Skip to main content

Lamarck Contre Darwin, Reduction Versus Statistics: Conceptual Issues in the Controversy over Directed Mutagenesis in Bacteria

  • Chapter
Organism and the Origins of Self

Part of the book series: Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science ((BSPS,volume 129))

Abstract

The purpose of this paper is to examine some conceptual aspects of the controversy over the possibility of directed mutagenesis in bacteria that has erupted since the publication of some provocative results by Cairns, Overbaugh and Miller [2]. The paper by Foster in this volume takes up more “empirical” issues, surveys the experimental literature, and offers occasionally different interpretations of the results. The conceptual issues that are important here occur at least at two levels, the first of which is, in a sense, metaphysical and the second, epistemological. First, the possibility of directed mutagenesis challenges the core of the current orthodox framework of evolutionary theory. Thus the sense in which mutations can indeed be “directed” is of considerable foundational importance to evolutionary theory. To the extent that such foundational issues are “metaphysical,” in the sense that they concern the most general and universal underlying features of the world explored by science, these conceptual issues properly belong to metaphysics. Second, much of the evidence on which the current controversy thrives is statistical evidence about the number of mutant bacteria. Experimental methods which rely on such evidence are non-reductive in the sense that they attempt to understand what occurs at a lower level—for instance, that within a bacterial cell—by making observations at a higher level—in the example, that of the cell.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 169.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 219.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 219.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Cairns, J., J. Overbaugh, and S. Miller. The origin of mutants. Nature 335: 142–145, 1988.

    PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  2. Cairns, J. et al., The origin of mutants. Nature 335: 142–145, 1988;

    PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  3. Sarkar, S. Reductionism and molecular biology: a reappraisal. Ph. D. Dissertation. Department of Philosophy, University of Chicago, 1989.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Sarkar, S., Reductionism and molecular biology: a reappraisal. Ph. D. Dissertation. Department of Philosophy, University of Chicago, 1989;

    Google Scholar 

  5. Kauffman, S.A. Articulation of parts explanation in biology and the rational search for them. Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science 8: 257–272, 1972;

    Google Scholar 

  6. Lewontin, R.C. The units of selection. Annual Review of Ecology and Systematics 1: 1–18, 1970.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Lewontin, R.C., The units of selection. Annual Review of Ecology and Systematics 1: 1–18, 1970, p. 1.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Lewontin, R.C., The units of selection. Annual Review of Ecology and Systematics 1: 1–18, 1970, p. 1.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Note that this explication of evolution by natural selection makes no mention of what the individuals of the population are. They could be molecules, organelles within a cell, cells, individuals (which in multi-cellular organisms would not be identical with cells), kins, groups, populations or species. What the appropriate units of selection are is a matter of considerable biological and philosophical controversy. In the case of bacteria, which is all that is directly of concern in this article, the levels of cells and individuals are identical thus partly avoiding this controversy. For details of this controversy, see Brandon, R. N. and R. N. Burian (eds.). Genes, Organisms, Populations: Controversies Over the Units of Selection. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1984.

    Google Scholar 

  10. See Wimsatt, W.C. Randomness and perceived randomness in evolutionary biology. Synthese 43: 287–329, 1980, for an attempt to analyze the difficulties with the notion of randomness appropriate for evolutionary biology.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Kimura (Kimura, M. The Neutral Theory of Molecular Evolution. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1983), in his more polemical moments seems to suggest such a viewpoint.

    Google Scholar 

  12. See Provine, W. The Origins of Theoretical Population Genetics. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1971, for details of this fascinating history.

    Google Scholar 

  13. See Maynard Smith, J. Evolutionary Genetics. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1989, for an emphasis on natural selection and

    Google Scholar 

  14. Lewontin’s review (Lewontin, R.C.A natural selection. Nature 339: 107, 1989) for a critique.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Haldane, J.B.S. The Causes of Evolution. London: Harper & Brothers, 1932;

    Google Scholar 

  16. Huxley, J. 1942. Evolution: The Modern Synthesis. London: George Allen & Unwin.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Not one of the figures discussed by Hull (Hull, D. Lamarck among the Anglos. In J.B. Lamarck, Zoological Philosophy. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1984, pp. xl—lxvi) in his colorful, though short, account of the history of neo-Lamarkism seems to have suggested that all mutations were directed.

    Google Scholar 

  18. For details of Lysenkoist claims, see Hudson, P.S., and R.H. Richens. The New Genetics in the Soviet Union. Cambridge: Imperial Bureau of Plant Breeding and Genetics, 1946.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Among those at least partly sympathetic to Lysenko’s claims, only Haldane (Haldane, J.B.S. Lysenko and genetics. Science and Society 4: 433–437, 1940) seems to have been fully clear that all that was needed to explain the kind of effects Lysenko claimed to be observing was that some mutations could be induced in such a fashion.

    Google Scholar 

  20. This strong notion of directedness has been championed by Lenski, R.E. Are some mutations directed? Trends in Ecology and Evolution 4: 148–150, 1989.

    PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  21. This weaker definition has been used by Sarkar, S. On the possibility of directed mutations in bacteria: statistical analyses and reductionist strategies. In PSA 1990. A. Fine, editor, 1990. Philosophy of Science Association, East Lansing. In press.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Many of the participants in the controversy would also reject the use of “neo-Lamarckism” on various grounds including vagueness. However, vagueness, at least, has been removed if the distinctions and definitions elaborated in the text are clear enough. For responses to some other objections to the use of “neo-Lamarckism,” see Sarkar, S., On the possibility of directed mutations in bacteria: statistical analyses and reductionist strategies. In PSA 1990. A. Fine, editor, 1990. Philosophy of Science Association, East Lansing. In press.

    Google Scholar 

  23. However, for an important treatment of the possible inheritance of acquired characteristics where the concept is not used vaguely, see Jablonka, E., and M.J. Lamb. The inheritance of acquired epigenetic variations. Journal of Theoretical Biology 139: 69–83, 1989.

    PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  24. Cullis, C.A. The generation of somatic and heritable variation in response to stress. American Naturalist 130: S62–S73, 1987.

    Google Scholar 

  25. The reasons given for not using the notion of the inheritance of acquired characteristics are also those for not using another related distinction due to Mayr, namely, that between “hard” and “soft” inheritance (Mayr, E. The Growth of Biological Thought. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1982), pp. 687–689). These choices, however, are made for the purpose of conceptual clarification. No suggestion is being made here that these other construals of the differences between neo-Darwinism and neo-Lamarckism can be avoided when the history of these disputes, especially during the first half of this century, is considered.

    Google Scholar 

  26. Lamarck, J.B. Zoological Philosophy. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1984, p. 113.

    Google Scholar 

  27. Darwin, C. On the Origin of Species. London: John Murray, 1859.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Darwin, C., On the Origin of Species. London: John Murray, 1859, pp. 134–139.

    Google Scholar 

  29. Mayr lists nine other examples (Mayr, E. Introduction. In C. Darwin, On the Origin of Species. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1964, p.xxvi).

    Google Scholar 

  30. See Eiseley, L. Darwin’s Century. New York: Doubleday Anchor, 1961, and

    Google Scholar 

  31. Ruse, M., The Darwinian Revolution: Science Red in Tooth and Claw. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1979, for details of these developments.

    Google Scholar 

  32. See, for example, Weismann, A. Das Keimplasma: Eine Theorie der Vererbung. Jena: Gustav Fischer, 1892.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Romanes, G.J. Life and Letters. London: Longmans, Green, 1896.

    Google Scholar 

  34. For details of this history, Sarkar, S, Reductionism and molecular biology: a reappraisal. Ph. D. Dissertation. Department of Philosophy, University of Chicago, 1989, and

    Google Scholar 

  35. Fischer, E.P., and C. Lipson. Thinking About Science: Max Delbrück and the Origins of Molecular Biology. New York: Knopf, 1988, and references therein.

    Google Scholar 

  36. Though the terms, “mutant” and “mutation” were routinely used for this transformation, it remained an open question whether these “mutations” were mutations of genes. In 1943, for example, Luria and Delbück carefully observe: “Naming such hereditary changes ‘mutations’ of course does not imply a detailed similarity with any of the classes of mutations that have been analyzed in terms of genes for higher organisms. The similarity may be merely a formal one (Luria, S.E., and M. Delbrück. Mutations of bacteria from virus sensitivity to virus resistance. Genetics 28: 491–511, 1943, p. 492).”

    PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  37. Even in the late 1950’s a few skeptics such as Hinshelwood (for example, in Dean, A.C.R., and C.N. Hinshelwood. Aspects of the problem of drug resistance in bacteria. In Drug Resistance in Microorganisms. G.E.W. Wolstenholme, and C.M. O’Connor, editors. London: J. & A. Churchill, 1957, pp. 4–24) would maintain that any reference to genes in bacteria would actually be a reference to complex chemical reaction networks.

    Google Scholar 

  38. d’Herelle, F. The Bacteriophage and Its Behavior. Baltimore: Williams and Wilkins, 1926;

    Google Scholar 

  39. Gratia, A. Studies on the d’Herelle phenomenon. Journal of Experimental Medicine 34: 115–131, 1921;

    PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  40. Burnet, F. M. “Smooth-rough” variation in bacteria in its relation to bacteriophage. Journal of Pathology and Bacteriology 32: 15–42, 1929.

    CAS  Google Scholar 

  41. Luria, S.E. and M. Delbrück, Mutations of bacteria from virus sensitivity to virus resistance. Genetics 28: 491–511, 1943, p. 492. According to Luria, he was led to the idea of the fluctuation test while watching the operation of slot machines during a faculty dance at the Bloomington Country Club in Indiana. If these machines were programmed to return money at random, the returns would form a Poisson distribution clustered around a mean and there would be virtually no jackpots. If, however, the machines were programmed so that they return occasional jackpots with many very tiny returns, the returns would fluctuate much more widely. The average return would be the same in both cases. The way in which the machines were programmed could only be determined by actually observing the actual distribution of the returns and not from the mean alone. Luria immediately applied this insight to the question of the distribution of mutants in bacteria.

    PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  42. For further details see Luria, S.E. A Slot Machine, a Broken Test Tube: An Autobiography. New York: Harper and Row, 1984, pp. 74–79.

    Google Scholar 

  43. Yang, Y.N., and P. Bruce Wright. Rough variation in V. cholerae and its relation to resistance to cholera-phage (Type A). Journal of Pathology and Bacteriology 38: 187–200, 1934.

    Google Scholar 

  44. Luria, S. E. and M. Delbruck (Mutations of bacteria from virus sensitivity to virus resistance. Genetics 28: 491–511, 1943, p. 492) do not cite them.

    PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  45. Neither do Newcombe, H. B. Origin of bacterial variants. Nature 164: 150–151, 1949,

    PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  46. Lederberg, J., and E. Lederberg. Replica plating and indirect selection of bacterial mutants. Journal of Bacteriology 63: 399–406, 1952, or

    PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  47. Cavalli-Sforza, L.L., and J. Lederberg. Isolation of preadaptive mutants by sib selection. Genetics 41: 367–381, 1956,

    PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  48. which were critical papers in the establishment of the neo-Darwinian view. Cavalli-Sforza and Lederberg do list them in their bibliography in an earlier paper (Cavalli-Sforza, L.L., and J. Lederberg. Genetics of resistance to bacterial inhibitors. In Symposium: Growth Inhibition and Chemotherapy. Rome: Istituto Superiore di Sanita, 1953, pp. 108–142) but do not discuss them in the text.

    Google Scholar 

  49. A recent article by Lederberg is responsible for drawing attention to the contribution of Yang and Bruce White (Lederberg, J. Replica plating and indirect selection of bacterial mutants: isolation of preadaptive mutants in bacteria by sib selection. Genetics 121: 395–399, 1989).

    PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  50. Luria, S.E. and M. Delbrück, Mutations of bacteria from virus sensitivity to virus resistance. Genetics 28: 491–511, 1943, p. 492, p. 493.

    PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  51. Luria, S.E. and M. Delbrück, Mutations of bacteria from virus sensitivity to virus resistance. Genetics 28: 491–511, 1943, p. 492, p. 493.

    PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  52. Lea, D.E., and C.A. Coulson. The distribution of the number of mutants in bacterial populations. Journal of Genetics 49: 264–285, 1949. As a historical curiosity, it is worth noting that it is possible that Fisher might have solved the Luria-Delbrück distribution first.

    Google Scholar 

  53. Crow (Crow, J.F., R.A. Fisher, a centenniel view. Genetics 124: 207–211, 1990)

    PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  54. recalls that while he found the Luria-Delbrück argument convincing, he thought that the mathematical treatment “shoddy and confusing (Crow, J.F., R.A. Fisher, a centenniel view. Genetics 124: 207–211, 1990 p. 210).”

    PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  55. Consequently, in 1946, he approached Fisher with the problem. Fisher “leaned back in his chair, thought for perhaps a minute, took a scrap of paper, and wrote a generating function (Crow, J.F., R.A. Fisher, a centenniel view. Genetics 124: 207–211, 1990 p. 210).” Crow, not understanding the formula yet, put that scrap of paper aside, intending to work on it later and then lost it!

    PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  56. Stewart, F., D. Gordon, and B. Levin. Fluctuation analysis: the probability distribution of the number of mutants under different conditions. Genetics 124: 175–185, 1990. There were many previous attempts to generalize the Luria-Delbrück distribution but none to this extent.

    PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  57. For example, phenotypic lag is considered in Armitage, P. The statistical theory of bacterial populations subject to mutation. Journal of the Royal Statistical Society B 14: 1–40, 1952, and

    Google Scholar 

  58. Koch, A.L. Mutation and growth rates from Luria-Delbrück fluctuation tests. Mutation Research 95: 129–143, 1982.

    Google Scholar 

  59. The latter and Mandelbrot, B. A population birth-and-mutation process I: explicit distributions for the number of mutants in an old culture of bacteria. Journal of Applied Probability 11: 437–444, 1974 also consider differential fitnesses (growth rates), of the original and mutant strains. The effect of these factors on the distributions will be considered in Section 5.

    Google Scholar 

  60. Newcombe, H.B. Delayed phenotypic expression of spontaneous mutations in Escherichia coli. Genetics 33: 447–476, 1948;

    Google Scholar 

  61. Demerec, M., and U. Fano. Bacteriophage-resistant mutants in Escherichia coli. Genetics 30: 119–136, 1945.

    PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  62. Witkin, E.M. Genetics of resistance to radiation in Escherichia coli. Genetics 32: 221–248, 1947;

    Google Scholar 

  63. Ryan, F.J. On the stability of nutritional mutants of bacteria. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences (USA) 34: 425–435, 1948.

    CAS  Google Scholar 

  64. Demerec, M. Production of staphylococcus strains resistant to various concentrations of penicillin. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences (USA) 31: 16–24, 1945;

    CAS  Google Scholar 

  65. Oakberg, E.F., and S.E. Luria. Mutations to sulfonamide resistance in Staphylococcus aureus. Genetics 32: 249–261, 1947

    CAS  Google Scholar 

  66. Demerec, M. Origin of bacterial resistance to antibiotics Journal of Bacteriology 56: 63–74, 1948.

    CAS  Google Scholar 

  67. Ryan, F.J., L.K. Schneider, and R. Ballentine. Mutations involving the requirement of uracil in Clostridium. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences (USA) 32: 261–271, 1946;

    CAS  Google Scholar 

  68. Alexander, H.E., and J. Leidy. Mode of action of streptomycin on type b Hemophilus influenzae. Journal of Experimental Medicine 85: 607–621, 1947;

    PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  69. Curcho, M. de la G. Mutation to tryptophan independence in Erbethella typhosa. Journal of Bacteriology 56: 374–375, 1948.

    CAS  Google Scholar 

  70. Newcombe, H.B., Delayed phenotypic expression of spontaneous mutations in Escherichia coli. Genetics 33: 447–476, 1948;

    Google Scholar 

  71. Ryan, F.J. Distribution of numbers of mutant bacteria in replicate cultures. Nature 169: 882–883, 1952.

    Google Scholar 

  72. Newcombe, H.B., Origin of bacterial variants. Nature 164: 150–151, 1949;

    PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  73. Witkin, E.M., Genetics of resistance to radiation in Escherichia coli. Genetics 32: 221–248, 1947.

    Google Scholar 

  74. Ryan, F.J, K. Schneider, and R. Ballentine et al., Mutations involving the requirement of uracil in Clostridium. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences (USA) 32: 261–271, 1946.

    CAS  Google Scholar 

  75. Ryan, F.J. Distribution of numbers of mutant bacteria in replicate cultures. Nature 169: 882–883, 1952.

    Google Scholar 

  76. Ryan, F.J. Distribution of numbers of mutant bacteria in replicate cultures. Nature 169: 882–883, 1952;

    Google Scholar 

  77. Ryan, F.J. Adaptation to use lactose in Escherichia coli. Journal of General Microbiology 7: 69–88, 1952.

    PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  78. This mutation is particularly relevant here because it is one of those studied by Cairns, J., J. Overbaugh, and S. Miller et al.,. The origin of mutants. Nature 335: 142–145, 1988. In fact, that work used Ryan’s studies as one of its starting points.

    PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  79. Ryan, F.J. Distribution of numbers of mutant bacteria in replicate cultures. Nature 169: 882–883, 1952.

    Google Scholar 

  80. Armitage, P., The statistical theory of bacterial populations subject to mutation. Journal of the Royal Statistical Society B 14: 1–40, 1952. Note that Ryan does not explicitly invoke phenotypic lag or any other specific mechanism.

    Google Scholar 

  81. Dean, A.C.R. and C.N. Hinshelwood, Aspects of the problem of drug resistance in bacteria. In Drug Resistance in Microorganisms. G.E.W. Wolstenholme, and C.M. O’Connor, editors. London: J. & A. Churchill, 1957, pp. 4–24.

    Google Scholar 

  82. Eriksen, K.R. Studies on the mode of origin of penicillin resistant staphylococci. Acta Pathologica et Microbiologica Scandinavica 26: 269–279, 1949.

    PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  83. However, Eriksen’s experimental results were not particularly convincing because small samples were taken from the cultures which made the statistical tests inefficient as Cavalli-Sforza L.L. and J. Lederberg. Genetics of resistance to bacterial inhibitors. In Symposium: Growth Inhibition and Chemotherapy. Rome: Istituto Superiore di Sanita, 1953, pp. 108–142 point out.

    Google Scholar 

  84. For Hinshelwood’s position, see, for example, Hinshelwood, C.N. Chemistry and bacteria. Nature 166: 1089–1092, 1950;

    PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  85. and Dean, A.C.R., and C.N. Hinshelwood. 1952. The resistance of Bact. Lactis aerogenes to proflavine (2: 8-diaminoacri-dine). I: the applicability of the statistical fluctuation test. Proceedings of the Royal Society B 139: 236–250, 1952.

    CAS  Google Scholar 

  86. Cavalli, L.L. Genetic analysis of drug-resistance. Bulletin of the World Health Organization 6: 185–206, 1952;

    PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  87. Michison, D.A. The occurrence of independent mutations to different types of streptomycin resistance in Bacterium coli. Journal of General Microbiology 8: 168–185, 1953.

    Google Scholar 

  88. Mitchison, D.A., The occurrence of independent mutations to different types of streptomycin resistance in Bacterium coli. Journal of General Microbiology 8: 168–185, 1953, studied three types of strains of Bacterium coli which had differences in growth rates while being selected for streptomycin resistance by fluctuation analysis.

    PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  89. Cavalli, L.L., Genetic analysis of drug-resistance. Bulletin of the World Health Organization 6: 185–206, 1952.

    PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  90. Newcombe, H.B., Origin of bacterial variants. Nature 164: 150–151, 1949.

    PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  91. Newcombe, H.B., Origin of bacterial variants. Nature 164: 150–151, 1949, p. 150.

    PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  92. Lederberg, J. and E.M. Lederberg, Replica plating and indirect selection of bacterial mutants. Journal of Bacteriology 63: 399–406, 1952;

    PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  93. Cavalli-Sforza, L.L. and J.L. Lederberg, Genetics of resistance to bacterial inhibitors. In Symposium: Growth Inhibition and Chemotherapy. Rome: Istituto Superiore di Sanita, 1956, pp. 108–142.

    Google Scholar 

  94. In practice Cavalli-Sforza L.L. and J. Lederberg. Genetics of resistance to bacterial inhibitors. In Symposium: Growth Inhibition and Chemotherapy. Rome: Istituto Superiore di Sanita, 1956, pp. 108–142 had to increase cell concentration in each cycle because of slow selection.

    Google Scholar 

  95. Stahl, F. Bacterial genetics: a unicorn in the garden. Nature 335: 112–113, 1988.

    PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  96. Lederberg was certainly aware of this but seems not to have regarded it as particularly relevant Cavalli-Sforza L.L. and J. Lederberg. Genetics of resistance to bacterial inhibitors. In Symposium: Growth Inhibition and Chemotherapy. Rome: Istituto Superiore di Sanita, 1953, p. 121).

    Google Scholar 

  97. Ryan, F.J. On the stability of nutritional mutants of bacteria. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences (USA) 34: 425–435, 1948.

    CAS  Google Scholar 

  98. Ryan, F.J. Distribution of numbers of mutant bacteria in replicate cultures. Nature 169: 882–883, 1952.

    Google Scholar 

  99. Ryan, F.J. Adaptation to use lactose in Escherichia coli. Journal of General Microbiology 7: 69–88, 1952.

    PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  100. This does not, of course, endorse in any way criticisms of the sort made by Hinshelwood, C.N., Aspects of the problem of drug resistance in bacteria. In Drug Resistance in Microorganisms. G.E.W. Wolstenholme, and C.M. O’Connor, editors. London: J. & A. Churchill, 1957, pp. 4–24

    Google Scholar 

  101. Hinshelwood, C.N. Chemistry and bacteria. Nature 166: 1089–1092, 1952.

    Google Scholar 

  102. Luria, S.E. and M. Delbrück, Mutations of bacteria from virus sensitivity to virus resistance. Genetics 28: 491–511, 1943, p. 492. Note that they do not explicitly state that one alternative is the negation of the other; they simply ignore intermediate possibilities.

    PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  103. Lea, D.E. and C.A. Coulson, The distribution of the number of mutants in bacterial populations. Journal of Genetics 49: 264–285, 1949.

    Google Scholar 

  104. Armitage, P. The statistical theory of bacterial populations subject to mutation. Journal of the Royal Statistical Society B 14: 1–40, 1952.

    Google Scholar 

  105. The objection just noted in the text is independent of whether the last one, that of the selective media being lethal for non-mutants, is valid. Indeed, phenotypic lag had already been invoked by Newcombe, H.B. Origin of bacterial variants. Nature 164: 150–151, 1949, even before Lea and Coulson had calculated the Luria-Delbrück distribution.

    PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  106. Cavalli-Sforza, L.L. and J. Lederberg, Genetics of resistance to bacterial inhibitors. In Symposium: Growth Inhibition and Chemotherapy. Rome: Istituto Superiore di Sanita, 1956, pp. 108–142.

    Google Scholar 

  107. Lederberg, J., and M. Ledergerg. Replica plating and indirect selection of bacterial mutants. Journal of Bacteriology 63: 399–406, 1952;

    PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  108. Newcombe, H.B. Origin of bacterial variants. Nature 164: 150–151, 1949. Both experiments rely on visual recognition and make no quantitative arguments whatsoever. What they do show, however, is that some mutations were spontaneous (random).

    PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  109. The discussion in this section is not intended to be complete. For details, see the paper by Foster in this volume and Sarkar, S. On the possibility of directed mutations in bacteria: statistical analyses and reductionist strategies. In PSA 1990. A. Fine, editor, 1990. Philosophy of Science Association, East Lansing. In press.

    Google Scholar 

  110. Shapiro, J. Observations on the formation of clones containing araB-lacZ cistron fusions. Molecular and General Genetics 194: 79–90, 1984.

    PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  111. Cairns, J., J. Overbaugh, and S. Miller. et al., The origin of mutants. Nature 335: 142–145, 1988.

    PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  112. Ryan, F.J. Distribution of numbers of mutant bacteria in replicate cultures. Nature 169: 882–883, 1952;

    Google Scholar 

  113. Ryan, F.J. Adaptation to use lactose in Escherichia coli. Journal of General Microbiology 7: 69–88, 1952.

    PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  114. This mutation is particularly relevant here because it is one of those studied by Cairns, J., J. Overbaugh, and S. Miller. et al., The origin of mutants. Nature 335: 142–145, 1988. In fact, that work used Ryan’s studies as one of its starting points.

    PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  115. Hall, B. Adaptive evolution that requires multiple spontaneous mutations I. Genetics 120: 887–897, 1988.

    PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  116. Lenski, R.E. Are some mutations directed? Trends in Ecology and Evolution 4: 148–150, 1989, emphasizes the importance of this point.

    PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  117. Cairns, J., et al., The origin of mutants. Nature 335: 142–145, 1988.

    PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  118. Mittler, J.E. and R.E. Lenski. New data on excisions of Mu from E. coli MCS2 cast doubt on directed mutation hypothesis. Nature 334: 173–175, 1990;

    Google Scholar 

  119. Shapiro, J. Observations on the formation of clones containing araB-lacZ cistron fusions. Molecular and General Genetics 194: 79–90, 1984;

    PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  120. Cairns, J., et al., The origin of mutants. Nature 335: 142–145, 1988.

    PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  121. Mittler, J.E. and Lenski, R.E., New data on excisions of Mu from E. coli MCS2 cast doubt on directed mutation hypothesis. Nature 334: 173–175, 1990.

    Google Scholar 

  122. Cairns, J., et al. The origin of mutants. Nature 335: 142–145, 1988. Note that these authors interpret the shift as a Poisson component added on to a Luria-Delbrück distribution, but this is an interpretation and, therfore, subject to legitimate questioning.

    PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  123. Stewart, F., D. Gordon, and B. Levin et al., Fluctuation analysis: the probability distribution of the number of mutants under different conditions. Genetics 124: 175–185, 1990.

    PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  124. The second and the last of these cannot be shown using the analysis of Stewart, F., et al., Fluctuation analysis: the probability distribution of the number of mutants under different conditions. Genetics 124: 175–185, 1990.

    PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  125. The importance of this case has been particularly emphasized by Charlesworth, D., B. Charlesworth, and J.J. Bull. Origin of mutants disputed. Nature 336: 525, 1988,

    Google Scholar 

  126. and Tessman, I. Origin of mutants disputed. Nature 336: 527, 1988.

    Google Scholar 

  127. Cairns has replied to this objection by observing that there did not appear to be any difference in fitness between mutant and non-mutant types in his experiments (Cairns, J. Origin of mutants disputed. Nature 336: 527–528, 1988.)

    Google Scholar 

  128. Stewart, F., D. Gordon, and B. Levin et al., Fluctuation analysis: the probability distribution of the number of mutants under different conditions. Genetics 124: 175–185, 1990.

    PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  129. Lenski, R.E., M. Slatkin, and F.J. Ayala. Mutation and selection in bacterial populations: alternatives to the hypothesis of directed mutation. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences (USA) 86: 2775–2778.

    Google Scholar 

  130. Lenski, R.E., M. Slatkin, and F.J. Ayala, Mutation and selection in bacterial populations: alternatives to the hypothesis of directed mutation. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences (USA) 86: 2775–2778;

    Google Scholar 

  131. Lenski, R.E., M. Slatkin, and F.J. Ayala. Another alternative to directed mutation. Nature 337: 123–124, 1989.

    PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  132. Levin, B., D, Gordon, and F. Stewart. Is natural selection the composer as well as the editor of genetic variation? Forthcoming, 1990.

    Google Scholar 

  133. Cairns, J. et al., The origin of mutants. Nature 335: 142–145, 1988. These mechanisms will be discussed in detail in the text.

    PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  134. Stahl, F., Bacterial genetics: a unicorn in the garden. Nature 335: 112–113, 1988;

    PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  135. Davis, B.D. 1989. Transcriptional bias: a non-Lamarckian mechanism for substrate-induced mutations. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences (USA) 86: 5005–5009, 1989.

    CAS  Google Scholar 

  136. For example, the mechanism suggested by Davis, B. D., Transcriptional bias: a non-Lamarckian mechanism for substrate-induced mutations. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences (USA) 86: 5005–5009, 1989, can be ruled out (in part due to the experimental reports of Davis himself).

    CAS  Google Scholar 

  137. Cairns, J. et al., The origin of mutants. Nature 335: 142–145, 1988.

    PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  138. Cairns, J. et al., The origin of mutants. Nature 335: 142–145, 1988, require the same organelle to contain the reverse transcriptase and monitor the performance of the RNA molecules. Thus the interaction from the feedback process to the organelle is automatically ensured. However, there is no conceptual reason to require the same organelle to do all this. Hence, the three requirements have been separated in the version presented in the text.

    PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  139. Stahl, F., Bacterial genetics: a unicorn in the garden. Nature 335: 112–113, 1988.

    PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  140. Davis, B.D., Transcriptional bias: a non-Lamarckian mechanism for substrate-induced mutations. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences (USA) 86: 5005–5009, 1989.

    CAS  Google Scholar 

  141. It should perhaps be emphasized that probably none of the proponents of these mechanisms, especially Davis, B.D., Transcriptional bias: a non-Lamarckian mechanism for substrate-induced mutations. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences (USA) 86: 5005–5009, 1989, would choose to call the mechanisms “neo-Lamarckian.” Moreover, all that is being suggested here is that they are only “neo-Lmarckian” in the sense that they satisfy the criteria of the explication of the term given in Section 2.

    CAS  Google Scholar 

  142. Cairns, J. et al., The origin of mutants. Nature 335: 142–145, 1988. It is, perhaps, worth emphasis that there is no evidence, as yet, in favor of these mechanisms

    PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  143. Davis, B.D., Transcriptional bias: a non-Lamarckian mechanism for substrate-induced mutations. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences (USA) 86: 5005–5009, 1989, has argued that such a mechanism, itself, would have adaptive value. This is quite likely and such a mechanism might well have arisen in a thoroughly neo-Darwinian fashion. However, the new mutations that such a mechanism would make possible would still show the characteristics of being neo-Lamarckian. Thus the basic question, whether there is any neo-Lamarckian mutagenesis, remains the same.

    CAS  Google Scholar 

  144. Sarkar, S. Reductionism and molecular biology: a reappraisal. Ph. D. Dissertation. Department of Philosophy, University of Chicago, 1989, for a detailed examination of this issue.

    Google Scholar 

  145. For details, Sarkar, S., Reductionism and molecular biology: a reappraisal. Ph. D. Dissertation. Department of Philosophy, University of Chicago, 1989, and

    Google Scholar 

  146. Wimsatt, W.C. Reductive explanation: a functional account. Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science 32: 671–710, 1976.

    Google Scholar 

  147. Cairns, J. Overbaugh, and S. Miller et al., The origin of mutants. Nature 335: 142–145, 1988, p. 145.

    Google Scholar 

  148. Sarkar, S. Reductionism and molecular biology: a reappraisal. Ph. D. Dissertation. Department of Philosophy, University of Chicago, 1989, and

    Google Scholar 

  149. Wimsatt, W. C. Reduction and reductionism. In Current Research in the Philosophy of Science. P.D. Asquith and H. Kyburg, editors. Philosophy of Science Association, pp. 352–377, 1978.

    Google Scholar 

  150. Sarkar, S. Reductionism and molecular biology: a reappraisal. Ph. D. Dissertation. Department of Philosophy, University of Chicago, 1989.

    Google Scholar 

  151. Kauffman, S.A., S.A. Articulation of parts explanation in biology and the rational search for them. Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science 8: 257–272, 1972;

    Google Scholar 

  152. Wimsatt, W.C., Reductive explanation: a functional account. Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science 32: 671–710, 1976.

    Google Scholar 

  153. The classic accounts of “theory reduction” are Nagel, E. The Structure of Science: Problems in the Logic of Scientific Explanation. New York: Harcourt, Brace & World, 1961, and

    Google Scholar 

  154. Schaffner, K. Approaches to reduction. Philosophy of Science 34: 137–147, 1967.

    Google Scholar 

  155. For arguments that attempt to show that such classic accounts of “theory reduction” cannot capture the flavor of research in molecular biology, Sarkar, S. Reductionism and molecular biology: a reappraisal. Ph. D. Dissertation. Department of Philosophy, University of Chicago, 1989.,

    Google Scholar 

  156. Wimsatt, W.C., Reductive explanation: a functional account. Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science 32: 671–710, 1976, and,

    Google Scholar 

  157. especially, Hull, D. Reduction in genetics—biology or philosophy? Philosophy of Science 39: 491–499, 1972.

    Google Scholar 

  158. Luria, S.E. and M. Delbrück, Mutations of bacteria from virus sensitivity to virus resistance. Genetics 28: 491–511, 1943, p. 492. The same point can be made about most of the research of the Phage Group which usually tried to infer informations about processes within the virus by looking at interactions of the virus, as a whole, with other entities. Though, the present article argues for reductionist research in the context of the problem being considered here, examples such as this clearly show the value of non-reductionist research in biology in other contexts. Of course it is almost trivial to assert the same value for non-reductionist research in most of evolutionary biology.

    PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  159. Cairns, J., J. Overbaugh, and S. Miller et al., The origin of mutants. Nature 335: 1988, p. 145.

    Google Scholar 

  160. Delbrück, M. A physicist looks at biology. Transactions of the Connecticut Academy of Sciences 38: 173–190,1949;

    Google Scholar 

  161. Stent, G.S. That was the molecular biology that was. Science 160: 390–395, 1968;

    PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  162. Bohr, N. Light and life. Nature 131: 421–423, 457–459, 1933.

    Google Scholar 

  163. The important point is that the willingness to use such tests show that there was no prior commitment only to investigate biological problems in a reductionist fashion. It is not being suggested that Luria and Delbrück were deliberately attempting to keep their research strategy non-reductionist. In fact, Delbrck at least partly operated with an assumption that the only way in which his non-reductionist hopes might be realized is by pushing reductionist physical methods to the extreme and finding a paradox that defied such explanation. For details of this history, Sarkar, S., Reductionism and molecular biology: a reappraisal. Ph. D. Dissertation. Department of Philosophy, University of Chicago, 1989, and

    Google Scholar 

  164. Fischer, E.P. and C. Lipson, Thinking About Science: Max Delbrück and the Origins of Molecular Biology. New York: Knopf, 1988.

    Google Scholar 

  165. The only class of exceptions to the general reductionist explanations offered by molecular biology, at present, is that of functional explanations. For details of the problems that functional explanations pose for reductionist accounts, Sarkar, S., Reductionism and molecular biology: a reappraisal. Ph. D. Dissertation. Department of Philosophy, University of Chicago, 1989, and

    Google Scholar 

  166. Sarkar, S. Natural selection, hypercycles and the origin of life. In PSA 1988, Vol. 1. A. Fine and J. Leplin, editors, pp. 196–206, 1988.

    Google Scholar 

  167. 86. Wimsatt, W.C. Teleology and the logical structure of function statements. Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science 3: 1–80, 1972.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1991 Kluwer Academic Publishers

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Sarkar, S. (1991). Lamarck Contre Darwin, Reduction Versus Statistics: Conceptual Issues in the Controversy over Directed Mutagenesis in Bacteria. In: Tauber, A.I. (eds) Organism and the Origins of Self. Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science, vol 129. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-011-3406-4_11

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-011-3406-4_11

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-0-7923-1185-0

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-011-3406-4

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics