Skip to main content

His Notion of the Absolute

  • Chapter
An Idealistic Pragmatism
  • 52 Accesses

Abstract

A very likely reason for the tendency to regard idealism and pragmatism as incompatible is the “absolutism” which the former generally espouses. The pragmatist frequently finds any notion of an Absolute unacceptable because it supposedly closes the door to other possibilities. Instead of any absolute monistic system, the typical pragmatist wants a healthy pluralism, which might provide him with a never-ending fund of workable, practical theories. No system, least of all an absolutistic system, could (supposedly) do this. A treatment of Royce’s notion of the Absolute is therefore much in order at this point, for Royce definitely retains his doctrine of the Absolute along with the pragmatic element that we find developing in his philosophy. It is the aim of this chapter to discover how he does this.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. FE, 345.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  3. FE, 346.

    Google Scholar 

  4. E.g., Vol. 54, “Fragments of Ph.D. Thesis…,” I.a.45: “how wide the gulf is between believing that we know and knowing.”

    Google Scholar 

  5. Cf. FE, 360.

    Google Scholar 

  6. FE, 358–359.

    Google Scholar 

  7. FE, 359.

    Google Scholar 

  8. FE, 363.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Cf. Chapter II, section B, supra.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Vol. 55, “The Critical Theory of Knowledge,” 5.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Use of capitals follows the general usage of Royce, although he himself is not utterly consistent on the point. Whatever substantives refer to the Absolute or God are capitalized, but personal pronouns referring to the same are not. Substantives which indicate man’s partial involvement in the Absolute are never capitalized.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Primer of Logical Analysis…, MS Copy, preserved at Houghton Library of Harvard University, 18.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Vol. 55, “1878 Notes,” 8.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Ibid., 10. Cf. Aristotle’s “basic premises” as he describes these in Posterior Analytics 1, 2.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Josiah Royce, “The Intention of the Prometheus Bound of Aeschylus, being an Investigation in the Dept. of Greek Theology (B.A. Thesis, University of California, 1875),” Bulletin of the University of California, June, 1875, 17. (In the original text the word after “believed” is is, but since the context suggests that this is a typographical or printer’s error, this is changed to in to make for more fluent reading.)

    Google Scholar 

  16. Cf. Vol. 79, “Reality and Consciousness,” 8.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Cf. Ibid., 3–5.

    Google Scholar 

  18. FE, 336–337.

    Google Scholar 

  19. FE, 337.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  21. FE, 337–338.

    Google Scholar 

  22. FE, 363. Cf. 338.

    Google Scholar 

  23. In RAP Royce makes an interesting point of identifying “absolute” and “real” in applying these terms to the distinction between truth and error: “[W]hen we here talk of an ‘absolute’ distinction between truth and error, we mean merely a ‘real’ distinction between truth and error. And this real distinction the fiercest partisan of relativity admits; for does he not after all argue for relativity against ‘absolutists,’ holding that he is really right, and they really wrong.” (376)

    Google Scholar 

  24. Cf. Vol. 79, “Of the Will…,” 9, 27, 41–2.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Vol. 80, “Some Illustrations…,” 47.

    Google Scholar 

  26. Josiah Royce, “Mind and Reality,” Mind 7 (1882), 51. Hereafter, M&R.

    Google Scholar 

  27. Cf. Ibid, and with Thayer’s description of pragmatism as necessarily involving the notion of possibilities as traits of reality (426).

    Google Scholar 

  28. Cf. M&R, 51–52. Note use of subjunctive in text: “This absolute experience, to which all facts would exhibit themselves in their connexion as uniformly subject to fixed law, is conceived as ‘possible.’ ”

    Google Scholar 

  29. M&R, 53.

    Google Scholar 

  30. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  31. M&R, 37.

    Google Scholar 

  32. FE, 346. Moreover, as Royce points out in an early article, even intuition cannot furnish us with proof positive in regard to the existence of the Absolute. Cf. Vol. 60, “Reality and Consciousness,” 43, 44: “We do not look for any intuition of the Absolute, for any revelation internally of a reality that is at the same time and in the same sense external; we seek only for the simplest and most consistent expression of the assumptions of our thoughts, hoping not to make them appear to be anything but assumptions. To do otherwise is to make gods with our own hands for the sake of worshipping them.”

    Google Scholar 

  33. Cf. Vol. 79, “Reality and Consciousness,” 6.

    Google Scholar 

  34. E.g. M&R, 39: “Our hypothesis is not pantheistic or theistic.”

    Google Scholar 

  35. Vol. 60, “Reality and Consciousness,” 38.

    Google Scholar 

  36. M&R, 54.

    Google Scholar 

  37. RAP, 433.

    Google Scholar 

  38. Cf. RAP, 134.

    Google Scholar 

  39. RAP, 442.

    Google Scholar 

  40. Cf. RAP, 176.

    Google Scholar 

  41. Note that diversity is essential to real harmony; else it reduces to unison or uniformity.

    Google Scholar 

  42. RAP, 175. (Italics in text.)

    Google Scholar 

  43. RAP, 140–141.

    Google Scholar 

  44. Cf. RAP, 201.

    Google Scholar 

  45. RAP, 211.

    Google Scholar 

  46. Recalling that Royce’s philosophy is essentially a philosophy of religion, consider the following: “The essence of Religion is therefore faith in the actual power of just and charitable deeds to render him happy who lives in constant performance of them, and faith consequently in a Power that secures the moral ordering of the universe. Whatever sect supports these principles, is a religious sect, whatever its other articles of faith. Whatever sect opposes them is truly atheistic, however outspoken its confessional orthodoxy.” (Vol. 55, “Fragment about Dec. 1877,” 46)

    Google Scholar 

  47. RAP, 217.

    Google Scholar 

  48. RAP, 217–218.

    Google Scholar 

  49. RAP, 218.

    Google Scholar 

  50. For an excellent treatment of Royce’s moral philosophy, see Peter Fuss, The Moral Philosophy of Josiah Royce (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1965).

    Google Scholar 

  51. Cf. RAP, 455. Also, cf. RAP, 252–283. Royce here refutes theistic positions other than his own; e.g., a monism not founded on experience, dualism — which is ultimately self-contradictory, and the “halting half Theism of the empirical Design Argument.” (279)

    Google Scholar 

  52. RAP, 455.

    Google Scholar 

  53. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  54. RAP, 453, 452. Cf. 455, where the pantheistic strain of Royce’s thought is even more manifest: “As the evil impulse is to the good man so is the evil will of the wicked man to the life of God, in which he is an element.”

    Google Scholar 

  55. RAP, 454. (Italics in text.) Note the future subjunctive and cf. Peirce’s fondness for same.

    Google Scholar 

  56. Cf. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  57. Cf. RAP, 382.

    Google Scholar 

  58. RAP, 381.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1972 Martinus Nijhoff, The Hague, Netherlands

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Mahowald, M.B. (1972). His Notion of the Absolute. In: An Idealistic Pragmatism. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-010-2736-6_4

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-010-2736-6_4

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-247-1184-0

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-010-2736-6

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics