Skip to main content

Part of the book series: The New Synthese Historical Library ((SYNL,volume 74))

  • 458 Accesses

Abstract

Markku Roinila (University of Helsinki, Finland), in Affects and Activity in Leibniz’s De affectibus, discusses the doctrine of substance that emerges from Leibniz’s unpublished early memoir De affectibus of 1679. The memoir marks a new stage in Leibniz’s views of the mind. The motivation for this change can be found in Leibniz’s rejection of the Cartesian theory of passion and action in the 1670s. Leibniz’s early Aristotelianism and some features of Cartesianism persisted, to which Leibniz added influences from Hobbes and Spinoza. His nascent dynamical concept of substance is seemingly a combination of old and fresh influences, representing a characteristically eclectic approach. The author argues that the influence of Hobbes is especially important in the memoir. To do that, he examines Leibniz’s development in the 1670s up to the De affectibus and considers the nature of affects in the memoir, especially the first affect which starts the thought sequence. This first affect of pleasure or pain is the key to Leibniz’s theory of active substances and in this way to the whole of Leibniz’s moral psychology and ethical metaphysics.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Schepers (2003, 133–135) speculates that by analysing Descartes’s and Spinoza’s views on passions or affections Leibniz sought to find material for his planned scientia generalis. Di Bella argues along the same lines (2006, 194). As I will argue later, I think Leibniz saw affections as important in his moral philosophy, as Elementa juris naturalis of 1671 already shows. Therefore I think that his interest in passions was fired up by the need to explain human behavior in general. In the previous year he also read and copied passages from Spinoza’s Ethica, parts III–V, noting in his letter to Vincent Placcius of 14. February 1678 that Spinoza had said many good things about the affects (A II, 1, 593).

  2. 2.

    See, for example, Discours de metaphysique, §10.

  3. 3.

    Active powers are potentialities, which are external principles of change or being at rest (Metaphysics 9. 8, 1049b5–10). Thus they are essential in explaining causes.

  4. 4.

    On the nature of the soul, see Second Meditation, CSM II, 19–20.

  5. 5.

    On Malebranche’s criticism of Descartes’s views, see James (1997, 108–123). On Leibniz’s intellectual development in the Paris years, see Antognazza (2008, 139–192) and Mercer (2001, 385–461).

  6. 6.

    Leibniz wrote a marginal note on the relationship between love and joy (A VI, 4, 1704). In 1671 he had discussed the essence of pure love in Elementa juris naturalis (A VI, 1, 431–485).

  7. 7.

    See especially his own definitions in A VI, 4, 1426.

  8. 8.

    The division A-J is made by the Academy editors. See A VI, 4, 1410.

  9. 9.

    Schepers finds in the last sections of De affectibus a logical structure. See Schepers (2003), especially 152–160. See also Di Bella (2006, 194).

  10. 10.

    “Passio est status aliquis qui causa proxima mutationis est” (A VI, 4, 1411). In much later Monadologie of 1714 Leibniz argues in §49–52 that mutual action and passion among substances is regulated by the pre-established harmony. In De affectibus Leibniz discusses in terms of individual minds which are either spontaneous in the sense that they are active or the opposite case.

  11. 11.

    A VI, 4, 1428–1429; translated in Di Bella (2006, 113).

  12. 12.

    Compare Passions, §24 (CSM I, 337). Referring to §27–28, Leibniz argues that affects are perceptions which are related to the soul and not to the body (A VI, 4, 1418). See also Giolito (1996, 198).

  13. 13.

    “Affectus est occupatio animi orta ex sententia animi circa bonum et malum” (A VI, 4, 1412).

  14. 14.

    For another account on Hobbes’s influence to Leibniz’s early thought, see McDonald Ross (2007, 20 and 24–27). I will return to the details of Hobbes’ influence to Leibniz in the next section.

  15. 15.

    “Sententia est intellectio ex qua sequitur voluntas” (A VI, 1412).

  16. 16.

    “Occupatio animi est inclinatio ad aliquid prae alio cogitandum” (A VI, 1412).

  17. 17.

    Hobbes, Leviathan, ch. 6 (1651). At this point Leibniz did not yet have the doctrine of innate instinct of the New Essays (I, ii) where we automatically strive for good or pleasure and avoid evil or imperfection.

  18. 18.

    On Hobbes’ influence to TMA, see Wilson (1997, 341–343) and Garber (2009a, 15–17).

  19. 19.

    See also Garber (2009a, 17–18).

  20. 20.

    The doctrine of perceiving bodies is also a debt Leibniz owes to Hobbes. See MacDonald Ross (2007, 27–30).

  21. 21.

    See also Boros (2007, 82–83) and Wilson (1997, 344). In his letter to Arnauld in 1671 Leibniz said that the philosophy of motion is a step towards the science of the mind (A II, 1, 278). On Leibniz’s early attempts to formulate such a science, see Busche (2004, 142–151).

  22. 22.

    See also Wilson (1997, 343–344).

  23. 23.

    See also Leibniz (1992, xlv).

  24. 24.

    This view is also present in Theoria motus abstracti, written in the same year. See Busche (2004, 151–153). Compare also De affectibus (A VI, 4, 1426).

  25. 25.

    See also Leibniz (2005, 161, n. 101).

  26. 26.

    Elementa verae pietatis, sive de amore Dei super omnia (A VI, 4, 1357–1366).

  27. 27.

    “Series est multitudo cum ordinis regula” (A VI, 4, 1426). See also A VI, 1424.

  28. 28.

    An interesting comparison can be made to Nouveaux essais II, xxi, §47 where Leibniz argues that we cannot affect our moral action directly, but we should reject our bad habits and adopt new ones in order to reach virtue. The habit is in a sense a series of thoughts which can be maintained by strong willing and developing the understanding (A VI, 6, 195–197). See also Roinila (2006) and Jones (2006, 252–261).

  29. 29.

    I think Di Bella is right in the sense that in Tractatus de Intellectus Emendatione (1662?), sec. 85 Spinoza argues that an objective effect proceeds in the soul according to the formal nature of its object. Thus the soul acts according to certain laws, like a spiritual automaton. See Spinoza (1985, 37). It is also true that Leibniz continued to use this description of the soul in many of his later writings, for example in Monadologie, §18. However, he does not use the concept in De affectibus and, as I argue, I think the primary influence can also be Hobbes. See also Monadologie, §37 and Principes de la nature et de la grace, fondés en raison, §8.

  30. 30.

    For Fichant’s argument, see Leibniz 1994. For a critical view on Fichant’s argument, see Garber (2009b).

  31. 31.

    In this, I am inspired by Goldenbaum’s article on Leibniz’s early fascination with Hobbes’s views (2009, 193–196).

  32. 32.

    Hobbes discusses series of appetites and aversions which form passions such as hope or fear. On Hobbes’ views on affects, see also De homine XI, 5 and XIII, 1.

  33. 33.

    See also Goldenbaum (2009, 199).

  34. 34.

    “Affectus est in animo, quod impetus in corpore” (A VI, 4, 1426). See also Schepers (2003, 135).

  35. 35.

    “Series cogitandi oritur vel ex ideis distinctis…vel oritur ex ideis confusis” (A VI, 4, 1424–1425). This passage clearly anticipates NE II, xxi, §39.

  36. 36.

    Although Leibniz does not discuss the topic more extensively, one can easily relate this idea to the classic problem of akrasia or weakness of the will. We are taken by a more vivid thought which leads us to another train of thoughts. The goal, of course, is to turn human attention to the most perfect series. See Leibniz’s later discussion of akrasia in NE, II, xxi, §35 (A VI, 6, 185–188).

  37. 37.

    Of branching, see Blank Chap. 7 in this volume.

  38. 38.

    See, for example, Nouveaux essais, II, xxi, §21–30 (A VI, 6, 181–183).

  39. 39.

    Giolito compares the Leibnizian affect to Cartesian internal emotions of the soul which he discusses in Passions, §147 (CSM I, 381). These are produced in the soul itself and are therefore not dependent on the movement of the animal spirits, although they may be aroused by external events such as a tragic play. However, the Cartesian intellectual passions are defined as particular passions, while Leibniz’s affect is general by nature. See Giolito (1996, 201–202).

  40. 40.

    See, for example, NE II, xxi, §47. See also Aristotle, Nichomachean Ethics VII.

  41. 41.

    See also Nadler (2006, 200).

  42. 42.

    Leibniz argues in much the same way in an appendix to Essais de theodicée, titled Remarques sur le livre de l’origine du mal, publié depuis peu en Angleterre: “No agent is capable of acting without being predisposed to what the action demands; and the reasons or inclinations derived from good or evil are the dispositions that enable the soul to decide between various courses…the truth is that the soul, or the thinking substance, understands the reasons and feels the inclinations, and decides according to the predominance of the representations modifying its active force, in order to shape the action.” (Leibniz (1978, 416); Leibniz (2005, 421)).

  43. 43.

    “Determinatur animus ad eam seriem cogitationum quae in se spectata perfectior est” (A VI, 4, 1430).

  44. 44.

    On the development of Leibniz’s views of harmony, see Mercer (2001, 208–220).

  45. 45.

    Leibniz also argues that the series of things is not necessary by an absolute necessity as there are many other series that are possible, i.e. intelligible, even if they are not actually performed. See Leibniz (2005, 119).

  46. 46.

    See also Di Bella (2005, 127).

  47. 47.

    For Descartes, passions are related to the fundamental difference between the soul and the body. See Passions, §2 (CSM I, 328).

  48. 48.

    On this topic, see Rutherford and Cover (2005).

  49. 49.

    Martha Kneale presents five different definitions on action and passion which she suggest were influenced by reading Spinoza. See Kneale (1976, 220–222).

  50. 50.

    In Leibniz’s mature view, the process of action and passion are atemporal although he sometimes sounds a lot like Spinoza. For example, in NE II, xxi, 72 he says: “If we take ‘action’ to be an endeavor towards perfection, and ‘passion’ to be the opposite, then genuine substances are active only when their perceptions… are becoming better developed and more distinct, just as they are passive only when their perceptions are becoming more confused. Consequently, in substances which are capable of pleasure and pain every action is a move towards pleasure, every passion a move towards pain” (A VI, 6, 210; Leibniz (1996, 210)). See also Monadologie §49 and Principes de la nature et de la grâce, §3.

  51. 51.

    I would like to thank Andreas Blank and an anonymous reviewer for comments to this article. The research for it was made possible by a grant 137891 of the Academy of Finland.

References

  • Antognazza, Maria Rosa. 2008. Leibniz. An intellectual biography. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boros, Gábor. 2007. Leibniz on love. In The concept of love in 17th and 18th century philosophy, ed. Gábor Boros, Herman De Dijn and Martin Moors, 79–94. Leuven: Leuven University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Busche, Hubertus. 2004. Mind and body in the young Leibniz. In Individuals, mind and bodies: themes from Leibniz, ed. M. Carrara, A. M. Nunziante and G. Tomasi, 141–158. Stuttgart: Steiner.

    Google Scholar 

  • De Gaudemar, Martine. 2009. A few remarks on the Leibnizian conception of the mind in the “early writings” of Leibniz. In The philosophy of the young Leibniz, ed. Mark Kulstad, Mogens Lærke and David Snyder, 177–188. Stuttgart: Steiner.

    Google Scholar 

  • Descartes, René. 1984–1985. The philosophical writings of Descartes, I-II. Trans. John Cottingham, Robert Stoothoff and Dugald Murdoch. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. (CSM)

    Google Scholar 

  • Di Bella, Stefano. 2005. The science of the individual: Leibniz’s ontology of individual substance. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Di Bella, Stefano. 2006. Le De affectibus leibnizien: de la dynamique des passions à la constitution de la substance individuelle. In Les passions à l’âge classique. Theorie et critiques des passions, II, dir. Pierre-François Moreau, 193–208. Paris: Presses universitaires de France.

    Google Scholar 

  • Garber, Daniel. 1998. Soul and mind: life and thought in the seventeenth century. In The Cambridge history of seventeenth-century philosophy, ed. Daniel Garber and Michael Ayers, 759–795. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Garber, Daniel. 2009a. Leibniz: body, substance, monad. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Garber, Daniel. 2009b. What did Leibniz learn about body in January 1678? In The philosophy of the young Leibniz, ed. Mark Kulstad, Mogens Lærke and David Snyder, 67–81. Stuttgart: Steiner.

    Google Scholar 

  • Giolito, Christophe. 1996. L’éradication d’une argumentation cartésienne: Leibniz à la lecture des Passions de l’âme. In Descartes et l’argumentation philosophique, dir. Frédéric Cossutta, 187–216. Paris: Presses universitaires de France.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldenbaum, Ursula. 2009. It’s love! Leibniz’s foundation of natural law as the outcome of his struggle with Hobbes’ and Spinoza’s naturalism. In The philosophy of the young Leibniz, ed. Mark Kulstad, Mogens Lærke and David Snyder, 189–201. Stuttgart: Steiner.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hobbes, Thomas. 1839. The English works of Thomas Hobbes of Malmesbury (I & III), ed. William Molesworth. London: Bohn. (EW)

    Google Scholar 

  • James, Susan. 1997. Passion and action. The emotions in seventeenth-century philosophy. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jones, Matthew L. 2006. The good life in the scientific revolution. Descartes, Pascal, Leibniz and the cultivation of virtue. Chicago: Chicago University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kneale, Martha. 1976. Leibniz and Spinoza on Activity. In Leibniz: a collection of critical essays, ed. Harry G. Frankfurt, 215–238. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm. 2005. Confessio philosophi. Papers concerning the problem of evil, 1671–1678. Trans., ed. and with an Intr. Robert C. Sleigh, Jr. New Haven and London: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm. 1996. New Essays on Human Understanding, trans. and ed. Peter Remnant and Jonathan Bennett. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm. 1971. Nouvelles lettres et opuscules inédits. Intr. Louis Alexandre Foucher de Careil. Hildesheim and New York: Olms (1857).

    Google Scholar 

  • Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm. 1989. Philosophical Essays. Edited and Translated by Roger Ariew and Daniel Garber. Indianapolis: Hackett.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm. 1976. Philosophical papers and letters. A selection trans. and ed., with and intr. Leroy E. Loemker. 2nd ed. Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm. 1978. Die philosophischen Schriften VI, hrsg. C. I. Gerhardt. Olms: Hildesheim.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm. 1994. La réforme de la dynamique: De corporum concursu (1678) et autres textes inédits, ed. and trans. Michel Fichant. Paris: Vrin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm. 1923-. Sämtliche Schriften und Briefe, Reihe I-VII. Herausgegeben von der Berlin-Brandenburgischen Akademie der Wissenschaften und der Akademie der Wissenschaften in Göttingen. Berlin: Akademie Verlag. (A)

    Google Scholar 

  • Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm. 1992. De summa rerum. Metaphysical papers, 1675–1676, trans. with an intr. G. H. R. Parkinson. New Haven and London: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm. 1985. Theodicy. Essays on the goodness of God, the freedom of man and the origin of evil. Ed. with an intr. Austin Farrer. Trans. E. M. Huggard. La Salle: Open Court (1951).

    Google Scholar 

  • Losonsky, Michael. 2001. Enlightenment and action from Descartes to Kant. Passionate thought. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • MacDonald Ross, George. 2007. Leibniz’s Debt to Hobbes. In Leibniz and the English-Speaking World, ed. by Pauline Phemister and Stuart Brown. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mercer, Christia. 2001. Leibniz’s metaphysics. Its origins and development. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Nadler, Steven. 2006. Spinoza’s Ethics. An introduction. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pasnau, Robert. 2011. Metaphysical themes 1274–1671. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Princess Elisabeth of Bohemia and René Descartes. 2007. The correspondence between Princess Elisabeth of Bohemia and René Descartes. Ed. and trans. Lisa Shapiro. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roinila, Markku. 2006. Deliberation and self-improvement in Leibniz. In Einheit in der Vielheit. VIII. Internationaler Leibniz-Kongress, Vorträge, hrsg. Herbert Breger, Jürgen Herbst and Sven Erdner, 856–863. Hannover: G. W. Leibniz Gesellschaft.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rutherford, Donald and Cover, J. A. (eds.). 2005. Leibniz. Nature and freedom. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schepers, Heinrich. 2003. De affectibus. Leibniz an der Schwelle zur Monadologie. Seine Vorarbeiten zum logischen Aufbau der möglichen Welten. Studia Leibnitiana 35: 133–161.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schneewind, Jerome B. 2006. The active powers. In The Cambridge history of eighteenth-century philosophy, ed. Knud Haakonssen, 557–607. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Spinoza, Baruch. 1985. The Collected Works of Spinoza, ed. and trans. Edwin Curley. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vargas, Evelyn. 2011. Perceiving machines: Leibniz’s teleological approach to perception. In Machines of nature and corporeal substances in Leibniz, ed. Justin E. H. Smith and Ohad Nachtomy, 175–186. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, Catherine. 1997. Motion, sensation, and the infinite: The lasting impression of Hobbes on Leibniz. British journal for the history of philosophy 5: 339–351.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Markku Roinila .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2015 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Roinila, M. (2015). Affects and Activity in Leibniz’s De affectibus . In: Nita, A. (eds) Leibniz’s Metaphysics and Adoption of Substantial Forms. The New Synthese Historical Library, vol 74. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-9956-0_6

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics