Skip to main content

Totality, Reason, Dialectics: The Importance of Hegel for Critical Theory from Lukács to Honneth

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
The Palgrave Handbook of Critical Theory

Part of the book series: Political Philosophy and Public Purpose ((POPHPUPU))

  • 3041 Accesses

Abstract

Critical theory has usually been regarded as a unique amalgamation of ideas drawn from Marx, Weber, and Freud, among other sources. What this view tends to minimize or overlook is the unique role of the critical theorists, beginning with Georg Lukács (a critical theorist “before the fact”), in reviving, interpreting, and further developing a distinctively Hegelian approach to the problems of knowledge, culture, and politics. This chapter first demonstrates the role of critical theorists in reviving Hegelianism in the early twentieth century. Then, it outlines the role of Hegelian philosophy as the basis for concepts of totality in the thought of Georg Lukács and Max Horkheimer, and of rationality in the thought of Herbert Marcuse and Theodor Adorno. The critique of, and then return to, Hegel in the work of Jürgen Habermas and Axel Honneth is also considered. The chapter concludes with an evaluation of three historical interpretations of the significance of the Hegelian element in critical theory, a consideration of the limits of Hegelianism for critical theory, and a suggestion of a fourth interpretation.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 189.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 249.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    For 50 years (approximately 1875–1925), the British Hegelians opposed the predominantly empiricist and utilitarian tendencies of British philosophy (Robbins 1982). Leading figures counterposed to these tendencies concepts of ontological monism (F.H. Bradley), recognitive ethics (T.H. Green), and political constitutionalism (Bernard Bosanquet). Yet, by the end of World War I, the new logical and linguistic ideas of Russell and Moore had made these idealist conceptions seem old-fashioned. In fact, Russell argued that they were founded on logical errors that vitiated any insights gained (Hylton 1990). Moore’s moral intuitionism assumed a “social detachment” that made neo-Hegelian conceptions of an ethical life seem unsubstantiated by any discernible moral psychology (Robbins 1982: 105). And an intellectual result of the war was to make any German-influenced philosophy appear vaguely antipatriotic.

  2. 2.

    Lukács’ Young Hegel was a companion piece to his earlier Destruction of Reason—an attack upon the current of German thought leading through Nietzsche that was generally characterized as “irrationalist” (Lukács 1981). Lukács claimed that The Young Hegel “contains a positive vision to contrast with the classical age of irrationalism” (Lukács 1975: xi). But this “vision” no longer leads to something identifiable as a “critical theory.”

  3. 3.

    What an odd coincidence it was that Marcuse’s view of Hegel as a liberal rationalist should contrast so sharply with that expressed in a similar work appearing at this time—The Open Society and Its Enemies, by Karl Popper. Popper was an Austrian émigré to Britain, with a rather shaky grasp of German philosophy. In the book, which was influential after the end of the war, Popper counted Hegel among the enemies of the “open [i.e., liberal] society”—a view that would have surprised Marcuse (not to speak of the British Hegelians) (Popper 1962)!

  4. 4.

    See, especially, Frederick Neuhouser, Foundations of Hegel’s Social Theory: Actualizing Freedom (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 2000).

  5. 5.

    An indication of this connection is one of Marcuse’s last writings, based on a talk he gave a year before his death in 1980 (Marcuse 1992).

  6. 6.

    Interestingly, the most authoritative source on the history of critical theory, Rolf Wiggershaus, is agnostic on this interpretive debate about the long-term failure or success of the Hegelian–Marxist element in critical theory (and whether a “return to Kant” is warranted) (Wiggershaus 1994).

  7. 7.

    One scholar who points this out is Christopher Lasch, referring to their work on the “authoritarian personality,” with which he contrasts Hannah Arendt’s more historically informed approach in her Origins of Totalitarianism (Lasch 1991: 445–50).

References

  • Adorno, Theodor. 1983. Negative dialectics. Trans. E.B. Ashton. New York: Continuum.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1993. Hegel: Three studies. Trans. S.W. Nicholsen. Cambridge, MA: Massachusetts Institute of Technology Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baynes, Kenneth. 1992. The normative grounds of social criticism: Kant, Rawls, and Habermas. Albany: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bencivenga, Ermanno. 2000. Hegel’s dialectical logic. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bottomore, Tom, and Patrick Goode (ed). 1978. Austro-Marxism. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bubner, Rüdiger. 1981. Modern German philosophy. Trans. E. Matthews. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Guha, Ramachandra. 2000. Environmentalism: A global history. New York: Longman.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, Jürgen. 1970. Toward a rational society: Student protest, science, and politics. Trans. J.J. Shapiro. Boston: Beacon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1971. Knowledge and human interests. Trans. J.J. Shapiro. Boston: Beacon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1973. Theory and practice. Trans. J. Viertel. Boston: Beacon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1979. Communication and the evolution of society. Trans. T. McCarthy. Boston: Beacon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1987. The philosophical discourse of modernity: Twelve lectures. Trans. F.G. Lawrence. Cambridge, MA: Massachusetts Institute of Technology Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1991. Moral consciousness and communicative action. Trans. C. Lenhardt, and S.W. Nicholsen. Cambridge, MA: Massachusetts Institute of Technology Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hegel, G.W.F.1977. The phenomenology of spirit. Trans. A.V. Miller. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Honneth, Axel. 1995. The fragmented world of the social: Essays in social and political philosophy. Albany: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1996. The struggle for recognition: The moral grammar of social conflicts. Trans. J. Anderson. Cambridge, MA: Massachusetts Institute of Technology Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2004. A social pathology of reason: On the intellectual legacy of critical theory. In The Cambridge companion to critical theory, ed. Fred Rush. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2010. The pathologies of individual freedom: hegel’s social theory. Trans. L. Löb. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2014. Freedom’s right: The social foundations of democratic life. Trans. J. Ganahl. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Horkheimer, Max. 1982. Critical theory: Selected essays. Trans. M.J. O’Connell, et al. New York: Continuum.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1993. Between philosophy and social science: Selected early writings. Trans. G. Frederick Hunter, et al. Cambridge, MA: Massachusetts Instituteof Technology Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Horkheimer, Max, and Theodor Adorno. 2002. Dialectic of enlightenment:Philosophical fragments. Trans. E. Jephcott. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hylton, Peter. 1990. Russell, idealism, and the emergence of analytic philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jay, Martin. 1973. The dialectical imagination: A history of the Frankfurt School and the Institute of Social Research, 1923–1950. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1984. Marxism and totality: The adventures of a concept from Lukács to Habermas. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhlmann, Wolfgang (ed). 1986. Moralität und Sittlichkeit: Das Problem Hegels und die Diskursethik. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lasch, Christopher. 1991. The true and only heaven: Progress and its critics. NewYork: Norton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lichtheim, George. 1971. From Marx to Hegel. New York: Continuum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lukács, Georg. 1971. History and class consciousness: Studies in Marxist dialectics. Trans. R. Livingstone. Cambridge, MA: Massachusetts Institute of TechnologyPress.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1975. The young Hegel: Studies in the relations between dialetics and economics. Trans. R. Livingstone. London: Merlin Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1981. The destruction of reason. Trans. P. Palmer. Atlantic Highlands: Humanities Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marcuse, Herbert. 1941. Reason and revolution: Hegel and the rise of social theory. Boston: Beacon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1992. Ecology and the critique of modern society. Capitalism, Nature, Socialism 3(3): 29–48.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Popper, Karl. 1962. The open society and its enemies, 2 vols. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Radkau, Joachim. 2014. The age of ecology: A global history. Trans. P. Camiller. Cambridge: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Robbins, Peter. 1982. The British Hegelians, 1875–1925. New York: Garland.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rush, Fred. 2004. Conceptual foundations of early critical theory. In The Cambridge companion to critical theory, ed. Fred Rush. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Schnädelbach, Herbert. 1984. Philosophy in Germany, 1831–1933. Trans. E. Matthews. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, Charles. 1975. Hegel. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wheatland, Thomas. 2009. The Frankfurt school in exile. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wiggershaus, Rolf. 1994. The Frankfurt school: Its history, theories, and political significance. Trans. M. Robertson. Cambridge, MA: Massachusetts Institute of Technology Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wolin, Richard. 2006. The Frankfurt school revisited, and other essays on politics and society. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Copyright information

© 2017 The Author(s)

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Dahbour, O. (2017). Totality, Reason, Dialectics: The Importance of Hegel for Critical Theory from Lukács to Honneth. In: Thompson, M. (eds) The Palgrave Handbook of Critical Theory. Political Philosophy and Public Purpose. Palgrave Macmillan, New York. https://doi.org/10.1057/978-1-137-55801-5_5

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics