Skip to main content

Conciliatory Democracy

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Conciliatory Democracy

Abstract

The chapter introduces the epistemic conciliation of conflicting judgments as the guiding ideal of democracy. Two examples explore and elucidate the application of the ideal to political issues. On the one hand, controversies about abortion seemingly offer little room for epistemic conciliation as they address an “either/or” conflict about its permissibility. A more detailed look at the issues involved, however, lays bare a number of dimensions along which the ideal can gain traction. This proves that it applies to more cases that meet the eye at first sight. Conflicts between different conceptions of justice, on the other hand, are more straightforward and indeed paradigmatic cases of political disagreement. After thus extricating the consequences of the ideal of epistemic conciliation for politics, the chapter argues that democratic decision-making of a certain form exhibits a tendency toward epistemic conciliation. The argument relies on Duncan Black’s Median Voter Theorem which states that in majoritarian voting procedures the position closest to the ideal point of the median voter will be able to defeat any alternative. This is a first explanation of the tendency of democratic decision-making to engender conciliatory outcomes.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 119.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Feldman (2006): p. 414.

  2. 2.

    See Feldman (2006): p. 433 for the original version of this example.

  3. 3.

    Cabuela May (2005): p. 347.

  4. 4.

    Possible answers include, of course, “not at all” and “all the way.” More nuanced positions are available, however. Gutman and Thompson, for instance, argue that only pro-choice advocates should pay a tax used to subsidize abortions; cf. Gutman and Thompson (1996): p. 88ff.

  5. 5.

    From which he considers that it follows that the state should not subsidize abortion; cf. Sher (1981).

  6. 6.

    For this reason talk of a translation of arguments drawing on religious beliefs into a public justification makes the issue seem easier than it is. How do you translate the normative force of foundational religious premises?

  7. 7.

    This assumes that there are no independent reasons for global up- or downgrading (see Chap. 4; Local and Global Downgrading and Independence and Chap. 6; Representative Democracy and the Fundamental Importance of Political Parties).

  8. 8.

    Rawls (1996): p. 63; Rawls agrees with this conclusion.

  9. 9.

    These are two of the ways in which the debate has and continues to be framed. Cf. Ferree et al. (2002): pp. 105ff.

  10. 10.

    Cf. Fuchs and Klingemann (1989).

  11. 11.

    Indeed, Cabuela May insists that these moral pragmatic reasons are the only reasons we have for accepting compromises between our own moral convictions and those of others. Cf. Cabuela May (2005).

  12. 12.

    One philosopher explains: “Political compromise occurs when a political agent invokes the fact of disagreement as a reason to accept an alternative that she perceives to be worse on its own merits than her initial position” (Cabuela May (2005): p. 318). This also holds for what Henry Richardson calls “deep compromises,” a term which he uses to denote a compromise that affects the ends of the compromising actors; cf. Richardson (2002): pp. 147ff.

  13. 13.

    Hirschman (1994): p. 216.

  14. 14.

    Przeworski (1991): p. 10.

  15. 15.

    For recent examples, see Barry (1991), Waldron (1999, 2006), and Christiano (1996): Chap. 6 and (2008).

  16. 16.

    Cf. Black (1948) and Downs (1957).

  17. 17.

    Cf. Riker (1982) who formulates the threat he takes public choice theory to pose for mandate theories of democracy.

  18. 18.

    For an illustration of this points, see, for example, Shepsle and Bonchek (1997): pp. 83ff.

  19. 19.

    See also McGann (2004).

  20. 20.

    However, the theorem was originally formulated by Condorcet and rediscovered by Charles Dodgson in 1884 only to be forgotten again. Eventually, it was Duncan Black (and not Kenneth Arrow!) who was the first to rediscover it and the writings of Condorcet, Borda, and Dodgson in the twentieth century; cf. Rowley (2004): p. 203f.

  21. 21.

    Another way of phrasing this problem in the public choice lingo is to say that no alternative is the Condorcet winner. All these formulations express the simple idea that for each policy adopted there exists a majority that prefers a different policy.

  22. 22.

    Hence, Riker’s rejection of “populism,” the idea that the people articulate their “will” through elections, in favor of a brand of liberalism which views elections simply as a device to get rid of political elites; cf. Riker (1982).

  23. 23.

    Cf. Niemi and Weisberg (1968).

  24. 24.

    Cf. Mackie (2003).

  25. 25.

    Cf. Poole and Romer (1985) and Poole and Rosenthal (1997).

  26. 26.

    Goodin (2007): p. 194.

  27. 27.

    Cf. Lipset and Rokkan (1967): p. 50 and Dalton (2006): p. 134.

  28. 28.

    A troubling example is the effect of racism on redistributive policies; cf. Lee and Roemer (2006).

  29. 29.

    Cf. Poole and Romer (1985).

  30. 30.

    Cf. Poole and Rosenthal (1997).

  31. 31.

    Cf. Roemer (2001). Roemer develops a sophisticated model of electoral competition which takes intra-party competition between various factions into account. It should be noted, however, that his model is committed to multidimensionality. See also Roemer (2006) for a broader perspective on multiparty electoral competition.

  32. 32.

    Cf. Siaroff (2000): p. 21f.

  33. 33.

    Riker (1982): p. 128.

  34. 34.

    Cf. Castles and Mair (1984), Huber and Inglehart (1995), and Benoit and Laver 2005).

  35. 35.

    Cf. Gabel and Huber (2000) who check the self-placements of party supporters against the placements of parties by experts.

References

  • Barry, B. (1991). Is Democracy Special? In B. Barry (Ed.), Democracy and Power: Essays in Political Theory 1. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Benoit, K., & Laver, M. (2005). Party Policy in Modern Democracies. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Black, D. (1948). On the Rationale of Group Decision Making. Journal of Political Economy, 56(1), 23–34.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cabuela May, S. (2005). Principled Compromise and the Abortion Controversy. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 33(4), 317–348.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Castles, F. G., & Mair, P. (1984). Left–Right Political Scales: Some ‘Expert’ Judgments. European Journal of Political Research, 12(1), 73–88.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Christiano, T. (1996). The Rule of the Many: Fundamental Issues in Democratic Theory. Boulder, CO: Westview Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Christiano, T. (Ed.). (2008). The Constitution of Equality: Democratic Authority and its Limits. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dalton, R. J. (2006). Social Modernization and the End of Ideology Debate: Patterns of Ideological Polarization. Japanese Journal of Political Science, 7, 1–22.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Downs, A. (1957). An Economic Theory of Democracy. New York: Harper and Row.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feldman, R. (2006). Epistemological puzzles about disagreement. In S. Hetherington (Ed.), Epistemology Futures (pp. 216–236). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ferree, M. M., Gamson, W. A., Gerhards, J., & Rucht, D. (2002). Shaping Abortion Discourse. Democracy and the Public Sphere in Germany and the United States. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Fuchs, D., & Klingemann, H.-D. (1989). The Left-Right Schema. In K. M. Jennigns, J. W. van Denth, et al. (Eds.), Continuities in Political Action: A Longitudinal Study of Political Orientations in Three Western Democracies (pp. 32–72). Berlin: de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gabel, J., & Huber, J. (2000). Putting Parties in Their Places. American Journal of Political Science, 44, 94–103.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goodin, R. E. (2007). Political Science. In R. E. Goodin, P. Pettit, & T. Pogge (Eds.), A Companion to Contemporary Political Philosophy (2nd ed., Vol. I, pp. 183–214). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Gutman, A., & Thompson, D. (1996). Democracy and Disagreement. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hirschman, A. O. (1994). Social Conflicts as Pillars of Democratic Market Society. Political Theory, 22(2), 203–218.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Huber, J. D., & Inglehart, R. (1995). Expert Interpretations of Party Space and Party Locations in 42 Societies. Party Politics, 1, 73–111.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lee, W., & Roemer, J. E. (2006). Racism and Redistribution in the United States: A Solution to the Problem of American Exceptionalism. Journal of Public Economic, 90, 1027–1052.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lipset, S. M., & Rokkan, S. (1967). Party systems and voter alignments: cross-national perspectives. New York: Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mackie, G. (2003). Democracy Defended. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • McDonald, M. D., & Budge, I. (2005). Elections, Parties, Democracy: Conferring the Median Mandate. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • McGann, A. J. (2004). The Tyranny of the Supermajority. Journal of Theoretical Politics, 16(1), 53–77.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Niemi, R. G., & Weisberg, H. F. (1968). A mathematical solution for the probability of the paradox of voting. Behavioral Science, 13(4), 317–323.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Poole, K. T., & Romer, T. (1985). Patterns of political action committee contributions to the 1980 campaigns for the United States House of Representatives. Public Choice, 47(1), 63–111.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Poole, K. T., & Rosenthal, H. (1997). Congress: A Political-Economic History of Roll Call Voting. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Przeworski, A. (1991). Democracy and the Market: Political and Economic Reforms in Eastern Europe and Latin America. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. (1996). Political Liberalism (2nd ed.). New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Richardson, H. S. (2002). Democratic Autonomy: Public Reasoning about the Ends of policy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Riker, W. H. (1982). Liberalism Against Populism: A Confrontation Between the Theory of Democracy and the Theory of Social Science. San Francisco: W. H. Freeman.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roemer, J. E. (2001). Political Competition. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roemer, J. E. (2006). Modeling Party Competition in General Elections. In B. R. Weingast & D. A. Wittman (Eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Political Economy (pp. 1110–1131). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rowley, C. K. (2004). Public Choice from the Perspective of the History of Thought. In C. K. Rowley & F. Schneider (Eds.), The Encyclopedia of Public Choice (pp. 201–214). New York: Kluwer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Shepsle, K. A., & Bonchek, M. S. (1997). Analyzing Politics: Rationality, Behavior and Institutions. New York: W.W. Norton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sher, G. (1981). Subsidized Abortion: Moral Rights and Moral Compromise. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 10(4), 361–372.

    Google Scholar 

  • Siaroff, A. (2000). Comparative European Party Systems: An Analysis of Parliamentary Elections Since 1945. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Waldron, J. (1999). Law and Disagreement. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Waldron, J. (2006). The Core of the Case Against Judicial Review. The Yale Law Journal, 115, 1346–1406.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Copyright information

© 2017 The Author(s)

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Ebeling, M. (2017). Conciliatory Democracy. In: Conciliatory Democracy. Palgrave Macmillan, London. https://doi.org/10.1057/978-1-137-57743-6_5

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics