Skip to main content

Part of the book series: Synthese Historical Library ((SYHL,volume 9))

Abstract

By ‘logic’ I mean ‘the analysis of argument or proof in terms of form’. The two main examples of Greek logic are, then, Aristotle’s syllogistic developed in the first twenty-two chapters of the Prior Analytics and Stoic propositional logic as reconstructed in the twentieth century. The topic I shall consider in this paper is the relation between Greek logic in this sense and Greek mathematics. I have resolved the topic into two questions: (1) To what extent do the principles of Greek logic derive from the forms of proof characteristic of Greek mathematics? and (2) To what extent do the Greek mathematicians show an awareness of Greek logic?

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 119.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. The translations of the Elements are by T. Heath, The Thirteen Books of Euclid’s Elements, 3 vols., Cambridge, England, 1925.

    Google Scholar 

  2. John Philoponus, In Aristotelis Analytica Priora Commentaria (ed. by M. Wallies), Berlin, 1905, 246.3–4, gives a similar illustration of the fifth anapodeiktos: ‘The side is either equal to or greater than or less than the side; but it is neither greater nor less; therefore it is equal’. For details on the anapodeiktoi and other aspects of Stoic logic, see B. Mates, Stoic Logic, Berkeley 1961.

    Google Scholar 

  3. These divisions and their names are taken from Proclus, In Primum Euclidis Elementorum Librum Commentarii (ed. by G. Friedlein), Leipzig, 1873, 203.1–210.16. The rigidity which they suggest is fully confirmed by Euclid’s Elements; and the terms them-selves, or forms of them, can all be found in third-century mathematical works. For references, see C. Mugler, Dictionnaire Historique de la terminologie geomitrique des grecs, Paris 1958.

    Google Scholar 

  4. As in D. Hilbert, Foundations of Geometry (transl. by L. Unger), La Salle, 111., 10th ed., 1971.

    Google Scholar 

  5. J. Łukasiewicz, Aristotle’s Syllogistic, Oxford, 2nd ed., 1957, p. 1, asserts that Aristotle does not allow singular terms in syllogisms. If Lukasiewicz is right, then no Euclidean argument would be an Aristotelian syllogism.

    Google Scholar 

  6. See, for example, H. Zeuthen, Geschichte der Mathematik im Altertum und Mittelalter, Copenhagen 1896, p. 117.

    Google Scholar 

  7. See Alexander of Aphrodisias, In Aristotelis Analyticorum Priorum Librum I Commentarium (ed. by M. Wallies ), Berlin 1883, 344. 13–20.

    Google Scholar 

  8. For inadequate attempts to explain the move, see Proclus, In Primum Elementorum, 49.4–57.8; and J. S. Mill, A System of Logic, London, 9th ed., 1875, III. ii. 2.

    Google Scholar 

  9. See, for example, F. Klein, Elementary Mathematics from an Advanced Standpoint (transl. by E. R. Hedrick and C. A. Noble), New York 1939, II, pp. 196–202.

    Google Scholar 

  10. H. Hasse and H. Scholz, ‘Die Grundlagenkrisis in der griechischen Mathematik’, Kant-Studien XXXIH (1928), 17, call it a first attempt at an axiomatization in the modern sense.

    Google Scholar 

  11. See ‘Continuity and Irrational Numbers’ in R. Dedekind, Essays on the Theory of Numbers (transl. by W. Beman), Chicago 1924, pp. 15–17.

    Google Scholar 

  12. F. Beckmann, in ‘Neue Gesichtspunkte zum 5. Buch Euklids’, Archive for History of Exact Sciences IV (1967/8), 106–107, lists twenty-four ‘tacit assumptions’ of Book V.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Łukasiewicz, Aristotle’s Syllogistic, p. 6, denies Platonic influence. But see W. and M. Kneale, The Development of Logic, Oxford 1962, pp. 44, 67–68.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Translation by T. Heath, Mathematics in Aristotle, Oxford 1949, p. 26. This is an excellent work to consult for details of the mathematical aspects of the passages I am discussing.

    Google Scholar 

  15. W. D. Ross, Aristotle’s Prior and Posterior Analytics, Oxford 1949, pp. 412–414.

    Google Scholar 

  16. For the details, see Simplicius, In Aristotelis Physicorum Libros Quattuor Priores Commentaria (ed. by H. Diels), Berlin 1882, 60.22–68.32.

    Google Scholar 

  17. The evidence is collected in F. Wehrli, Die Schule des Aristoteles, Basel/Stuttgart, 2nd ed., 1969, VIII, 11–20.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Quoted by Simplicius, In Aristotelis Categorias Commentarium (ed. by C. Kalbfieisch), Berlin 1907, 394.13–395.31.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Institutio, V.5 (said of those about Chrysippus). Diogenes Laertius, Vitae Philosophorum (ed. by H. S. Long), Oxford 1964, VII. 190, lists among Chrysippus’s works ‘On a true diezeugmenon’ and ‘On a true sunemmenon’

    Google Scholar 

  20. Sextus Empiricus, Adversus Mathematicos, VIII.443, in Opera II (ed. by H. Mutsch- mann and J. Mau), Leipzig 1914. Alexander associates the one-premissed arguments with ‘those about Antipater’ (In Topicorum, 8.16–19). Other relevant passages are col¬lected in C. Piantl, Geschichte der Logik im Abendlande, Leipzig 1855, I, 477–478.

    Google Scholar 

  21. In Analyticorum Priorum, 164.30–31, 278.6–14. At 284.13–17 Alexander ascribes to hoi apo tes Stoas the second, third, and fourth themata. On the themata, see O. Becker, Vber die vier Themata des stoischen Logik, in Zwei Untersuchungen zur antiken Logik, Klassisch-philologische Studien XVII (1957), 27–49.

    Google Scholar 

  22. See the passages in H. Bonitz, ‘Index Aristotelicus’, in Aristotelis Opera (ed. by I. Bekker), Berlin 1831–70, V, 70b4–13.

    Google Scholar 

  23. G. Vlastos, ‘Zeno of Sidon as a Critic of Euclid’, in The Classical Tradition (ed. by L. Wallach ), Ithaca, N.Y., 1966, pp. 154–155.

    Google Scholar 

  24. W. Cronert, Kolotes und Menedemos, Studien zur Palaeographie und Papyruskunde VI (1906), 109.

    Google Scholar 

  25. O. Neugebauer, über eine Methode zur Distanzbestimmung Alexandria-Rom bei Heron, Det Kgl. Danske Videnskabernes Selskab XXVI (1938), 21–24.

    Google Scholar 

  26. See. K Tittel, De Gemini Stoici Studiis Mathematicis Quaestiones Philologae, Leipzig 1895. Brehier (‘Posidonius d’Apamee’, pp. 46–49) thinks that Geminus’s work on math¬ematics is derived entirely from Posidonius.

    Google Scholar 

  27. See E. Zeller, Die Philosophie der Griechen in ihrer geschichtlichen Entwicklung, Leipzig, 5th ed., 1923, pt. 3, sec. 2, pp. 642–645. The same material is found in E. Zeller, A History of Eclecticism in Greek Philosophy (transl. by S. F. Alleyne), London 1883, pp. 113–117. The importance of the reawakening of interest in Aristotle’s work for the history of logic is stressed by J. Mau, ‘Stoische Logik’, Hermes LXXXV (1957), 147–158. The historical reconstruction of the present paper seems to provide support for Mau’s views.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1974 D. Reidel Publishing Company, Dordrecht-Holland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Mueller, I. (1974). Greek Mathematics and Greek Logic. In: Corcoran, J. (eds) Ancient Logic and Its Modern Interpretations. Synthese Historical Library, vol 9. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-010-2130-2_4

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-010-2130-2_4

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-94-010-2132-6

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-010-2130-2

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics