/holytech.html. Accessed 15 May 2011

  • Kurzweil R (2005) The singularity is near. Viking, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • MacKay D (1969) Information, mechanism and meaning. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Mitchell M (2002) Is the universe a universal computer? Science 298(5591):65–68

    Google Scholar 

  • Nadin M (1991) Mind—anticipation and chaos. Belser Presse, Stuttgart

    Google Scholar 

  • Nadin M (2009) Anticipation and the artificial. Aesthetics, ethics, and synthetic life. Special issue on ethics and aesthetics of technologies—AI & Society (computer science). Springer, London, pp 103–118

  • Nadin M (2010a) Anticipation and dynamics: Rosen’s anticipation in the perspective of time. (Special issue) International Journal of General Systems 39:1 Taylor and Blackwell, London, pp 3–33

  • Nadin M (2010b) Anticipatory computing: from a high-level theory to hybrid computing implementations. Int J Appl Res Inf Technol Comput (IJARITAC) 1(1):1–27

    Google Scholar 

  • Nadin M (2011a) Information and semiotic processes. The semiotics of computation. In: Pearson C, Brier S (eds) Cybernetics and human knowing. A journal of second-order cybernetics, autopoiesis and cyber-semiotics, 18:1–2, pp 153–175

  • Nadin M (2011b) Computation, information, meaning. anticipation and games. Int J Appl Res Inf Tech Comput (IJARITAC) 2(4):1–26

    Google Scholar 

  • Nicolelis MAL, Shuler M (2001) Thalamocortical and corticocortical interactions in the somatosensory system. In: Nicolelis MAL (ed) Advances in neural population coding. Progress in brain research, 130, Elsevier Science, Amsterdam, pp 89–110

  • Prescott M (2010) Everything is a program [online] michaelprescott.typepad.com/michael_prescotts_blog/2010/08/getting-to-the-bottom-of-things.html. Accessed 16 June 2011

  • Putnam H (1960) Minds and machines. In: Hook S (ed) Dimensions of mind: a symposium. New York University Press, New York. (Reprinted (1964) In: Anderson AR (ed) Minds and machines. Prentice-Hall, Englewood Cliffs pp 43–59)

  • Pylyshyn Z (1980) The “causal power” of machines. Behav Brain Sci 3:442–444

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rosen R (1985) Organisms as causal systems which are not mechanisms: an essay into the nature of complexity. In: Rosen R (ed) Theoretical biology and complexity: three essays into the natural philosophy of complex systems. Academic Press, Orlando, pp 165–203

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosen R (1988) Prologue. In: Kelso JAS, Mandell AJ, Shlesinger MF (eds) Dynamic patterns in complex systems. World Scientific, Singapore, pp 3–70

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosen R (1991) Life itself. Columbia University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Rucker R (2005) The lifebox, the seashell, and the soul: what gnarly computation taught me about ultimate reality, the meaning of life, and how to be happy. Thunder’s Mouth Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Rucker R (2008) Everything is alive. Progress of theoretical physics supplement 173:363–370

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sokurov A (2011) Faust. Winner of the Golden Lion Award at the 68th Venice International Film Festival

  • Specter M (2011) Test-tube burgers, The New Yorker, pp 32–38, 23 May

  • Turkle S (2011) Alone together: why we expect more from technology and less from each other. Basic Books, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Vinge V (1993) The coming technological singularity, Vision-21: interdisciplinary science & engineering in the era of cyberspace.In: Proceedings of a symposium held at NASA Lewis Research Center (NASA Conference Publication CP-10129) http://www-rohan.sdsu.edu/faculty/vinge/misc/singularity.html. Accessed 3 June 2011

  • Von Helmholtz H (1878) The facts in perception. In: Ewald WB (ed) From Kant to Hilbert: a source book in the foundations of mathematics, vol 2. Oxford University Press, Cambridge 1996, pp 698–726

  • Weizenbaum J (1976) Computer power and human reason: from judgment to calculation. W. H. Freeman, San Francisco

    Google Scholar 

  • Wolfram S (2002) A new kind of science. Wolfram Media, Champaign

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Zuse K (1969) Rechnender Raum. Friedrich Vieweg & Sohn, Braunschweig. English: calculating space, an MIT Technical Translation Project MAC, MIT, 1970, AZTEC School of Languages, Inc., Cambridge

Download references

Acknowledgments

In some ways, my first meeting with Joseph Weizenbaum (Interface—Multimediale, Hamburg 1993) was the beginning of this article. Our views on the “digital age” were quite different, but our respective assessments of the impact of the digital on the human being were congruent. Over time, Heinz von Foerster (whom I met on the same occasion), Terry Winograd, Lotfi Zadeh, E.D. Hirsch, Jr., Wolfgang Coy, Hans-Jörg Kreowski, and Solomon Marcus offered me the opportunity to continue the dialog. Even Steven Wolfram agreed to disagree with me on matters of anticipation. Finally, Karamjit Gill gave me the opportunity to put my thoughts, accumulated over some time, to paper. Mike Cooley and Larry Stapleton, the peers who reviewed my paper, thought that it deserves the readers’ attention. I owe them my gratitude for suggesting improvements. Of course, antÉ—Institute for Research in Anticipatory Systems at the University of Texas at Dallas and my current host, the Hanse Institute for Advanced Studies, deserve credit for facilitating the work, as does Elvira Nadin, my right hand and my heart. Christian Freksa and Otthein Herzog are my research partners at the Institute, while Reto Weiler and Dorothe Poggel do their best to support my endeavors. For whatever the reader might find fault with, I stand and remain willing to learn from others (and to correct myself as necessary).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Mihai Nadin.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Nadin, M. Antecapere ergo sum: what price knowledge?. AI & Soc 28, 39–50 (2013). https://doi.org/10.1007/s00146-012-0400-8

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s00146-012-0400-8

Keywords

Navigation