Skip to main content

Introduction: Speculations Concerning the Origins of the Self

  • Chapter
Organism and the Origins of Self

Part of the book series: Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science ((BSPS,volume 129))

Abstract

Defining the operative ideology of the biological sciences is in the midst of re-assessment. Confidence in the chemo-mechanical reductive model is in continued debate, and the issue appears to focus on the organism, which has fallen between two seemingly crushing spheres of thought—molecular/cellular biology, on the one hand, and behavioral/ecological biology, on the other. As a physician, I participate in this discussion with the least well-defined discipline at his calling. Medicine at the end of the 20th century relies on contributions from technology, physics, chemistry, psychology as integral to its practice as the biological sciences. As a result, we do not possess a well-defined theory of medicine, a self-contained system of its own principles, by which it exclusively pursues expansion of its knowledge base or regulates its intellectual and practical activities. It borrows from everywhere, and in the process appears as a patchwork quilt, in places highly developed and precisely effective, and in others, painfully devoid of any reasonable hypothesis or therapy [1]. Success in areas amenable to mechanical models (i.e. orthopedics, cardiovascular surgery) or military metaphor (antimicrobial therapy) has been staggering. But such principles are not necessarily applicable to more complex systems based on hierarchical construction, such as the immune or nervous systems, or in developing strategies against cancer or AIDS.

“If science is not to degenerate into a medley of ad hoc hypotheses, it must become philosophical and must enter upon a thorough criticism of its own foundations.” Alfred North Whitehead, Science and the Modern World.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 169.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 219.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 219.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  1. Alvan Feinstein has eloquently argued that medicine requires its own unique science that does not rely on other disciplines, resists legitimatizing reductionism, and employs mathematical analysis suitable to its specific purposes. See Clinical Judgement, Baltimore: Williams and Wilkins, 1967 and a series of biometric papers: An additional basic science for clinical medicine. Ann. Int. Med. 99: 393–397, 544–550, 705–712, 843–848, 1983 and Clinical biostatistics. LVII. A glossary of neologisms in quantitative clinical science. Clin. Pharm. Therap. 30: 564–577, 1981.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Allen GE. Life Science in the Twentieth Century: Cambridge University Press, 1981.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Tauber AI and Chernyak L. Metchnikoff and the Origins of Immunology. New York: Oxford University Press, 1991.Portions of the study have been published separately: Chernyak L and Tauber AI. The birth of immunology: Metchnikoff, the embryologist. Cell. Immunol. 117: 218–233, 1988

    Google Scholar 

  4. Portions of the study have been published separately: Chernyak L and Tauber AI. The birth of immunology: Metchnikoff, the embryologist. Cell. Immunol. 117: 218–233, 1988

    Article  PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  5. Chernyak L and Tauber AI. The idea of immunity: Metchnikoff’s metaphysics and science. J. Hist. Biol., 23: 187–249, 1990

    Article  PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  6. Tauber AI and Chernyak L. The birth of immunology: II. Metchnikoff and his critics. Cell. Immunol. 121: 447–473, 1989.

    Article  PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  7. Issues directly germane to modern interpretation have been explored in Tauber AI and Chernyak L. Metchnikoff and a theory of medicine. J. Royal Soc. Med., 82: 699–701, 1989

    CAS  Google Scholar 

  8. Tauber AI. Metchnikoff, the modern immunologist, J. Leuk. Biol. 47: 560–566, 1990 and Tauber AI. The immunological Self: A centenary perspective. Perspect. Biol. Med., In Press. Many elements of this Introduction are products of the exciting collaborative effort I have enjoyed with Chernyak, and have been explored with a different orientation in the above cited works.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Metchnikoff’s mature position, although basically unchanged from 1882 to his death in 1916 is best summarized in his Immunity in Infective Diseases (1901) trans. KG. Binnie, Cambridge, 1905. Reprinted by Johnston Reprint Corp., 1968.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Buss LW. The Evolution of Individuality. Princeton, 1987.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Margulis L. Symbiosis in Cell Evolution. San Francisco, Freeman, 1981.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Edelman GM. Topobiology. An Introduction to Molecular Embryology. New York: Basic Books, 1988.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Henry JJ, Amemiya S, Wray GA and Raff RA. Early inductive interactions are involved in restricting cell fates of mesomeres in sea urchin embryos. Dev. Biol. 136: 140–153, 1989.

    Article  PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  14. CH Waddington. Evolutionary adaptation in Evolution. After Darwin. Vol. 1. The Evolution of Life. Its Origin, History, and Future. S. Tax, (ed.) Chicago: The University of Chicago, 1959, pp. 381–402.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Reprinted in CH Waddington. The Evolution of an Evolutionist. Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1975, pp. 36–59. See also the discussion by Bonner JT. The Evolution of Development. Cambridge University Press, 1958.

    Google Scholar 

  16. See also the discussion by Bonner JT. The Evolution of Development. Cambridge University Press, 1958.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Lewontin R. The Genetic Basis of Evolutionary Change. New York: Columbia University Press, 1974

    Google Scholar 

  18. further discussed by Eliott Sober in The Nature of Selection. Evolutionary Theory in Philosophical Focus. Cambridge, MIT Press, 1984.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Metchnikoff’s intuitive proposition was experimentally proven by Chabry (Chabry, L. J. Anat. Physiol (Paris) 23: 167–319, 1887), who showed that destruction of one cell of a two-celled frog embryo resulted in half a tadpole; the later classical studies of Roux and Driesch based on this work directed the course of experimental embryology for decades.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Metchnikoff E. Lectures on the Comparative Pathology of Inflammation, trans. F.A. Starling and E.H. Starling. London: Kegan Paul, Trench, Trubner and Co., Ltd., 1893. Reprinted by Dover Publications Inc., NY, 1968.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Reprinted by Dover Publications Inc., NY, 1968.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Johnston IS and Hildemann WH. Cellular defense systems of the Porifera in N. Cohen and M.M. Sigel, editors, The Reticuloendothelial System. A Comprehensive Treatise Vol. 3, Phylogeny and Ontogeny, New York: Plenum Press, 1982, pp. 37–57.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Bigger CH and Hildemann WH. Cellular defense system of the coelenterata in N. Cohen and M.M. Sigel, editors, The Reticuloendothelial System. A Comprehensive Treatise Vol. 3, Phylogeny and Ontogeny, New York: Plenum Press, 1982, pp. 59–87.

    Google Scholar 

  24. The issue is well reviewed in Ratcliff, N.A. and Cooper EL. Invertebrate defense systems: An overview in N. Cohen and M.M. Sigel, editors, The Reticuloendothelial System. A Comprehensive Treatise Vol. 3, Phylogeny and Ontogeny, New York: Plenum Press, 1982, pp. 1–35

    Google Scholar 

  25. Marchallionis JJ. Immunity in Evolution. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1977.

    Google Scholar 

  26. The vertebrate immune system may represent a convergent evolution of allorecognition, one which arose as a nonadaptive byproduct of sophisticated modes of xenorecognition. Alternatively, the immune systems of vertebrates and echinoderms may be homologous with those found in clonal invertebrates, only to have subsequently become adopted as a mechanism of xenorecognition. The latter hypothesis is supported by the fact that several primitive echinoderms (which are presumed ancestral stock for the chordates) were sedentary, potentially clonal, organisms. Thus, vertebrate ancestors may well have encountered fusion as a naturally occurring event and developed allorecognition as a response to the threat of somatic cell parasitism following fusion. Further support is found in the fact that vertebrate recognition of foreign tissue still requires simultaneous self-recognition (i.e., antigens presented on macrophages result in the release of interleukins only to T-cells which match the antigen in the context of appropriate self markers). Hence the primitive system, though no longer required for fusion once mobility was acquired, was nevertheless required in xenorecognition and, accordingly, not lost in the course of evolution [Buss, op. cit., pp. 151–152].

    Google Scholar 

  27. See also Buss LW and Green DR. Histoincompatibility in vertebrates: The relict hypothesis. J. Comp. Dev. Immunol. 9: 191–201, 1985.

    Article  CAS  Google Scholar 

  28. Edelman E. CAM’S and Igs: Cell adhesion and the evolutionary origins of immunity. Immunol. Rev. 100: 9–43, 1987

    Article  Google Scholar 

  29. Rutishauser U, Acheson A, Hall AK, Mann DM and Sunshine J. Science 240: 53–57, 1988

    Article  CAS  Google Scholar 

  30. Matsunaga T and Mori N. Globulin superfamily molecules are all related. Scand. J. Immunol. 25: 485–495, 1987.

    CAS  Google Scholar 

  31. Chernyak and I discuss these issues in our essay of this volume, The dialectical Self: Immunology’s contribution.

    Google Scholar 

  32. See for general review: Adler R (ed) Psychoneuroimmunology. New York: Academic Press, 1981.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Korneva EA, Klimenko VM and Shkhinek EI. Neurohumoral Maintenance of Immune Homeostasis (S.A. and E.O. Corson, translators and editors). Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1985.

    Google Scholar 

  34. Locke S, Ader R, Besedovsky H, Hall N, Solomon G and Strom T (ed). Foundations of Psychoneuroimmunology. New York: Aldine Publishing Co., 1985.

    Google Scholar 

  35. Metalnikov S and Chorine V. Role des reflexes conditionnels dans l’immunite. Ann. de l’Inst. Pasteur 40: 893–900, 1926. English translation and commentary in J.D. Bibel, Milestones in Immunology. Madison: Science Tech Publ., 1988. pp. 312–316.

    Google Scholar 

  36. Felten DL, Felten S Y, Carlson SL, Olschowka JA and Livnat S. Noradrenergic and peptidergic innervation of lymphoid tissue. J. Immunol. 135: 755s–765s, 1985.

    PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  37. Bockman DE and Kirby ML. Neural crest interactions in the development of the immune system. J. Immunol. 135: 766s–772s, 1985.

    PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  38. Goetzl EJ, Chernov T, Renold F and Payan DG. Neuropeptide regulation of the expression of immediate hypersensitivity. J. Immunol. 135: 802s–805s, 1985

    PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  39. Russell M, Dark KA, Cummins RW, Ellman G, Callaway E and Peeke HVS. Learned histamine release. Science 225: 733–734, 1984.

    Article  PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  40. Hall NR, McGillis JP, Spangelo BL and Goldstein AL. Evidence that thymosins and other biologic response modifiers can function as neuroactive immunotransmitters. J. Immunol. 135: 806s–811s, 1985.

    PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  41. Ruff MR, Sacerdote P, Wiedermann CJ and Pert CB. Neuropeptide receptors are shared components of nervous and immune systems. In: Neuropeptides and Stress, Hans Selye Symposia on Neuroendocrinology Stress, Tache Y, Morely J and Brown M (Eds.). Springer-Verlag, New York, 1989, pp. 235–246.

    Google Scholar 

  42. Subject well reviewed by J.E. Blalock. A molecular basis for bidirectional communication communication between the immune and neuroendocrine systems. Physiol. Reviews 69: 1–32, 1989.

    CAS  Google Scholar 

  43. Roth J, LeRoith D, Collier ES, Weaver NR, Watkinson A, Cleland CF and Glick SM. Evolutionary origins of neuropeptides, hormones, and receptors: Possible applications to immunology. J. Immunol. 816s–819s, 1985.

    Google Scholar 

  44. Roth J, LeRoith D, Lesniak, MA, de Pablo F, Bassas L and Collier E. Molecules of intracellular communication in vertebrates, invertebrates, and microbes: do they share common origins? Progress in Brain Reseach Vol. 68. Hokfelt, T, K. Fuxe, and B. Pernow (ed.) pp. 71–79, 1986.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  45. Edelman G. Neural Darwinism. The Theory of Neuronal Group Selection. New York: Basic Books, 1987.

    Google Scholar 

  46. See F.J. Varela, Organism — A meshwork of selfless selves in this volume, and earlier theoretical work of particular interest: Varela FJ, Coutinho A, Dupire B and Vaz NN. Cognitive Networks: Immune, neural and otherwise, in Theoretical Immunology, Part Two. A.S. Perelson (ed.). Redwood City: Addison-Wesley Publishing Co., 1988, pp. 359–375.

    Google Scholar 

  47. Coutinho A, Forni L, Holmberg D, Ivars F and Vaz N. From an antigen-centered, clonal perspective of immune responses to an organism-centered network perspective of autonomous activity in a self-referential immune system. Immunol. Rev. 79: 151–168, 1984.

    Article  PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  48. Vaz NM and Varela FJ. Self and non-self: An organism-centered approach to immunology. Med. Hypoth. 4: 231–267, 1978.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  49. An experimental program has been generated by the Paris School: Stewart J and Varela FJ. Exploring the meaning of connectivity in the immune network. Immunol. Rev. 110: 37–61, 1989

    Article  PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  50. Varela FJ and Coutinho A. Times and Trends. Immune networks: Getting on to the real thing. Res. Immunol. 140: 837–845, 1989

    Article  PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  51. Stewart J, Varela FJ and Coutinho A. The relationship between connectivity and tolerance as revealed by computer simulation of the immune network: Some lessons for an understanding of autoimmunity. J. Autoimmun. 2: 15–23, 1989

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  52. Lundkvist I, Coutinho A, Varela F and Holmberg D. Evidence for a functional idiotypic network among natural antibodies in normal mice. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. 86: 5074–5078, 1989.

    Article  PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  53. Jerne NK. The generative grammar of the immune system. EMBO. J. 4: 847–852, 1985.

    PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  54. Jerne NK. Idiotypic networks and other preconceived ideas. Immunol. Rev. 79: 5–24, 1984.

    Article  PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  55. For an excellent history of modern immunology, see AM Silverstein, A History of Immunology. New York: Academic Press, 1989.

    Google Scholar 

  56. Benner R; van Oudenaren M, Bjorklund F, Ivars F and Holmberg D. “Background” immunoglobulin production measurement, biological significance and regulation. Immunol. Today 3: 243–249, 1982.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  57. The macrophage appears to recognize antibody bound to newly exposed “senescent antigens”, derived from band 3, the erythrocyte transporter. (Kay MMB, Bosman GJ, Johnson GJ and Beth AH. Band-3 polymers and aggregates, and hemoglobin precipitates in red cell aging. Blood Cells 14: 275–289, 1988.)

    CAS  Google Scholar 

  58. Whether the neo-antigen is a proteolyzed or oxidized product, or a newly formed dimer of a native protein is not known. The sensecent antigen, in addition to being found on the erythrocyte, has been demonstrated on the surface of lymphocytes, neutrophils, platelets, embryonic kidney cells and adult liver cells. (Kay MMB. Isolation of the phagocytosis-inducing IgG-binding antigen on senescent somatic cells. Nature 289: 491–494, 1981.)

    Article  PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  59. In this case, the neo-antigen is recognized by immunoglobulin, however, altered physico-chemical plasma membrane structures may be recognized by phagocytes (Tanaka Y and Schroit AJ. Insertion of fluorescent phosphatidylserine into the plasma membrane or red blood cells. J. Biol. Chem. 258: 11335–11343, 1983), thus the relative importance of immune (i.e. antibody) vs. non-immune recognition mechanisms of phagocyte targets is unsettled.

    PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  60. For a provocative hypothesis concerning autoimmunity see R.S. Root-Bernstein, Self, nonself and the paradoxes of autoimmunity in this volume, pp. 159–209.

    Google Scholar 

  61. Models recently proposed by Deboer, Perelson and Segel in A.S. Perelson (ed.) Theoretical Immunology, Vol. 1 and 2. Redwood City: Addison-Wesley, 1988

    Google Scholar 

  62. G. Parisi. A simple model for the immune network. Proc. Nat. Acad. Sci. USA 87: 429–433, 1990.

    Article  PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  63. Russet-Kraemer, L and WJ Bock. Prologue: The necessity of the organism. Amer. Zool. 29: 1057–1060, 1989. This paper serves as an introduction to a recent symposium devoted to the historical and scientific status of the biological concept of organism.

    Google Scholar 

  64. Levins R; and Lewontin R. The Dialectical Biologist, Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1985, pp. 2–3.

    Google Scholar 

  65. Masson D. Recent British Philosphy, London, 1867.

    Google Scholar 

  66. Shapiro JA. Bacteria as multicellular organisms. Sci. Am. 1988, pp. 82–89

    Google Scholar 

  67. Shapiro JA and Hsu C. Escherichia coli K-12 cell-cell interactions seen by time-lapse video. J. Bacteriol. 171: 5963–5974, 1989.

    PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  68. Shapiro JA. Intercellular communication and genetic change in bacterial populations in Engineered Organisms in the Environment: Scientific Issues, edited by HO Halvorson, D Pramer, M Rogul. Washington, D.C.: American Society for Microbiology, 1985, pp. 63–69.

    Google Scholar 

  69. Sonea S. A new look at bacteria. ASM News 55: 2–4, 1989

    Google Scholar 

  70. Sonea S. Bacterial viruses, prophages, and plasmids, reconsidered. Ann. NY Acad. Sci. 503: 251–260, 1987

    Article  PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  71. Sonea S. A bacterial way of life. Nature 331: 216, 1988.

    Article  PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  72. Galaty DH. The philosophical basis of mid-nineteenth century German reductionism. J. Hist. Med. Allied Sci. 29: 295–316, 1974.

    Article  PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  73. Lenoir, T. The Strategy of Life. Teleology and Mechanics in Nineteenth Century Biology. Dordrecht: D. Reidel, 1982 and republished by The University of Chicago Press, 1989.

    Google Scholar 

  74. The most famous example was the concept of ontogeny recapitulating phylogeny, viz. the “Meckel-Serres Law”. Here the same laws regulate embryonic development and historical progression of species, von Baer rigorously attacked this formulation as the leading teleomechanist of his day.

    Google Scholar 

  75. See Russell, E.S. Form and Function. A Contribution to the History of Animal Morphology. London: John Murray Ltd. 1916.

    Google Scholar 

  76. Republished by the University of Chicago Press, 1982 and Stephen Jay Gould, Ontogeny and Phylogeny. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1977, pp. 35–63.

    Google Scholar 

  77. Schelling, F.W.J. Ideas for a Philosophy of Nature, translated by E.F. Harris and P. Heath. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988.

    Google Scholar 

  78. An excellent recent review of early 19th century science is Romanticism and the Sciences, edited by A. Cunningham and N. Jardine, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990.

    Google Scholar 

  79. McFarland, J.D. Kant’s Concept of Teleology. Edinburgh: University of Edinburgh Press, 1970.

    Google Scholar 

  80. Bergmann C and Leukart R. Anatomisch physisch Ubersicht des Thiereiches. Stuttgart, 1852. The scientific development of this position is of great interest and we will outline it briefly. Lenoir (note No. 38) argues persuasively that the work of Schwann, Liebig, Lotze, Bergmann and Leukart, (late 1830’s to mid 1850’s) rather than simply rejecting vitalism and establishing biochemical reductionism, in fact was closer to Kant’s original teleomechanical thesis than their teachers Karl von Baer and Johannes Müller.

    Google Scholar 

  81. To argue that the parts were meaningful only in relation to the whole is a far different concept from von Baer’s position that the whole is ontologically primary and directs the organization of its parts (an Aristotelian version). Consistent with Kant, Schwann excluded “any sort of directive agent from discussion of biological organization” (Lenoir, p. 129). Liebig and Lotze joined Schwann as third generation teleomechanists who sought to purge vitalism as a propagating life force. Teleology in their hands was to remain a program to investigate the whole, looking at the parts in view of defining and understanding function. In 1842, Liebig (Liebig, J. Die organische Chemie in iker Anwendung auf Physiologie und Pathologie. Braunschweig, 1842.), and Lotze (Lotze, H. “Lebenskraft”, Handworterbuch der Physiologie. Vol. 1 ed. R. Wagner. Gottingen, 1842.) published their seminal works: Lotze clearly enuniciated his position: teleology does not offer an explanation, but serves as a regulative principle of inquiry, which serves to promote the investigation as to how the organized body functions. In this view, forces were not to be treated as independent beings, e.g. like other material objects (another focus of assault on Naturphilosophie). Similarly, Liebig attacked vitalism by regarding all forces in the organic body (chemical, electrical, etc) as particular manifestations of motion that could ultimately be expressed in terms of momentum and work. Each regarded the process of material exchange in the animal as the central issue, and heat was thought as the crucial element in the interconversion of the various forces. The reductionists focused on the same research program, but with a broadened agenda. To establish the conservation and conversion of energy in organic processes was not only to deny a vitalistic element, but also to establish the ultimate reducibility of organic function to physics and chemistry; this strategy was successfully employed by Helmholtz, who shed the teleological construct, and whose brillant experimental success must be viewed as directly linked to the eventual eclipse of the teleomechanistic program.

    Google Scholar 

  82. Kant, I. The Critique of Judgement. Translated by Werner S. Pluhar. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Co., 1987.

    Google Scholar 

  83. Loeb, J. The Mechanistic Conception of Life. (1912) Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1964.

    Google Scholar 

  84. Also see Philip J. Pauly, Controlling Life, Jacques Loeb and the Engineering Ideal in Biology. New York: Oxford University Press, 1987.

    Google Scholar 

  85. Woodger, J.H. Biological Principles. A Critical Study. London. Routledge and Kegan Paul Ltd., 1929.

    Google Scholar 

  86. Eigen, M. and Schuster, P. The hypercycle. A principle of natural self-organization. Naturwissenschaften 64: 541–565, 1977; 65: 7–41; 65: 341–369, 1978.

    Article  PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  87. Gatlin, L.L. Information Theory and the Living System. New York: Columbia University Press, 1972.

    Google Scholar 

  88. Welch, G.R. and Clegg, J.S. (eds.) The Organization of Cell Metabolism. New York: Plenum Press, 1985

    Google Scholar 

  89. Welch, G.R. (ed.) Organized Multienzyme Systems. Catalytic Properties. New York: Academic Press, 1985

    Google Scholar 

  90. Keleti, T. and Ovadi, J. Control of metabolism by dynamic macromolecular interactions. Cur. Top. Cell. Reg. 29: 1–33, 1988

    CAS  Google Scholar 

  91. Heinrich, H., Rapoport, S.M. and Rapoport, T.A. Metabolic regulation and mathematical models. Prog. Biophys. Molec. Biol. 32: 1–82, 1977.

    Article  CAS  Google Scholar 

  92. Surveys of this problem have recently been published: Self organizing systems. The Emergence of Order. Edited by FE Yates, A Garfinkel, DO Walter, and GB Yates. New York: Plenum Press, 1987 and Artificial Life: Proceedings of an Interdisciplinary Workshop on the Synthesis and Simulation of Living System. C.F. Langton (ed.). Redwood City, CA: Addison-Wesley Publishing Co., 1989.

    Google Scholar 

  93. A celebrated exception is the case of several physicists who turned to biology in the 1930’s and 40’s as a result of the philosophical challenge presented by the writings of Erwin Schrodinger (What is Life? The Physical Aspect of the Living Cell. Cambridge University Press, 1944) and Niels Bohr (Light and Life, Nature 131: 421–423, 457–459, 1933. See also related papers in The Philosophical Writings of Niels Bohr, Vol. II and III. Woodbridge, Conn., Ox Bow Press, 1987). One well-examined example (E.P. Fischer and C. Lipson Thinking About Science: Max Delbrück and the Origins of Molecular Biology. New York: WW Norton and Co., 1988) is that of Max Delbrück, who sought to establish (in bacterial genetics) Bohr’s notion that a complementary explanation to physics and chemistry existed in biological systems, i.e. organic function could not be ultimately explained by reductive sciences. It is of note that by the early 1960’s Bohr although asserting the crucial role of teleology in biology, had become more respectful of the reductionist approach.

    Google Scholar 

  94. Surely, as long as for practical or epistemological reasons one speaks of life, such teleological terms will be used in complementing the terminology of molecular biology. This circumstance, however, does not in itself imply any limitation in the application to biology of the well-established principles of atomic physics. [Niels Bohr, Light and Life revisited (address given June, 1962; unfinished manuscript, Philosophical Writings, Vol. Ill, op. cit., p. 26].

    Google Scholar 

  95. Delbriick’s own musings on these issues are discussed in “A physicist’s renewed look at Biology: Twenty years later”. Science 168: 1312–1315, 1970; “Light and Life III”. Carlsberg Research Communications. 41: 299–309, 1976, and Mind from Matter. An Essay on Evolutionary Epistemology. Palo Alto: Blackwell Scientific Publications, 1986.

    Google Scholar 

  96. Devault, D. Quantum Mechanical Tunnelling in Biological Systems, 2nd Edition. Cambridge University Press, 1984

    Google Scholar 

  97. Cha, Y., Murray, C.J. and Klinman, J.P. Hydrogen tunneling in enzyme rections, Nature 243: 1325–1330, 1989

    CAS  Google Scholar 

  98. Kuri, A. and Wolynes, P.G. Electron tunneling paths in proteins. Science 236: 1647–1652, 1987

    Article  Google Scholar 

  99. Klinman, J.P. Quantum mechanical effects in enzyme-cataysed hydrogen transfer reactions. Trends Biochem. Sci. 14: 368–373, 1989.

    Article  PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  100. Recent discussion of the interface between quantum mechanics and biology has been speculatively explored by Muses and Yates. See C.A. Muses, Interfaces between quantum physics and bioenergetics, and F.E. Yates, Quantumstuff and biostuff. A view of patterns of convergence in contemporary science in Self Organizing Systems, ed. F.E. Yates, op. cit. pp. 489–497 and 617–644.

    Google Scholar 

  101. Bachelard, G. The New Scientific Spirit. Boston: Beacon Press, 1984, p. 3.

    Google Scholar 

  102. For example, the success of gene control and lambda phage molecular biology as a paradigm for eukaryote gene regulation is a particularly exciting chapter in the power of reductionist biology (see Mark Ptashne, A Genetic Switch. Cambridge: Cell Press, 1987), and for a summary of gene regulation at the mRNA level, see Marilyn Kozach, A profusion of controls, J. Cell. Biol. 107: 1–7, 1988.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  103. As I have examined reductionism and the role it has played in science — in biology particularly—I have found that it has served primarily as a program or a policy; it has not served really, for the biologist, as a rule or law. The biologist might like to think of it as such, but more often than not he has used reductionism as a means of advocating a research strategy, of delineating what to him seems to be an acceptable type of explanation for the biological sciences. [Mendelsohn, E. Commentary, Part I. Conference on Explanation in Biology: Historical. Philosophical, and Scientific aspects. J. Hist. Biol. 2: 135–140, 1969, p. 139.]

    Google Scholar 

  104. Shimony, A. Some proposals concerning parts and wholes, in Parts and Wholes. Swedish Council for Planning and Coordination of Research. Stockholm, 1983, pp. 115–122.

    Google Scholar 

  105. Whitehead AN. Science and the Modern World. New York: Macmillan Company, 1925.

    Google Scholar 

  106. Coleridge ST. Hints Towards the Formation of a More Comprehensive Theory of Life. London: John Chruchill, 1848. Apropos this dialectical issue, there are some uncanningly pre-Whiteheadian statements in this monograph: But to form the first conception of a real thing, we state both as one in the idea, duration….or the oneness of space and time, is the predicate of all real being…. But as little can we conceive the oneness, except as the mid-point producing itself on each side; that is, manifesting itself on two opposite poles. Thus, from identity we derive duality, and from both together we obtain polarity, synthesis, indifference, predominance…. (p. 53).

    Google Scholar 

  107. That Coleridge can be so easily linked to Whitehead, simply re-emphasizes the affinity Whitehead had for the Romantic (as acknowledged in his debt to Wordsworth). What I find of particular interest is the strong dialectical component, the polarity and synthesis in Nature that so marked Naturphilosophie and so profoundly influenced Coleridge, and then re-emerged in Whitehead’s metaphysics, albeit in a refracted form.

    Google Scholar 

  108. In a sense, Naturphilosophie can be viewed as one among many forms in which Romanticism manifested itself. It was perhaps, as one commentator put it, merely—one extreme systematization [Snelders, HAM Inorganic natural sciences 1797–1840: An introductory survey. Studies in Romanticism 9: 193–215, 1970, p. 195.] of Romantic ideas. [Raimonda Modiano, Coleridge and the Concept of Nature. Tallahassee; Florida State Univ. Press, 1985, p. 141.]

    Google Scholar 

  109. For analysis of Theory of Life, see T.H. Levere, Poetry Realized in Nature, Samuel Taylor Coleridge and Early 19th Century Science. Cambridge, 1981, pp. 42–45; 161–166; 215–219, and Coleridge’s “reactionary” influence on medicine and biology see A. Desmond, The Politics of Evolution. Chicago: Univ. of Chicago Press, 1989.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  110. David Guest in A Textbook of Dialectical Materialism (New York: International Publishers, 1939) cites several attempts (e.g. H. Levy, Aspects of Dialectical Materialism, London: Watts and Co., 1934, J.B.S. Haldane, The Marxist Philosophy and the Sciences. Freeport, N.Y. Books for Library, Press, 1939. Marcel Prenant Biology and Marxism translated by CD. Greaves, New York: International Publishers, 1943) at showing the relevance of dialectical materialism for biology “when he is not afraid of the social conclusions to be drawn from it” (p. 102). In fact, these studies, like virtually every treatment of the subject, are politically motivated and either are passionately supportive or rejecting it out of hand (i.e. Sidney Hook’s Dialectical Materialism and Scientific Method, Manchester: Committee of Science and Reason, 1955). A dispassionate assessment of dialectical thinking in biology, that would attempt to place dialectical materialism within its appropriate extra-Soviet context, is still required. In the context of our concern, dialectical is used in the sense used by E.S. Russell, without the embrace of Engel, whose political motivations were apparently overlooked by infatuated sympathizers like Joseph Needham: [Engel’s concept of nature as dialectical] was rightly directed against the static conceptions of the scientists of his time, who were unprepared for the mass of contradictions that science was about to have to deal with, and who did not appreciate that nature is full of apparently irreconcilable antagonisms and distinctions which are reconciled at higher organisational levels. [Needham, J. A Biologist’s view of Whitehead, in The Philosophy of Alfred North Whitehead. The Library of Living Philosophers, ed. PA Schilpp. Menasha, Wisconsin: Banta Publishing Co., 1941, pp. 243–271.]

    Google Scholar 

  111. The sentiment is sympathetic, but the scientific contribution remains problematic.

    Google Scholar 

  112. Wetter, G.A. Dialectical Materialism. A Historical and Systematic Survey of Philosophy in the Soviet Union. Translated by P. Heath. New York: Praeger, 1958.

    Google Scholar 

  113. Gould, S.J. Is a new and general theory of evolution emerging? Paleobiology 6: 119–130, 1980.

    Google Scholar 

  114. See the respective essays of Partricia Foster and Sahotra Sarkar in this volume.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1991 Kluwer Academic Publishers

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Tauber, A.I. (1991). Introduction: Speculations Concerning the Origins of the Self. In: Tauber, A.I. (eds) Organism and the Origins of Self. Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science, vol 129. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-011-3406-4_1

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-011-3406-4_1

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-0-7923-1185-0

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-011-3406-4

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics