Skip to main content

Conceptualism and Nonconceptualism in Kant: A Survey of the Recent Debate

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Kantian Nonconceptualism

Abstract

As one of the main proponents of Kantian nonconceptualism, Lucy Allais provides a helpful overview of the current debate on nonconceptualism in Kant scholarship by drawing on those papers that represent what appear to be central argumentative possibilities. She also responds to certain objections from conceptualists, and in specific respects makes concessions to the conceptualist, whilst holding on to her original claim that Kant is committed to a kind of nonconceptualism and that a nonconceptualist reading of intuition must be our starting point in approaching central arguments such as in the Transcendental Deduction. She emphasises that her modestly nonconceptualist interpretation is entirely compatible with thinking that all intuitions are conceptualised, that conceptualisation radically transforms what is given in intuition and for what is given in intuition to play a role in cognition, intuitions must be conceptualised.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 89.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 119.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Allais (2009, 2010, 2012, 2015) and Allais (forthcoming a, b).

  2. 2.

    See McLear (2014b:771–2) and Tolley (MS b).

  3. 3.

    For example, Griffith (2012) explicitly assimilates intuition to perception.

  4. 4.

    See McLear (2014b:771).

  5. 5.

    See Golob (2014), McLear (2014b:771–2) and Tolley (MS b).

  6. 6.

    See Allais (2015) and Allais (forthcoming a).

  7. 7.

    See McLear (2016)) and Stephenson (2015b).

  8. 8.

    This is argued in detail by McLear (2014b) and Tolley (MS b). See McLear (2013) for a detailed account of Kant’s view of perception and Matherne (2015) for an account of the role of imaginative synthesis in perception.

  9. 9.

    See Golob (2014).

  10. 10.

    On the nonconceptualist side, I think I did this in Allais (2009); on the other side, see Griffith (2012).

  11. 11.

    See also McLear (2014b).

  12. 12.

    See Schulting (2015b:569) for a similar account of a moderate nonconceptualism.

  13. 13.

    See Hanna (2005), and Hanna, Chap. 5, this volume.

  14. 14.

    They quote Falkenstein as saying that this footnote is “so obscure that it can be made to serve the needs of any interpretation whatsoever” (Onof and Schulting 2015:4).

  15. 15.

    See Allais (2009:392ff.) and Connolly (2014:319). Bauer (2012:223) argues that Kant makes it clear both that the blindness of intuition is total and that the blindness is the emptiness of cognitive content. He does not, however, provide strong evidence for this. He points out that Kant says that the understanding is necessary for objects to have relation to an object, and therefore for cognition to have the possibility of being true (A62–3/B87), and that the synthetic unity of apperception is necessary for anything “to become an object for me” (B138). These are important passages that the nonconceptualist must respond to (I discuss them in detail in Allais 2015 and Allais, forthcoming a), but whether Kant’s notion of “relation to an object” and of something being possible as an object of cognition are the same as having any representational content at all is certainly not apparent simply from the texts quoted.

  16. 16.

    There is even less reason to take it to mean something specific and technical, like intentional content, as Williams (2012:60) does, given that Kant says nothing to explain that this is how he is using the word.

  17. 17.

    This is appealed to by Bauer (2012:217).

  18. 18.

    Ibid.

  19. 19.

    This is appealed to by Bowman (2011:422).

  20. 20.

    Bauer (2012:223) takes this passage as decisive.

  21. 21.

    McDowell’s reading is discussed in detail by Williams (2012).

  22. 22.

    See Allais (2010, 2015).

  23. 23.

    See Allais (2015), Chap. 7, Allais (forthcoming a), and McLear ((2016). See also McLear, Chap. 8 in this volume.

  24. 24.

    This chapter is focused on the question of Kant’s conceptualism. A further crucial question with respect to intuition, which I do not discuss here, is whether or not intuitions involve the presence of the objects they represent. Stephenson (2015b) argues against the idea that they do, and the options with respect to this question are helpfully summarised by Gomes and Stephenson in Chap. 3 in this volume. I argue that intuitions involve the presence of the objects they represent in Allais (2010, 2015).

  25. 25.

    See Pendlebury (1995).

  26. 26.

    See, for example, Ginsborg (2008).

  27. 27.

    See McLear (2015).

  28. 28.

    I also argue this in Allais (2015) Chap. 7, and Allais (forthcoming a, b).

  29. 29.

    See, for example, Bauer (2012) and Ginsborg (2008).

  30. 30.

    See also Bauer (2012:227) and Land (2015a:25).

  31. 31.

    See also Land (2015a:30) and Pippin (1993:294).

  32. 32.

    Allais (2009).

  33. 33.

    See Schulting (2015b) for discussion.

  34. 34.

    See Schulting (2015b:575).

  35. 35.

    Allais (2015) and Allais (forthcoming a).

  36. 36.

    Thus we can read the claim that the same function that unifies concepts in a judgement also unifies intuition (A79/B104–5) not as a claim about what produces unified intuition but as about a function that (conceptually) unifies intuitions that already exist (so already have intuitional unity).

  37. 37.

    Griffith claims that “if he intends to show that ‘everything that may ever come before the senses’ stands under the categories, then even sense perception without judgment stands under the categories” (2012:207). We have already seen that there is an important distinction between a nonconceptualism which denies that the objects of our perception are brought under the categories, and one which denies that they need be brought under the categories in order to be given to us in intuition.

  38. 38.

    See also Land (2015a:33).

Bibliography

  • Allais, Lucy. 2009. Kant, Non-Conceptual Content and the Representation of Space. Journal of the History of Philosophy 47(3): 383–413.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2010. Kant’s Argument for Transcendental Idealism in the Transcendental Aesthetic. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 110(1, Part 1): 47–75.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2012. Perceiving Distinct Particulars. In Kantian Metaphysics Today: New Essays on Time and Space, eds. R. Baiasu et al., 41–66. Basingstoke and New York: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2015. Manifest Reality: Kant’s Idealism and His Realism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2016a. Synthesis and Binding. In Kant and the Philosophy of Mind, eds. A. Gomes and A. Stephenson. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2016b. Transcendental Idealism and the Transcendental Aesthetic: Reading the Critique of Pure Reason Forwards. In Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason: A Critical Guide, ed. J. O’Shea. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bauer, N 2012. A Peculiar Intuition: Kant’s Conceptualist Account of Perception. Inquiry 55(3): 215–237.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bowman, B. 2011. A Conceptualist Reply to Hanna’s Kantian Non-Conceptualism. International Journal of Philosophical Studies 19(3): 417–446.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Connolly, K. 2014. Which Kantian Conceptualism (or Non-conceptualism)? Southern Journal of Philosophy 52(3): 316–337.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ginsborg, H 2008. Was Kant a Nonconceptualist? Philosophical Studies 137(1): 65–77 [also published in D. Heidemann (2013), pp. 208–18.].

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Golob, S. 2014. Kant on Intentionality, Magnitude, and the Unity of Perception. European Journal of Philosophy 22(4): 505–528.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gomes, A 2014. Kant on Perception: Naive Realism, Non-Conceptualism, and the B-Deduction. Philosophical Quarterly 64(2014): 1–19.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Griffith, A. 2012. Perception and the Categories: A Conceptualist Reading of Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason. European Journal of Philosophy 20(2): 193–222.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grüne, S 2011. Is There a Gap in Kant’s B Deduction? International Journal of Philosophical Studies 19(3): 465–490.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hanna, R 2005. Kant and Nonconceptual Content. European Journal of Philosophy 13(2): 247–290.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ——— 2011b. Kant’s Non-Conceptualism, Rogue Objects, and the Gap in the B Deduction. International Journal of Philosophical Studies 19(3): 399–415.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Land, T. 2011. Kantian Conceptualism. In Rethinking Epistemology, eds. G. Abel et al., 197–239. Berlin: de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Land, T 2015a. Nonconceptualist Readings of Kant and the Transcendental Deduction. Kantian Review 20(1): 25–51.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Matherne, S. 2015. Images and Kant’s Theory of Perception. Ergo 2: 737–777.

    Google Scholar 

  • McDowell, J 1994. Mind and World. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ——— 1998. Having the World in View: Sellars, Kant and Intentionality. [The Woodbridge Lectures]. Journal of Philosophy 95(9): 431–491.

    Google Scholar 

  • McLear, C. 2011. Kant on Animal Consciousness. Philosophers’ Imprint 11(15): 1–16.

    Google Scholar 

  • McLear, C 2013. Essays on Kant on Perception and Cognition, unpublished Ph.D. dissertation, Cornell University.

    Google Scholar 

  • ——— 2014b. The Kantian (Non)-Conceptualism Debate. Philosophy Compass 9(11): 769–790.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ——— 2015. Two Kinds of Unity in the Critique of Pure Reason. Journal of the History of Philosophy 53(1): 79–110.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ——— 2016a. Kant on Perceptual Content. Mind.

    Google Scholar 

  • Onof, C., and D. Schulting. 2015. Space as Form of Intuition and as Formal Intuition: On the Note to B160 in Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason. Philosophical Review 124(1): 1–58.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pendlebury, M. 1995. Making Sense of Kant’s Schematism. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 55(4): 777–797.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pippin, R 1993. Hegel’s Original Insight. International Philosophical Quarterly 33(3): 285–295.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schulting, D 2015b. Probleme des “kantianischen” Nonkonzeptualismus im Hinblick auf die B-Deduktion. Kant-Studien 106(4): 561–580.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stephenson, A 2015b. Kant on the Object-Dependence of Intuition and Hallucination. Philosophical Quarterly 65(260): 486–508.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tolley, C 2016b. Kant on the Distinction between Perception and Experience.

    Google Scholar 

  • Watkins, E 2008. Kant and the Myth of the Given. Inquiry 51(5): 512–531.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williams, J. 2012. How Conceptually-Guided are Kantian Intuitions? History of Philosophy Quarterly 29(1): 57–78.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Lucy Allais .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Copyright information

© 2016 The Author(s)

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Allais, L. (2016). Conceptualism and Nonconceptualism in Kant: A Survey of the Recent Debate. In: Schulting, D. (eds) Kantian Nonconceptualism. Palgrave Macmillan, London. https://doi.org/10.1057/978-1-137-53517-7_1

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics