Skip to main content

Part of the book series: Analecta Husserliana ((ANHU,volume 59))

Abstract

What does “imagination” mean? Strawson noticed that “the uses, and applications, of the terms ‘image’, ‘imagine’, ‘imagination’, and so forth make up a very diverse and scattered family”.1 Edward Casey is also right when he adds that “the very multiplicity of such accounts suggests that there are as many kinds of imagination as there are explanations or descriptions of it”.2 In this paper I will argue that the phenomenological analysis of imaginative phenomena worked out by Edmund Husserl in the course of his philosophical career on the one hand gives us a clue to an understanding of these “scattered” phenomena in terms of a unified field and on the other provides us with grounds for the claim that, prevailing Western philosophical attitudes notwithstanding, the cognitive performance of imaginative acts cannot be ignored.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 169.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 219.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 219.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. P. F. Strawson, “Imagination and Perception,” in Experience and Theory, ed. L. Foster and J. W. Swanson (London: Duckworth, 1970), p. 31.

    Google Scholar 

  2. E. S. Casey, Imagining. A Phenomenological Study (Bloomington/London: Indiana University Press, 1976), p. 5.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Cf. J.-P. Sartre, L’imagination (Paris: Presses Universitaires de France, 1965e), pp. 146–148.

    Google Scholar 

  4. E. Tugendhat, Der Wahrheitsbegriff bei Husserl und Heidegger (Berlin: de Gruyter, 19702), p. 27.

    Google Scholar 

  5. E. Husserl, Phantasie, Bildbewußtsein, Erinnerung. Zur Phänomenologie der anschaulichen Vergegenwärtigungen. Texte aus dem Nachlaß (1898–1925), ed. E. Marbach (The Hague: Nijhoff, 1980), “Husserliana” XXIII, p. 6.

    Google Scholar 

  6. E. Husserl, Ideen zu einer reinen Phänomenologie und phänomenologischen Philosophie, First Book, Allgemeine Einführung in die reine Phänomenologie, Part One, ed. K. Schuhmann (The Hague: Nijhoff, 1976), “Husserliana” IIV1, p. 90.

    Google Scholar 

  7. On the following cf. ibid, p. 252; E. Husserl, Erste Philosophie (1923/24), second part, Theorie der phänomenologischen Reduktion, ed. R. Boehm (The Hague: Nijhoff, 1959), “Husserliana” VIII, pp. 111–112; Husserl, Phantasie, Bildbewußtsein Erinnerung,op. cit., pp. 18–20, 29.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Husserl, Phantasie, Bildbewußtsein, Erinnerung, op. cit., p. 19.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Cf. R. Bernet, I. Kern, and E. Marbach, Edmund Husserl. Darstellung seines Denkens (Hamburg: Meiner, 1989), p. 140; M. M. Saraiva, L’imagination selon Husserl (The Hague: Nijoff, 1970), pp. 93–95.

    Google Scholar 

  10. The thread of this inquiry is to be found in the analysis that Husserl developed in the lectures of 1905 on “Phantasy and Image-Consciousness,” now edited in Phantasie, Bildbewußtsein, Erinnerung, op. cit., pp. 1–108.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Cf. E. Husserl, Erfahrung und Urteil. Untersuchungen zur Genealogie der Logik, ed. L. Landgrebe (Hamburg: Meiner, 19856), pp. 359–360.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Cf. E. Husserl, Formale und transzendentale Logik. Versuch einer Kritik der logi- schen Vernunft,ed. P. Janssen (The Hague: Nijhoff, 1974), “Husserliana” XVII, p. 242.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Cf. E. Husserl, Analysen zur passiven Synthesis. Aus Vorlesungs-und Forschungsmanuskripten. 1918–1926, ed. M. Fleischer (The Hague: Nijhoff, 1966), “Husserliana” XI, p. 34: “The very same stock of hyletic data is the common base of two superimposed apprehensions. [chwr(133)1 They are in conflict one with the other, each of them in it own way is strongly motivated and as it were `claimed’ by the perceptual situation up to now and its intentional content.”

    Google Scholar 

  14. Husserl, Phantasie, Bildbewußtsein, Erinnerung, op. cit., p. 48.

    Google Scholar 

  15. In order to understand more fully how this principle of consistency works, it may be worthwhile to refer to Hume’s argument with regard to the nature of miracles: a miracle can in no way exist, since we accept believing in a “wonder” only when not to believe in it would mean to admit something even more wonderful (Cfr. D. Hume, Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding, Vol. IV of D. Hume, The Philosophical Works, ed. Th. Green and Th. Grose, [Aalen: Scientia, 1964], Sect. X).

    Google Scholar 

  16. Cf. Husserl, Phantasie, Bildewußtsein, Erinnerung, op. cit., p. 77: the question “Why do we set value on continuity instead of discontinuity?” remains unanswered.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Cf. ibid., p. 40: “The oft-cited example of a wax-works shows that if the imaginative function is put to one side, an imaginative phenomenon transforms itself and gives rise instead to a common perceptual apprehension, and perhaps even into a perception in the strict sense of the term, with a basis in normal belief. We might at first mistake the wax model for a person. In this case we have a normal perception, though it reveals itself afterwards as a mistake. When we suddenly become aware of the deception, a consciousness of an imaginative kind occurs.”

    Google Scholar 

  18. Cf. ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Cf. ibid., p. 47.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Cf. ibid., pp. 482–485.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Ibid., p. 47.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Ibid., p. 489.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Ibid., p. 66.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Cf. Husserl, Ideen I, op. cit., pp. 247–248; Husserl, Phantasie, Bildbewußtsein, Erinnerung, op. cit., p. 508.

    Google Scholar 

  26. Husserl, Ideen I, op. cit., p. 252.

    Google Scholar 

  27. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Cf. Husserl, Phantasie, Bildbewußtsein, Erinnerung, op. cit., pp. 479–480, 486–491.

    Google Scholar 

  29. Ibid., p. 480.

    Google Scholar 

  30. Cf. Husserl, Ideen I, op. cit.,p. 90: “In my lectures delivered at Göttingen (since the summer term of 1904, in fact) I have substituted the inadequate exposition which I gave in the Logical Investigations with an improved version of the same”

    Google Scholar 

  31. Cf., for instance, Husserl, Phantasie, Bildbewußtsein, Erinnerung, op. cit., pp. 83, 150, 161.

    Google Scholar 

  32. Ibid., p. 66.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Cf. Ibid., p. 67, note 1.

    Google Scholar 

  34. Ibid., p. 76.

    Google Scholar 

  35. Husserl’s conclusion leaves us in no doubt: “Of course there is no real insertion of phantasy in perception as such, as if a mixture could really originate from it. [chwr(133)] Synthesis leads the corresponding parts of both fields to a synthetical unity, [chwr(133)] but this unity in the intellective consciousness of transition is not the unity of appearance” (ibid., cf. also pp. 67–68, 74, 86).

    Google Scholar 

  36. Ibid., p. 67.

    Google Scholar 

  37. Cf. Husserl, Erfahrung und Urteil, op. cit., §§ 36–39, and the manuscript these paragraphs are based on (MS. M III 3 VII: “Wirklichkeit und Phantasie. Untersuchungen zum Problem der Individuation”). M. M. Saraiva’s synthesis is also particularly well-done. (cf. L’imagination selon Husserl, op. cit., p. 223).

    Google Scholar 

  38. Cf. Husserl, Phantasie, Bildbewußtsein, Erinnerung, op. cit., p. 67.

    Google Scholar 

  39. Ibid., p. 513.

    Google Scholar 

  40. Cf. ibid., pp. 85–87; Saraiva, L’imagination selon Husserl, op. cit., pp. 130–133.

    Google Scholar 

  41. Husserl, Phantasie, Bildbewußtsein, Erinnerung, op. cit., p. 100.

    Google Scholar 

  42. Cf. for instance ibid., p. 191: “Memory can be used just as well as imagination.”

    Google Scholar 

  43. Cf. Marbach, Einleitung, op. cit., pp. LXIII—LXV.

    Google Scholar 

  44. Husserl, Phantasie, Bildbewußtsein, Erinnerung, op. cit., p. 294.

    Google Scholar 

  45. Ibid., p. 296.

    Google Scholar 

  46. Ibid.p. 298. Here a fleeting terminological innacuracy leads Husserl to use the terms “actuality” and “inactuality” instead of “positionality” and “neutrality.” Cf. E. Husserl Zur Phänomenlogie des inneren Zeitbewußtseins (1893–1917) ed. R. Boehm (The Hague: Nijhoff, 1966), “Husserliana” X, p. 102: “`Actuality’ and `inactuality’ here have the same meaning as `potentiality’ and `neutrality’ in the sense of the Ideen.” On these topics cf. also G. Piana Elementi di una dottrina dell’esperienza (Milan: Il Saggiatore, 1979), p. 114.

    Google Scholar 

  47. Cf. Husserl, Ideen I, op. cit.,p. 250; Husserl, Erste Philosophie, op. cit., pp. 112–113; E. Husserl, Phantasie, Bildewußtsein, Erinnerung, op. cit., p. 322; Bernet, Kern, and Marbach, Edmund Husserl. Darstellung seines Denkens, op. cit., pp. 137–138; Saraiva, L’imagination selon Husserl, op. cit., pp. 204–216. On the way this idea matured in the course of time, see Husserl, Phantasie, Bildbewußtsein, Erinnerung, op. cit., pp. 217, 245–248, 253–255, 277, 281–282. To define phantasy as a neutralized presentification is to put it in the same frame of reference as image-consciousness, which is a neutralized presentation. According to this argument, Belussi’s distinction between a-positionality (image-consciousness) and quasi-positionality (phantasy) is unjustifiable (cf. F. Belussi, Die modaltheoretischen Grundlagen der husserlschen Phänomenologie [Freiburg/Munich: Alber, 1990], pp. 251–260).

    Google Scholar 

  48. Husserl, Phantasie, Bildbewußtsein, Erinnerung, op. cit., p. 77.

    Google Scholar 

  49. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  50. Cf. Husserl himself: “Genetically speaking a discredit [scil. neutralization] of this nature is very important. A phantasy-will, namely a discredited one, yields no action, a phantasy-judgement yields no willing, etc.” (Husserl, Phantasie, Bildbewußtsein, Erinnerung, op. cit., p. 104). A similar argument — but in a different context — is put forward by Jean-Paul Sartre in L’imaginaire. Psychologie phénoménologique de l’imagination (Paris: Gallimard, 1940), p. 158.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1999 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Volonté, P. (1999). Imagination: Rescuing What is Going to be Cancelled. In: Tymieniecka, AT. (eds) Life Scientific Philosophy, Phenomenology of Life and the Sciences of Life. Analecta Husserliana, vol 59. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-2079-3_30

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-2079-3_30

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-481-5057-1

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-017-2079-3

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics