Skip to main content

Semantics and the Place of Psychological Evidence

  • Chapter
New Waves in Philosophy of Language

Part of the book series: New Waves in Philosophy ((NWIP))

Abstract

My aim in this chapter is to explore one point of similarity between an approach to semantic theorizing known as minimal semantics and an earlier approach to meaning proposed by Paul Grice. Before I set out the structure of the chapter in more detail, however, I would like to say something by way of an introduction to minimal semantics. Minimal semantics follows in the tradition of formal approaches to meaning of the kind put forward by Frege, early Wittgenstein, Carnap, Davidson, and others. Although the term ‘formal semantics’ is itself somewhat vague, it seems that what unites theorists on this side of the divide is, first, the belief that semantic content attaches to objects which can be formally described (so sentences or, more probably, sentences relativized to contexts of utterance) and, second, the expectation that linguistic meaning will be amenable to study via scientific methods of inquiry, broadly construed. This formal approach is of course diametrically opposed to the other main tradition in philosophy of language: speech act or use theories of meaning. The classic advocates of speech act theories include Austin, later Wittgenstein and Searle, but more recently the approach has re-emerged under the label of ‘contextualism’, as advocated by Recanati, Travis, and the relevance theorists Sperber and Wilson, and Carston, amongst many others. The age-old debate between formal theories and speech act theories has thus metamorphosed into the debate between minimalism and contextualism in the contemporary domain.1

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Bibliography

  • Avramides, A. (1989) Meaning and Mind: An Examination of a Gricean Account of Meaning (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press).

    Google Scholar 

  • Bach, K. (2006) ‘The Excluded Middle: Semantic Minimalism Without Minimal Propositions’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 72, 1–9.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bach, K. (2006b) ‘The Top Ten Misconceptions about Implicature’, in B. Birner and G. Ward (eds) Drawing the Boundaries of Meaning: Neo-Gricean Studies in Pragmatics and Semantics in Honor of Laurence R. Horn (Amsterdam: John Benjamins).

    Google Scholar 

  • Borg, E. (2004a) Minimal Semantics (Oxford: Oxford University Press).

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Borg, E. (2004b) ‘Formal Semantics and Intentional States’, Analysis, 64, 215–23.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Borg, E. (2007) ‘Minimalism versus Contextualism in Semantics’, in G. Preyer and G. Peter (eds) Context-Sensitivity and Semantic Minimalism: New Essays on Semantics and Pragmatics (Oxford: Oxford University Press).

    Google Scholar 

  • Borg, E. (2009). ‘Must a Semantic Minimalist Be a Semantic Internalist?’, The Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume, 83, 31–51.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Borg, E. (ms) Semantics from Syntax: In Defence of Minimal Semantics.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cappelen, H. and Lepore, E. (2005) Insensitive Semantics: A Defense of Demantic Minimalism and Speech Act Pluralism (Oxford: Blackwell).

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Carruthers, P. (1996) Language, Thought and Consciousness: An Essay in Philosophical Psychology (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Clapp, L. (2007) ‘Minimal (Disagreement about) Semantics’, in G. Preyer and G. Peter (eds) Context-Sensitivity and Semantic Minimalism: Essays on Semantics and Pragmatics (Oxford: Oxford University Press).

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1984) Inquiries into Truth and Interpretation (Oxford: Clarendon Press).

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1986) ‘A Nice Derangement of Epitaphs’, in E. Lepore (ed.) Truth and Interpretation (Oxford: Blackwell).

    Google Scholar 

  • Davies, M. (1987) ‘Tacit Knowledge and Semantic Theory: Can a Five Per Cent Difference Matter?’, Mind, 96, 441–62.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davies, M. (2006) ‘Foundational Issues in the Philosophy of Language’, in M. Devitt and R. Hanley (eds) The Blackwell Guide to the Philosophy of Language (Oxford: Blackwell).

    Google Scholar 

  • Dummett, M. (1993) Origins of Analytical Philosophy (London: Duckworth and Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press).

    Google Scholar 

  • Evans, G. (1982) The Varieties of Reference (Oxford: Clarendon Press).

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. (1990) A Theory of Content and Other Essays (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press).

    Google Scholar 

  • Garcia-Carpintero, M. (2001) ‘Gricean Rational Reconstructions and the Semantics/ Pragmatics Distinction’, Synthese, 128, 93–131.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gibbs, R. (2002) ‘A New Look at Literal Meaning in Understanding What Is Said and Implicated’, Journal of Pragmatics, 34, 457–86.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grice, P. (1989) Studies in the Way of Words (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press).

    Google Scholar 

  • Horn, L. (2006) ‘More Issues in Neo-and Post-Gricean Pragmatics: A Response to Robyn Carston’s Response’, Intercultural Pragmatics, 3, 81–93.

    Google Scholar 

  • Katz, J. (1977) Propositional Structure and Illocutionary Force (New York: Thomas Y. Crowell).

    Google Scholar 

  • Pinker, S. (2007) The Stuff of Thought: Language as a Window into Human Nature (London: Allen Lane).

    Google Scholar 

  • Recanati, F. (2004) Literal Meaning (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, B. (2006) ‘Against Grammatical Computation of Scalar Implicatures’, Journal of Semantics, 23, 361–82.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sauerland, U. (2004) ‘Scalar Implicatures in Complex Sentences’, Linguistics and Philosophy, 27, 367–91.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Soames, S. (2002) Beyond Rigidity (Oxford: Oxford University Press).

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Stainton, R. (2006) Words and Thoughts (Oxford: Oxford University Press).

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Stanley, J. (2000) ‘Context and Logical Form’, Linguistics and Philosophy, 23, 391–434.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stanley, J. (2005) ‘Semantics in Context’, in G. Preyer and G. Peter (eds) Contextualism in Philosophy: Knowledge, Meaning, and Truth (Oxford: Oxford University Press).

    Google Scholar 

  • Storto, G. and Tanenhaus, M. (2004) ‘Are Scalar Implicatures Computed Online?’, Proceedings of WECOL.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Copyright information

© 2010 Emma Borg

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Borg, E. (2010). Semantics and the Place of Psychological Evidence. In: Sawyer, S. (eds) New Waves in Philosophy of Language. New Waves in Philosophy. Palgrave Macmillan, London. https://doi.org/10.1057/9780230248588_3

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics