Skip to main content

Part of the book series: Analecta Husserliana ((ANHU,volume 60))

  • 178 Accesses

Abstract

In 1827 the great Geneva botanist Auguste-Pyrame de Candolle devoted a chapter of his massive Organographie végétale to the question of the individuality of plants and reached conclusions which were highly paradoxical to common sense:

According to the first opinion, which we habitually follow in ordinary language, a willow, a cherry tree, a cabbage, etc. are so many unique individuals; but, as soon as we examine them more closely we find that these so-called individuals are strangely divisible: almost all of their parts are susceptible to being at will separated from the whole, and of forming a new individual (being). This division can even be stretched indefinitely and there are some individuals, such as for instance the first weeping willow to be brought to Europe (I choose this example because we only have one of the sexes and it has never been sown) that, as I say, simply by division has produced all the weeping willows existing in Europe today and will produce all the ones we will want to produce in the future. From a physiological point of view all these willows are then portions of only one individual. In this sense, the word individual would be even less exact than if we consider a granite mountain as a mineralogical individual that man can at his will divide into as many fragments as he wants by crushing the rocks.1

De Candolle also gave news of the existence of animals that, though apparently unique, upon a closer examination reveal that they are nothing but agglomerates that have a life in common, such as botrylles, pyrosomes and maybe the hydras and fresh water polyps that, after Trembley’s observations, were of such interest in the XVIIIth century. A superficial observation of vegetable organisms and of these extremely primitive animals would only extend to them the characteristics belonging to animals of a higher order which, like ourselves, since they have only one centre of nutrition and life, cannot be divided into further individuals.2

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 169.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 219.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 219.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. Auguste-Pyrame de Candolle, Organographie végétale, ou description raisonnée des organes des plantes (Paris, 1827), henceforth OV, Vol. II, pp. 228–229.

    Google Scholar 

  2. A.-P. de Candolle, Théorie élémentaire de la botanique ou exposition des principes de la classification naturelle et de l’art de décrire et d’étudier le végétaux (Paris, 1813), p. 14; cfr OV, II,p. 228. The cloning of animals from cells of adult individuals, which had been announced while this essay was being written, shows that de Candolle’s declarations about the individuality of vegetables can in fact be applied to the entire would of living organisms.

    Google Scholar 

  3. OV,I, pp. 11–12.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Theodor Schwann, Mikroskopische Untersuuchungen uben die Uebereinstimmung in der Struktur und dem Wachstum der Thiere und Pflanzen (Berlin, 1839), henceforth MU,pp. iv—v.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Schwann, MU,p. vi.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Schwann, MU,pp. vii—viii.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Schwann, MU, pp. x—xiii.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Schwann, MU,p. xiii.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Schwann, MU,p. 45.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Schwann, MU,pp. 193–194.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Johann Wolfgang Goethe, Hymnus der Natur (Die Natur Aphoristisch),in: Gasmtausgabe der Werke und Schriften in zweiundzwanzig Bänden (Stuttgart, 1959), henceforth GW,XVIII, p. 60.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Goethe, Entwurf zu: Die Absicht eingeleitet (about 1800) in: GW,XVIII, p. 867.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Goethe, ibid.,in: GW,XVIII, p. 867.

    Google Scholar 

  14. See my essay “Formbildung, Zufall und Notwendigkeit, Schelling und die Naturwissenschaften um 1800” in: Schelling und die Selbstorganisation. Neue Forschungsperspektiven, Selbstorganisation. Jahrbuch für Komplexität in den NaturSozial-und Geistewissenschaften,Band 5, ed. Marie-Louise Heuser-Kessler and Wilhelm G. Jacobs (Berlin: 1994), henceforth FZN,pp. 107–108. See also my essay “La vita come pluralità senziente. La scuola medica stahliana e il suo influsso sulla filosofia del secondo Settecento” (Life as a Sentient Plurality. The Stahalian Medical School and Its Influence on Philosophy in the Second Half of the 18th C.), in Filosofia e Teologia, l sensi della vita,2/96 (Naples), pp. 276–291.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Baruch Spinoza, Ethica,Italian translation by Gaetano Durante (Florence, 1963), henceforth E,p. 141.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Spinoza, E,Pars II, Lemma IV, p. 143.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Ernst Mach, Die Mechanik in ihrer Entwickelung. Historisch-kritisch dargestellt (Leipzig, 1897), henceforth ME,pp. 196–199.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Spinoza, E,Pars II, Lemma VII, p. 145.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Spinoza, E,Pars I, Prop. XV, Scholium, p. 41.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Mach, ME,211; for the above see p. 210.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Spinoza, E,Pars II, Prop. XII, p. 131; Prop. XXIV, pp. 167–169.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Spinoza, E,Pars II, Prop. XXIV, pp. 167–169.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Spinoza, E,Pars II, Prop. XXIV, pp. 167–169.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Spinoza, E,Pars II, Prop. XLV, Scholium, p. 209; as for the above, see the enunciation and demonstration of same proposition; also Pars V, Prop. XXIX, Scholium, p. 627.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Spinoza, E,Pars I, Prop. XXIV, and particularly the Corollarium, pp. 59–61.

    Google Scholar 

  26. Spinoza, E,Pars V, Prop. XXXVI, pp. 635–637.

    Google Scholar 

  27. Spinoza, E,Pars V, Prop. XX, Scholium, pp. 613–615.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Friedrich Wilhelm Josef Schelling, Sämmtliche Werke (Stuttgart-Augusta, 1856–1861), henceforth SW, III, p. 22.

    Google Scholar 

  29. Schelling, SW, p. 23, n. 1.

    Google Scholar 

  30. Schelling, SW,p. 18, n. 2.

    Google Scholar 

  31. Schelling, SW, p. 43.

    Google Scholar 

  32. Moiso, FZN,pp. 106–110.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Schelling, SW, III, pp. 174–175, n. 3.

    Google Scholar 

  34. Schelling, SW,pp. 176–177.

    Google Scholar 

  35. Matthias Jakob Schleiden, Schellings und Hegels Verhältnis zur Naturwissenschaft (Leipzig, 1844). A new edition with an important introduction by Olaf Breidbach has appeared recently (Weinheim, 1988).

    Google Scholar 

  36. M. J. Schleiden, Grundzüge der Wissenschaftlichen Botanik nebst einer Metodologischen Einleitung als Anleitung zum Studium der Pflanze (Leipzig, 184), henceforth GWB, I, pp. 28–29.

    Google Scholar 

  37. Schleiden, GWB, I, pp. 18–19.

    Google Scholar 

  38. Schleiden, GWB, p. 20.

    Google Scholar 

  39. Friedrich Nietzsche, Nachgelassene Fragmente,in: Kritische Studienausgabe,ed. Giorgio Colli and Mazzino Montinari (Munich/Berlin/New York, 1988),henceforth KSA,Vol. II, fragm 41/11/, Aug.—Sep. 1885, pp. 687–688.

    Google Scholar 

  40. Nietzsche, KSA, Vol. 12, fragm 2 /92/, Herbst 1885-Herbst 1886, pp. 106–107.

    Google Scholar 

  41. Nietzsche, KSA, Vol. 12, fragm. 2 /87/, Herbst 1885-Herbst 1886, pp. 104–105.

    Google Scholar 

  42. Nietzsche, KSA, Vol. 12, fragm. 1 /128/, Herbst 1885-Herbst 1886, p. 41.

    Google Scholar 

  43. Nietzsche, KSA, Vol. 11, fragm. 36 /23/, June—July 1885, p. 561.

    Google Scholar 

  44. An enlightening interpretation has been offered by Jacques Derrida in “Ousia et grammé”, now in Marges de la philosophie (Paris, 1979). See for example, p. 62: “So Aristotle maintained that the now is in some way the same, in some other way the non-same […], that time is continuous according to the now and divided according to the now”.

    Google Scholar 

  45. Nietzsche, KSA, Vol. 11, fragm. 36 /25/, June—July 1885, pp. 561–562.

    Google Scholar 

  46. Nietzsche, KSA, Vol. 11, fragm. 36 /27/, June—July 1885, p. 562.

    Google Scholar 

  47. Goethe, Problem und Erwiderung, in GW, XIX, pp. 347–348.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1999 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Moiso, F. (1999). Nature and Individuality. In: Tymieniecka, AT. (eds) Life — The Outburst of Life in the Human Sphere. Analecta Husserliana, vol 60. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-2083-0_2

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-2083-0_2

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-481-5058-8

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-017-2083-0

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics