Skip to main content

Application and the Act of Reading

  • Chapter
The Concept of Literary Application
  • 137 Accesses

Abstract

In the previous two chapters, I described the act of application and compared or contrasted it with some other actions or processes thought to occur when literature is read and experienced. In this chapter, I look more closely at the act of reading as a whole and attempt to explain how application enters into that more comprehensive context.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. Simon Garrod and Meredyth Daneman, “Reading, Psychology of”, in Encyclopedia of Cognitive Science, ed.-in-chief Lynn Nadel, vol. 3 (London, New York, and Tokyo: Nature Publishing Group, 2003), pp. 848–54; here, p. 848.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Jhumpa Lahiri, “Unaccustomed Earth”, in Lahiri’s Unaccustomed Earth (New York and Toronto: Alfred A. Knopf, 2008), pp. 3–59 (at p. 3).

    Google Scholar 

  3. Teun A. van Dijk and Walter Kintsch, Strategies of Discourse Comprehension (San Diego: Academic Press, 1983), pp. 11–12.

    Google Scholar 

  4. The term and the concept are still current in the psychology of reading; see, e.g., Isabelle Tapiero, Situation Models and Levels of Coherence: Toward a Definition of Comprehension (Mahwah, N.J. and London: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, 2007), esp. chapter 2.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Nadine Gordimer, The Pickup (New York: Farrar, Straus and Giroux, 2001), p. 3.

    Google Scholar 

  6. See, e.g., Susan Lanser’s sophisticated account of the phenomenon: Susan Sniader Lanser, The Narrative Act: Point of View in Prose Fiction (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1981).

    Google Scholar 

  7. The idea of a discourse mode is related to the pragmatic notion of an illocutionary force. Just as a one-sentence utterance can be said to have a certain illocutionary force according to classical speech-act theory, a whole discourse can be said to have a certain global illocutionary force, and the global illocutionary force would be a central constituent of the discourse mode. It is true that the idea of global illocutionary force has never become popular within linguistic pragmatics. It was introduced, or at least considered, by van Dijk in the late 1970s and early 1980s — see his “Pragmatics and Poetics”, in Pragmatics of Language and Literature, ed. Teun A. van Dijk (Amsterdam: North-Holland, 1976), pp. 23–57 (at p. 36) and his Studies in the Pragmatics of Discourse (The Hague, Paris, and New York: Mouton, 1981), p. 254. However, I can find no references to pragmatic force at the discourse level in a work like The Handbook of Pragmatics, ed. Laurence R. Horn and Gregory Ward (Malden, Mass.: Blackwell, 2004). As I describe a discourse mode, it is, nevertheless, something richer and more individualized than a standard illocutionary force. It comes close to what I have elsewhere called a “communicational genre” and exemplified with Bachtin’s speech genres and genres in the sense described by E.D. Hirsch; see my article “Conclusion: A Pragmatic Perspective on Genres and Theories of Genre”, in Literary Genres: An Intercultural Approach, ed. Gunilla Lindberg-Wada (Berlin and New York: Walter de Gruyter, 2006), pp. 279–305, esp. pp. 291–93. In my present book, nothing hinges on the exact definition of the concept of a discourse mode, and I do not enter into a deeper explanation of the notion.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Franz Kafka, “The Transformation” (1915), in The Transformation and Other Stories: Works Published during Kafka’s Lifetime, trans. and ed. Malcolm Pasley (Harmondsworth: Penguin Books, 1992), pp. 76–126, at p. 76.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Philip Roth, Everyman (London: Vintage Books, 2007), p. 171.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Paul Auster, Travels in the Scriptorium (London: Faber and Faber, 2006), esp. pp. 1–3, 50–54, and 126–29.

    Google Scholar 

  11. The situation is exactly the opposite in analytical aesthetics, where it is more or less undisputed that the real author has a role to play for the constitution of meaning. See, e.g., Robert Stecker, “Interpretation”, in The Routledge Companion to Aesthetics, ed. Berys Gaut and Dominic McIver Lopes (London and New York: Routledge, 2001), pp. 239–51;

    Google Scholar 

  12. Paisley Livingston, Art and Intention: A Philosophical Study (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2005).

    Book  Google Scholar 

  13. Mieke Bal, Narratology: Introduction to the Theory of Narrative, 3rd edn (Toronto, Buffalo, and London: University of Toronto Press, 2009), pp. 15–16.

    Google Scholar 

  14. For the concept of relevance to the addressee, see esp. Mats Furberg, Saying and Meaning: A Main Theme in J.L. Austin’s Philosophy (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1971), pp. 93–94. Cf. Chapter 9, note 7.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Robert Stecker, Interpretation and Construction: Art, Speech, and the Law (Malden, Mass.: Blackwell, 2003), p. 59.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  16. Umberto Eco, “Intentio Lectoris: The State of the Art”, Differentia: Review of Italian Thought 2 (1988), pp. 147–68, at p. 160; emphasis Eco’s.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Jerrold Levinson, “Intention and Interpretation in Literature”, in Levinson’s The Pleasures of Aesthetics: Philosophical Essays (Ithaca and London: Cornell University Press, 1996), pp. 175–213, at pp. 176–77.

    Google Scholar 

  18. E.D. Hirsch, Jr., Validity in Interpretation (New Haven and London: Yale University Press, 1967), p. 8.

    Google Scholar 

  19. E.D. Hirsch, Jr., The Aims of Interpretation (Chicago and London: University of Chicago Press, 1976), p. 8.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Walter Kintsch, Comprehension: A Paradigm for Cognition (Cambridge, New York, and Melbourne: Cambridge University Press, 1998), p. 3.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Marcel Adam Just and Patricia A. Carpenter, The Psychology of Reading and Language Comprehension (Boston etc.: Allyn and Bacon, 1987), p. 18. I supose that Just and Carpenter would regard automatic processes as processes of which readers are unaware.

    Google Scholar 

  22. See Howard Shevrin, “Unconscious Processes”, in Encyclopedia of Cognitive Science, ed.-in-chief Lynn Nadel, vol. 4 (London, New York, and Tokyo: Nature Publishing Group, 2003), pp. 441–48.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Copyright information

© 2012 Anders Pettersson

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Pettersson, A. (2012). Application and the Act of Reading. In: The Concept of Literary Application. Palgrave Macmillan, London. https://doi.org/10.1057/9781137035424_3

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics