Skip to main content

Abstract

In 1766, parliament passed the Declaratory Act, proclaiming that Westminster had full power to make law binding the colonies “in all cases whatsoever.” The notion of parliamentary sovereignty which it reflected was one generally accepted by eighteenth century English lawyers. The triumph of parliament in the revolution of 1688 was supposed to have secured liberty from despotism; and the language of English politics was henceforth much less legalistic than it had been in the seventeenth century. The structure of the balanced constitution was widely lauded, receiving Montesquieu’s seal of approval. Anxiety about arbitrary government now centred not on the structure of government, but on its operation. Opposition politicians feared that patronage and electoral corruption would increase the influence of the crown and its ministers, and thereby upset the balance. In this context, the rhetoric of civic virtue became more prominent, as “country party” ideologists drawing on the works of Machiavelli and James Harrington urged active political participation to prevent corruption (see Pocock 2003; Robbins 1959; Dickinson 1979). Politicians who argued that parliament was bound by the constitution understood it more in terms of its political spirit than in strictly legal terms. For Radical agitators, meanwhile, the prime remedy to political ills was not to declare limitations on the power of parliament, but to ensure greater representation of the people in the institutions. From the other side of the Atlantic, however, things looked altogether different. To Americans, parliament in the mid-eighteenth century came to look like an institutional equivalent of the Stuart kings, willing to interfere arbitrarily with their property rights. The Declaratory Act brought to a head a clash between two distinct visions of the common law, derived from the same tradition: an English positivist view centred on parliamentary sovereignty, and an American conception, which invoked fundamental, customary rights, which could not be removed by the legislature (Greene 1986a; Greene 1994; Reid 1986; Reid 1987; Reid 1991; Reid 1993).

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 219.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 299.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 279.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Andrea Padovani .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2007 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Padovani, A., Stein, P.G. (2007). The Age of the Federalists. In: Padovani, A., Stein, P.G. (eds) A Treatise of Legal Philosophy and General Jurisprudence. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-9880-8_9

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics