Skip to main content

The Persecution of Absolutes: On the Kantian and Neo-Kantian Theories of Science

  • Chapter
The Kaleidoscope of Science

Part of the book series: Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science ((BSPS,volume 94))

Abstract

Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason intends, in part, to be a theory of science; to what extent is a matter of interpretation. Of the German philosophical systems inspired by him, some sought to abolish, conserve and transform his premises all at once — in the famous triple sense that Hegel ascribed to ’sublation’ (Aufhebung). Others regarded their own philosophy as a creative interpretation of Kant’s system. The former group, the speculative idealists like Fichte, Schelling and Hegel, lost any specific interest in the foundations of the exact sciences — in the same way as scientists rarely sought contact with them: they rather tended to stress the gap between speculation and Wissenschaft. A scientific orientation was retained or revived among those philosophers who viewed themselves as authentic interpreters of Kant — from Solomon Maimon to the School of Marburg. Neo-Kantianism, like phenomenology a generation later, began with a protest against vulgar positivism (or psychologism). Yet Husserl — particularly in the Logische Untersuchungen — took some of his leading models from pure mathematics and tried to develop an empirical idealism of sorts, i.e. a taxonomy of concrete a priori entities; while the Neo-Kantians of Marburg (as opposed to those in Baden) were guided by models derived from mathematical physics.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. The paradoxes of induction involve either the syntax of law-like statements (such as the Raven Paradox) or their predicates (such as Goodman’s Paradox). In the latter case, the paradox applies as much to the possibility of verification as it does to the possibility of falsification. Every inductive generalization which summarizes previous observations in the forms (x)(A(x)B(x)) can be said to be either’verified’ or’not falsified’ irrespective of whether we shall find in the future that B(x) or that B(x) is the case, since it is quite possible that the property (predicate) that we interpreted as B(x) in the past was, in reality, another property B(x t-o) B(x t>o), which behaves like B(x) in the past. Cf. N. Goodman, Facts, Fiction and Forecast (Indianapolis, 1965), pp. 59–83.

    Google Scholar 

  2. G.W. Leibniz, Philosophische Schriften, ed. C.I. Gebhart (Berlin, 1885; reprint Hildesheim, 1965), IV, p. 6; VI, pp. 50, 321; VII, pp. 278, 303, 304, 603. Cf. A. Funkenstein, “The Dialectical Preparation of Scientific Revolutions,” in: The Copernican Achievement, ed. R. Westman (Los Angeles, 1975), pp. 165–203, esp. 178–187.

    Google Scholar 

  3. William of Ockham, Centiloquium theologicum, concl. VI. Both in my article (note 2) and elsewhere (“Continuity and Change in 17th Century Thought and Science,” Publications of the Israel Academy of Sciences, VI, 6, Jerusalem, 1981, pp. 101–131) I have argued that, in contrast to the Middle Ages, science in the seventeenth century employed counterfactual states - ideal experiments - not to demonstrate God’s omnipotence, but as limiting cases of reality. Such thought-experiments (e.g. inertial motion) do not describe reality, yet are constitutive for its understanding. Cf. p. 59.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Thomas Aquinas, Summa Theologiae 9 q. 25 a. 5 resp. 3; De Potentia q. 3.a. 17, p. 103. In both places, Aquinas employs the remarks of Maimonides about the limit of every rationalization — that is, the element of contingency necessary in every conception of universal order. Cf. my comment in Miscellanea Medievalia XI (1977), p. 89, n. 27.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Immanuel Kant, Kritik der reinen Vernunft (hereafter KdrV), Gesammelte Schriften (Berlin, 1911), B 599–611.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Ibid., B 95–98.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Aristotle, Metaphysica V, 1022b22.

    Google Scholar 

  8. A. Maier, Kants Qualitätskategorien (Kantstudien 65), Berlin 1930, pp. 8–23; “Die Mathematik der Formalattituden,” in: An der Grenze von Scholastik und Naturwissenschaft (Rome, 1922); E. Sylla, “Medieval Conceptions of the Latitude of Forms — the Oxford Calculatores,” Archive d’Histoire doctrinale et literaire du Moyen Age 51 (1974): 223–283.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Kant, KdrV, B 611 (note).

    Google Scholar 

  10. Hermann Cohen, Logik der reinen Erkenntnis (Berlin, 19142), p. 68. In the following, I have not attempted to root out the shift from Cohen’s earlier perspective (in: Das Prinzip der Infinitissemalmethode und seine Geschichte (reprint, Frankfurt am Main, 1968)) to his mature theory of science.

    Google Scholar 

  11. B. Croce, Die Philosophie Giambattista Vico’s, transl. E. Auerbach and Th. Lucke (Tübingen, 1927), pp. 3–17;

    Google Scholar 

  12. K. Löwith, “Vico’s Grundsatz: verum et factum convertuntur,” in: Aufsatze und Vortrdge 1930–1970 (Stuttgart, 1971), pp. 157–188

    Google Scholar 

  13. S.H. Bergmann, “The Principle of Apriority in the Philosophy of Hermann Cohen,” Knesset 1944; Introduction to Logic (Jerusalem, 1953), pp. 210–213.

    Google Scholar 

  14. W. Marx, Transzendentale Logik als Wissenschaftstheorie (Frankfurt am Main, 1977), pp. 103 ff., esp. 119 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Since this is so, W. Marx argues that Cohen never succeeds in establishing science as the exclusive property of pure thought (op. cit., pp. 133–154). But he does not treat self- referential structures in Cohen’s interpretation explicitly.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Above note 3.

    Google Scholar 

  17. D. Henrich, Hegel im Kontext (Frankfurt am Main, 1971), pp. 95 ff., showed how the dialectical moves in the Wesenslogik can be interpreted as a logic of explication. Cohen, whose logic is both open-ended and nothing but a logic of scientific discovery, renders himself even better for such a perspective.

    Google Scholar 

  18. W.O. Quine, “The Two Dogmas of Empiricism,” From a Logical Point of View (Cambridge, Mass., 1953)

    Google Scholar 

  19. H.P. Grice and F.P. Strawson, “On Defense of a Dogma,” Philosophical Review 65 (1956): 141–158.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  20. Robert Musil, Der Mann ohne Eigenschaften (Hamburg, 1952), p. 40.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Editor information

Edna Ullmann-Margalit

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1986 D. Reidel Publishing Company

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Funkenstein, A. (1986). The Persecution of Absolutes: On the Kantian and Neo-Kantian Theories of Science. In: Ullmann-Margalit, E. (eds) The Kaleidoscope of Science. Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science, vol 94. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-5496-0_5

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-5496-0_5

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-277-2159-4

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-009-5496-0

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics