Skip to main content

Part of the book series: The New Synthese Historical Library ((SYNL,volume 74))

  • 408 Accesses

Abstract

Andreas Blank (Paderborn University, Germany), in Presumption and Leibniz’s Metaphysics of Action, 1678–1680, shows that in notes from the period between 1678 and 1680, Leibniz discusses the role of ontological requisites for the metaphysics of the agency of individual substances. In these notes, Leibniz takes up some considerations from his writings from the period between 1669 and 1671. In both periods, Leibniz connects the analysis of the ontological notion of requisite with the epistemological notion of presumption. According to Leibniz’s suggestion in both periods, we should presume that other persons will take the course of action that has the smallest number of requisites. In this context, Leibniz uses one of the traditional conceptions of presumption derived from the juridical tradition: the conception of presumption as an evidence-based conjecture concerning the agency of persons. Such presumptions were taken to be true unless and until contrary evidence becomes available. The author argues that Leibniz’s views concerning such action-related presumption and those concerning the ontological requisites of actions are closely linked. Very much as action-related presumptions can be revised in the light of additional evidence, requisites can be prevented from leading to the actions that they would bring about taken in isolation through the occurrence of further requisites – be they internal or external. Therefore, Leibniz’s metaphysics of the agency of individual substances in the period between 1678 and 1680 should be understood much more in the context of an experience-based ontology that allows for interaction between internal and external requisites of action than in the context of Leibniz’s later, speculative ontology that excludes causal interactions between substances.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. 1.

    See below, note 52.

  2. 2.

    See, e.g., Alciato (1617, vol. 4, cols. 579–584).

  3. 3.

    On the notion of indicium in medieval and Renaissance law, see Franklin (2001, 27–43); on the theory of interpreting signa in Renaissance law, see Maclean (1992). Evidence-based presumptions played a significant role in the early modern controversies over excepted crimes (see Blank 2012) and territorial rights (see Blank 2011, 2013).

  4. 4.

    Mascardi (1607, vol. 1, 32): “Praesumptio est coniectura, seu divinatio in rebus dubiis, collecta ex argumentis, vel indiciis per rerum circumstantias frequenter eventibus.”

  5. 5.

    Menochio (1608, 7): “Est indicium coniectura ex probabilibus & non necessariis orta, a quibus potest abesse veritas, sed non verisimilitudo veri, quae quandoque mentem iudicantis ita perstringunt, ut cogant conscientiam iudicis iudicare secundum ipsa.”

  6. 6.

    A VI, 4, 1426. Leibniz takes this thought up in a slightly later manuscript: “Something is determined towards some state or action when something else follows from it considered in itself or when no obstacle occurs, and relates to what is absolutely determined towards causing something (which includes all requisites) as demonstration relates to presumption: determination in this sense is a presumption based on what is naturally prior” (A VI, 4, 404).

  7. 7.

    A VI 4, 1428–1429.

  8. 8.

    A VI, 4, 1411.

  9. 9.

    A VI, 4, 1430.

  10. 10.

    A VI, 4, 1426.

  11. 11.

    A VI, 4, 1412–1413.

  12. 12.

    A VI, 4, 308. Here Leibniz takes up John Wilkins’s explication of the notion of “what contributes something” [conferens] as “a requisite according to a certain mode of production.” See A VI, 4, 39; see Wilkins 1668: 35.

  13. 13.

    For detailed accounts of Leibniz’s notion of requisite, see Adams (1994, 115–119); Piro (2002, 38–54); Di Bella (1991, 2005a, 72–98, b).

  14. 14.

    A VI, 2, 483.

  15. 15.

    See A VI, 2, 489.

  16. 16.

    See A VI, 2, 499.

  17. 17.

    A VI, 2, 567.

  18. 18.

    On Leibniz’s evaluation of the talents of the different candidates in this work, see Griard (2008).

  19. 19.

    A IV, 1, 11.

  20. 20.

    A IV, 1, 15–16.

  21. 21.

    A IV, 1, 5.

  22. 22.

    A IV, 1, 14.

  23. 23.

    A IV, 1, 43.

  24. 24.

    A IV, 1, 21.

  25. 25.

    A IV, 1, 471.

  26. 26.

    A IV, 1, 31.

  27. 27.

    A IV, 1, 32.

  28. 28.

    A VI, 1, 472.

  29. 29.

    Ibid.

  30. 30.

    A VI, 2, 565.

  31. 31.

    Ibid.

  32. 32.

    Ibid.

  33. 33.

    I owe this way of formulating the problems to a conversation with Mark Kulstad.

  34. 34.

    A VI, 1, 472.

  35. 35.

    A VI, 4, 303.

  36. 36.

    VI, 4, 1412.

  37. 37.

    A VI, 4, 74.

  38. 38.

    A VI, 4, 380–381.

  39. 39.

    A VI, 4, 2764, marginal note.

  40. 40.

    Ibid.

  41. 41.

    A VI, 4, 2762.

  42. 42.

    A VI, 4, 2758.

  43. 43.

    A VI, 1, 455.

  44. 44.

    Ibid. On Leibniz’s attitude towards Aristotelian ethics, see Piro (1994).

  45. 45.

    A VI, 1, 471.

  46. 46.

    A VI, 1, 343–345.

  47. 47.

    Ibid.

  48. 48.

    Ibid. On Leibniz’s reasons to include love into his conception of justice, see Busche (1997, 307–310); Goldenbaum (2002, 209–231).

  49. 49.

    A VI, 1, 455.

  50. 50.

    A VI, 1, 471; Translation from Adams (1994, 204), with one sentence added.

  51. 51.

    See A VI, 1, 398; A VI, 1, 405; A VI, 2, 487, note 3; A VI, 2, 495 and 495, note 46; A VI, 3, 127.

  52. 52.

    Burkhardt (1980, 425–426); Adams (1994, 205).

  53. 53.

    A VI, 1, 471.

  54. 54.

    A VI, 1, 476; see also A VI, 1, 480.

  55. 55.

    See A VI, 4, 2777; A VI, 4, 2758, 2761 and 2767. On Leibniz’s theory of justice as caritas sapientis, see Grua (1953); Riley (1996).

  56. 56.

    A VI, 1, 465.

  57. 57.

    A VI, 1, 466.

  58. 58.

    See A VI, 2, 565 (variants to A VI, 1, 465).

  59. 59.

    A VI, 1, 470.

  60. 60.

    A VI, 2, 567.

  61. 61.

    Ibid.

  62. 62.

    A VI, 4, 2761.

  63. 63.

    Ibid. For a similar statement, see A VI, 4, 613.

  64. 64.

    A VI, 4, 2761.

  65. 65.

    For an utilitarian interpretation of Leibniz’s notion of common good, see Elster (1975, 129). Such an interpretation is criticized, for different reasons, in Riley (1996, 160–164) and in Basso (2005, 54–57).

  66. 66.

    A VI, 4, 2758.

  67. 67.

    A VI, 1, 471.

  68. 68.

    Ibid.

  69. 69.

    Ibid.

  70. 70.

    A VI, 4, 2762 (see above, note 41).

References

  • Adams, R. M. 1994. Leibniz. Determinist, Idealist, Theist. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alciato, A. 1617. Opera omnia. 4 vols. Frankfurt: Lazarus Zetzner.

    Google Scholar 

  • Basso, L. 2005. Individuo e communita nella filosofia politica di G. W. Leibniz. Soveria Mannelli: Rubbetino.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blank, A. 2011. Leibniz on Usucaption, Presumption, and International Justice. Studia Leibnitiana 43: 70–86.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blank, A. 2012. Presumption, Torture, and the Controversy over Excepted Crimes, 1600–1632. Intellectual History Review 22: 131–145.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blank, A. 2013. Johannes von Felden on Usucaption, Justice, and the Society of States. Journal of the History of Ideas 74: 411–427.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Burkhardt, H. 1980. Logik und Semiotik in der Philosophie von Leibniz, Munich: Philosophia.

    Google Scholar 

  • Busche, H. 1997. Leibniz’ Weg ins perspektivische Universum. Eine Harmonie im Zeitalter der Berechnung, Hamburg: Meiner.

    Google Scholar 

  • Di Bella, S. 1991. Il ‘Requisitum’ leibniziano come ‘pars’ e come ‘ratio’: tra inerenza e causalita. Lexicon Philosophicum 5: 129–152.

    Google Scholar 

  • Di Bella, S. 2005a. The Science of the Individual: Leibniz’s Ontology of Individual Substance. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Di Bella, S. 2005b. Leibniz’s Theory of Conditions: A Framework for Ontological Dependence. Leibniz Review 15: 67–93.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Elster, J. 1975. Leibniz et la formation de l’ésprit capitaliste. Paris: Aubier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Franklin, J. 2001. The Science of Conjecture. Evidence and Probability before Pascal. Baltimore, MD and London: The Johns Hopkins University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldenbaum, U. 2002. All you need is love, love … Leibniz’ Vermittlung von Hobbes’ Naturrecht und christlicher Nächstenliebe als Grundlage seiner Definition der Gerechtigkeit. In Neuzeitliches Denken. Festschrift für Hans Poser zum 65. Geburtstag, ed. G. Abel, H.-J. Engfer, and C. Hubig, 209–231. Berlin, New York: De Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Griard, J. 2008. The Specimen Demonstrationum Politicarum Pro Eligendo Rege Polonorum: From the Concatenation of Demonstrations to a Decision Appraisal Procedure. In Leibniz: What Kind of Rationalist?, ed. M. Dascal, 371–382. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Grua, G. 1953. Jurisprudence universelle et Theodicee selon Leibniz. Paris: Presses Universitaires de France.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maclean, I. 1992. Interpretation and Meaning in the Renaissance. The Case of Law. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mascardi, G. 1607. De probationibus. 3 vols. Frankfurt: Saurius.

    Google Scholar 

  • Menochio, G. 1608. De praesumptionibus, coniecturis, signis, et indicibus. 3 vols. Lyon: Crispinus.

    Google Scholar 

  • Piro, F. 1994. Leibniz et l’Éthique à Nicomaque. In Leibniz und die Frage nach der Subjektivität, ed. Renato Cristin, 179–196. Stuttgart: Steiner.

    Google Scholar 

  • Piro, F. 2002. Spontaneità e ragion sufficiente. Determinismo e filosofia dell’azione in Leibniz. Roma: Edizioni di storia e letteratura.

    Google Scholar 

  • Riley, P. 1996. Leibniz’s Universal Jurisprudence. Justice as the Charity of the Wise. Cambridge, Mass., and London: Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wilkins, J. 1668. An Essay Towards a Real Character, and a Philosophical Language. London: Gellibrand & Martyn.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Andreas Blank .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2015 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Blank, A. (2015). Presumption and Leibniz’s Metaphysics of Action. In: Nita, A. (eds) Leibniz’s Metaphysics and Adoption of Substantial Forms. The New Synthese Historical Library, vol 74. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-9956-0_7

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics