Skip to main content

Introduction. Leibniz’s Metaphysics and the Adoption of Substantial Forms

  • Chapter
Leibniz’s Metaphysics and Adoption of Substantial Forms

Part of the book series: The New Synthese Historical Library ((SYNL,volume 74))

Abstract

In his letter to John Frederick, Duke of Brunswick-Hanover, from 1679, Leibniz embraces an apparently scholastic theory of substantial forms about which modern philosophers were very critical. This is the reason why the years 1678–1679 are important in Leibniz’s development, for it was during this time that Leibniz, thinking within the frame of substantial forms, developed the theory of corporeal substance and laid the groundwork for his theory of monadology.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. 1.

    Leibniz to John Frederick, Duke of Brunswick-Hanover (1679); A II, 1, 749–759, especially p. 754; L 259–262, especially p. 261.

  2. 2.

    Aristotle, Metaphysics, VII, 1, 1028b.

  3. 3.

    See Leibniz’s letter to Remond from 10 January 1714, GP III, 606.

  4. 4.

    Descartes, Meditationes de prima philosophia III.

  5. 5.

    See Arnauld’s objection to Meditationes de prima philosophia 4.3.

  6. 6.

    Roger Ariew, Descartes and the Last Scholastics (1999, 155–171).

  7. 7.

    Confessio naturae contra atheistas, GP IV, 109.

  8. 8.

    Theoria motus abstracti, GP IV, 230.

  9. 9.

    De summa rerum, A VI, 3, 474–475.

  10. 10.

    De summa rerum, A VI, 3, 474.

  11. 11.

    De summa rerum, A VI, 3, 477; Parkinson 31.

  12. 12.

    “It is clear from this that there is a world a creatures, living beings, animals, entelechies, souls, in the smallest particle of matter” (Monadology 66, GP VI, 618; L 650).

  13. 13.

    Theoria motus abstracti 17; GP IV, 230; L 141. See also To Arnauld, November 1671, GP I, 71; L 149.

  14. 14.

    De summa rerum, A VI, 3, 524; Parkinson 85.

  15. 15.

    To Arnauld, November 1671, GP I, 71; L 149.

  16. 16.

    Notes on the reply of Foucher to the criticism of his criticism of the Recherche de la verite, L 155.

  17. 17.

    VE 651–652. In order to see more details, see Fichant (1998, 196–197).

  18. 18.

    Fichant (1998, 2021), Garber (2009, 225–226).

  19. 19.

    To Duke John Frederick, 1679; A II, 1, 754; L 261.

  20. 20.

    DM 10–12; GP IV, 434–436; L 308–309.

  21. 21.

    NS 2–3; GP IV, 478–479; L 453–454.

  22. 22.

    To Remond, January 10, 1714; GP III, 605–607; L 654–655.

References

  • Fichant, Michel. 1998. Science et métaphysique dans Descartes et Leibniz. Paris: PUF.

    Google Scholar 

  • Garber, Daniel. 2009. Leibniz: Body, Substance, Monad. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Adrian Nita .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2015 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Nita, A. (2015). Introduction. Leibniz’s Metaphysics and the Adoption of Substantial Forms. In: Nita, A. (eds) Leibniz’s Metaphysics and Adoption of Substantial Forms. The New Synthese Historical Library, vol 74. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-9956-0_1

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics