Skip to main content

Part of the book series: Contributions to Phenomenology ((CTPH,volume 1))

  • 212 Accesses

Abstract

Most broadly expressed, the phenomenological theme investigated in the preceding chapters is: “being in the real, objective world pertaining to my mental living as transcendental mental living in the natural attitude.”1 More narrowly expressed, this theme was developed with respect to the “genesis” of the ideas of time and space as products of subscientific-philosophic thinking and experiencing that take for granted the positing of the naturalness belonging to the natural attitude2—a development that consciously set aside the “naturalistic conception” of the ideas of time and space with respect to their specifying assumptions exercised in modern philosophy and science.3 In particular there were two central specifying assumptions singled out for attention and on which the epistemic and ontic claims of modern scientific and philosophic thinking and experiencing rest (section 38ff.). The first is the idea that geometry and kinematics define space, and if space defines reality it would seem to follow that geometry and kinematics define reality.4

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 169.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 219.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 219.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. See above, pp. 28, 95.

    Google Scholar 

  2. See above, pp. 32f., 107f.

    Google Scholar 

  3. See above, pp. 108ff., 121ff.

    Google Scholar 

  4. This situation has made itself felt in recent discussions of so-called “medical ethics;” see F. Kersten, “The Life Concept and Life Conviction: A Phenomenological Sketch,” pp. 11 Off.

    Google Scholar 

  5. This leads to the substitution of concepts of scientific thinking for those of subscientific thinking and experiencing; see in this connection, F. Kersten, The Constancy Hypothesis in the Social Sciences,’ pp. 524ff.

    Google Scholar 

  6. See above, p. 109.

    Google Scholar 

  7. See above, pp. 155ff.

    Google Scholar 

  8. See F. Kersten, “The Life Concept and Life Conception,” pp. 112f.

    Google Scholar 

  9. In this connection, see Claesges, Edmund Husserls Theorie der Raumkonstitution, section 9, pp. 45ff.; Elisabeth Ströker, Philosophische Untersuchungen zum Raum, especially III. Abschnitt.

    Google Scholar 

  10. See above, pp. 43ff., 71.

    Google Scholar 

  11. See above, pp. 55, 89ff.

    Google Scholar 

  12. See above, p. 89.

    Google Scholar 

  13. See above, pp. 92f.

    Google Scholar 

  14. See above, p. 93f.

    Google Scholar 

  15. See above, p. 92. For a detailed review of Husserl’s discussion, see Claesges, sections 5–10.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Claesges, p. 34. The translation is mine.

    Google Scholar 

  17. See Ideas, I, sections 23f.; 12.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Ibid., section 15.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Ibid., section 72.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Ibid., section 73.

    Google Scholar 

  22. The analogy has its origin in the Third Logical Investigation, section 3ff., and especially section 25, p. 289 (second edition): “Die Zerstückung der quasi-räumlichen Ausbreitung eines visu-allen, unverändert dauernden, aber in Abstraktion von dem zeitlichen Moment betrachteten Inhalts bestimmt auch eine Zerstückung dieses Inhalts selbst.”

    Google Scholar 

  23. See Ideas, I, section 88.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Ideas, I, section 49.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Ibid., section 50.

    Google Scholar 

  26. Ibid., section 53; see above, pp. 12ff., 55f., 111.

    Google Scholar 

  27. Primarily in Carl Stumpf, Über den psychologischen Ursprung der Raumvorstellung, pp. 106ff.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Gurwitsch, Phenomenology of Thematics,’ p. 262.

    Google Scholar 

  29. Ibid., pp. 266ff. It should be noted in this connection that Gurwitsch avoids Husserl’s reformulations in Ideas, I, sections 12 and 15, and that he does not consider the distinction between discrete and non-discrete parts.

    Google Scholar 

  30. See above, pp. 15f.

    Google Scholar 

  31. To be sure, Gurwitsch wants to understand something different by “ego” than does Husserl; see Gurwitsch, “A non-egological Concept of Consciousness,” Studies in Phenomenology and Psychology, pp. 287ff. For a more Husserlian account of the “ego,” see Robert W. Jordan, “Being and Time: Some Aspects of the Ego’s Involvement in his Mental Life,” in Phenomenology: Continuation and Criticism, pp. 105ff.; for a more conservative view, see F. Kersten, “Privatgesichter,” pp. 128f.

    Google Scholar 

  32. This would seem to be the gist of Ideas, Second Book, section 64. In this connection, see Ludwig Landgrebe, “Seinsregionen und regionale Ontologien in Husserls Phänomenologie,” in Ludwig Landgrebe, Der Weg der Phänomenologie, pp. 143ff.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Landgrebe, p. 148.

    Google Scholar 

  34. For another version of this criticism, see F. Kersten, “Heidegger and Transcendental Phenomenology,” pp. 211ff.

    Google Scholar 

  35. Landgrebe, p. 153. The translation is mine. For Landgrebe’s role in the preparation of Ideas, Second Book, see Husserliana IV, pp. xviiif.

    Google Scholar 

  36. Landgrebe, p. 153; Husserl, Ideas, II, p. 208. See also Alfred Schütz, “Husserl’s Ideas, Volume II,” in Collected Papers, edited by I. Schütz (The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1966), pp. 27ff.; and Paul Ricoeur, “Husserl’s Ideas II: Analyses and Problems,” in Paul Ricoeur, Husserl. An Analysis of His Phenomenology, pp. 76ff.

    Google Scholar 

  37. See above, pp. 298ff.

    Google Scholar 

  38. Husserl, Ideas, II, p. 208.

    Google Scholar 

  39. Ibid., section 2. See Landgrebe, p. 154.

    Google Scholar 

  40. Ibid., section 49ff.

    Google Scholar 

  41. Ibid., pp. 297f.

    Google Scholar 

  42. Ibid., pp. 299, 301 f. The translations are mine.

    Google Scholar 

  43. See the “Einleitung des Herausgebers,” Husserliana IV, pp. xviiiff.

    Google Scholar 

  44. Landgrebe, p. 157.

    Google Scholar 

  45. Ibid., p. 158. The translation is mine.

    Google Scholar 

  46. Husserl, Ideas, I, sections 78, 79.

    Google Scholar 

  47. See above, section 4, p. 14.

    Google Scholar 

  48. See above, pp. 27f.

    Google Scholar 

  49. See above, pp. 19f., 24f., 28f., 35f.

    Google Scholar 

  50. Descartes, Philosophical Essays, translated with an Introduction and Notes by Laurence J. Lafleur (Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill Company, 1964), pp. 100, 102. See above, section 38.

    Google Scholar 

  51. Gottfried Wilhelm von Leibniz, Monadology and Other Philosophical Essays, translated by Paul Schrecker and Anne Martin Schrecker, p. 6.

    Google Scholar 

  52. See above, section 39.

    Google Scholar 

  53. David Hume, A Treatise of Human Nature, edited by L.A. Selby-Bigge, p. 65.

    Google Scholar 

  54. Ibid., p. 66.

    Google Scholar 

  55. Immanuel Kant, Kritik der reinen Vernunft, B 629f. The translation is by Norman Kemp Smith, Immanuel Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason, p. 506f.

    Google Scholar 

  56. Ibid., B 626; translation, p. 504. See also Eugen Fink, Alles und Nichts, Ein Umweg zur Philosophie, pp. 140ff.; Roman Ingarden, Der Streit um die Existenz der Welt, p. 61. See above, section 40f.

    Google Scholar 

  57. Ingarden, pp. 60f.; see also Roman Ingarden, Das Literarische Kunstwerk, section 15. In addition, see H.J. Paton, Kant’s Metaphysic of Experience, II, pp. 358ff.

    Google Scholar 

  58. See above, pp. 27f.

    Google Scholar 

  59. Jules Vuillemin, Physique et Métaphysique Kantiennes, p. 343. See also pp. 345ff. Exactly what, by implication, are the “postulates of the epoché” Vuillemin does not say.

    Google Scholar 

  60. For a review of Brentano’s ideas in this connection, see F. Kersten, “Franz Brentano and William James,” pp. 177ff.

    Google Scholar 

  61. Husserl, Logische Untersuchungen, 2 II, 1, p. 428; II, 2, pp. 139f. English translation, pp. 598f., 780ff.

    Google Scholar 

  62. Ibid., II, 1, p. 430; translation, p. 599.

    Google Scholar 

  63. That is to say, Kant, like Brentano, holds that there is but one generic feature of mental living; accordingly, as Gurwitsch has shown, there is likewise but one meaning of “objectivity” in Kant. See Aron Gurwitsch, “La Conception de la conscience chez Kant et chez Husserl,” pp. 73ff.

    Google Scholar 

  64. See above, p. 287.

    Google Scholar 

  65. Husserl, Logische Untersuchungen, II, 1, p. 437. The translation is mine.

    Google Scholar 

  66. See Ideas, I, section 104.

    Google Scholar 

  67. See Husserl, Logische Untersuchungen, II, 2, section Iff.; Adolf Reinach, “Zur Theorie des negativen Urteils,” Gesammelte Schriften, pp. 57ff.

    Google Scholar 

  68. See Husserl, Logische Untersuchungen, II, 2, section 43; see above, pp. 89ff., and F. Kersten, “Can Sartre Count?” pp. 343f.

    Google Scholar 

  69. See above, p. 28.

    Google Scholar 

  70. See above, p. 286.

    Google Scholar 

  71. See above, pp. 15f.

    Google Scholar 

  72. Ideas, I, section 90, p. 185.

    Google Scholar 

  73. See above, pp. 14ff., 33ff.

    Google Scholar 

  74. Ideas, I p. 186.

    Google Scholar 

  75. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  76. Kant, Kritik der reinen Vernunft, B 627; translation, p. 505.

    Google Scholar 

  77. Ibid., B 629; translation, p. 506.

    Google Scholar 

  78. Ideas, I, p. 187.

    Google Scholar 

  79. Ibid., p. 188.

    Google Scholar 

  80. Ibid., section 102, p. 214; cf. section 103ff.

    Google Scholar 

  81. Rudolf Boehm, “Zum Begriff des ‘Absoluten’ bei Husserl,” p. 221. Translation in R.O. Elveton, The Phenomenology of Husserl, p. 179.

    Google Scholar 

  82. See Husserl, Logische Untersuchungen, Zweiter Band, Zweiter Teil, (Husserliana XIX/2), pp. 851f. for the distinction between spread and extension.

    Google Scholar 

  83. See Ideas, I, section 44ff.

    Google Scholar 

  84. See above, pp. 302f.

    Google Scholar 

  85. Boehm, translation, p. 180.

    Google Scholar 

  86. Ideas, I, section 46.

    Google Scholar 

  87. Cf. Thomas Hobbes, The Elements of Philosophy, Part II, Chapter VII. Also see above, pp. 120ff.

    Google Scholar 

  88. Ideas, I, p. 110.

    Google Scholar 

  89. Boehm, translation, pp. 181, 182.

    Google Scholar 

  90. See Ideas, I, section 103ff.

    Google Scholar 

  91. Or to express the situation as Husserl does in Logische Untersuchungen, II, 12 pp. 400ff., especially pp. 435f. (translation, pp. 578ff., 604f.), the distinction is between the object which is intended to and the object as it is intended to; see also Gurwitsch, The Field of Consciousness, pp. 185ff.

    Google Scholar 

  92. Nor is this yet a case of predication; see Gurwitsch, “Perceptual Coherence as the Foundation of the Judgment of Predication,” pp. 84ff.

    Google Scholar 

  93. See above, pp. 27f.

    Google Scholar 

  94. Above, pp. 30f., 34f.

    Google Scholar 

  95. Above, pp. 28f.

    Google Scholar 

  96. Husserl, Formal and Transcendental Logic, pp. 272f. Translation by Cairns.

    Google Scholar 

  97. See above, p. 70.

    Google Scholar 

  98. Formal and Transcendental Logic, p. 273. See above, sections 20, 34, 78f., 80.

    Google Scholar 

  99. See above, p. 325.

    Google Scholar 

  100. Boehm, translation, pp. 196f.

    Google Scholar 

  101. Some indication is given above, p. 226, in the discussion of Becker; see also Becker, “Beiträge zur phänomenologischen Begründung,” pp. 419ff., 457ff. See also above, pp. 60ff., 119, 154f., for some indication of the scope and nature of the problems that arise at this juncture.

    Google Scholar 

  102. Kant, Kritik der reinen Vernunft, B 294f. Translation, p. 257.

    Google Scholar 

  103. Husserl, Ideas, I, p. 235.

    Google Scholar 

  104. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  105. Husserl, Cartesian Meditations, p. 132.

    Google Scholar 

  106. Ibid., p. 142.

    Google Scholar 

  107. Ibid., p. 146.

    Google Scholar 

  108. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  109. Ibid. Also see above, sections 17, 18. In Formal and Transcendental Logic Husserl gives a yet broader scope to his formulation of transcendental aesthetics and analytics. He proceeds to disclose what he calls the “logos of the aesthetic world” and the “logos in a higher sense” that belongs to the real, objective world and to science, an “analytic logos.” The same “distribution” of dimensions or oriented constitution is to be found as in the Cartesian Meditations, but now set in a specific historical context, namely the context of modern science. This context emerges when Husserl concludes a discussion of the transformation of traditional logic into transcendental phenomenological logic by observing that all the material a priori disciplines the nature of which he developed under the heading of “logic” are developed in the pregnant sense of the term, “logic.” Transcendental logic or, equivalently stated, ontology, elaborates the universal Apriori of a possible world. Such elaboration gives rise at various stages to the problem of a “world-logic” or “ontology of the world” (“mundane Ontologie”). As the study of the underpinings of that structure we find, again in a new sense of the term, transcendental aesthetics which “deals with the eidetic problem of any possible world as a world given in ‘pure experience’ and thus precedes all science in the ‘higher’ sense; accordingly it undertakes the eidetic description of the all-embracing Apriori, without which no Objects could appear unitarily in mere experience, prior to categorial actions..., and therefore without which the unity of a Nature, the unity of a world, as a passively synthesized unity, could not become constituted at all.” (Translation by Dorion Cairns, p. 292.) To be a genuine science, this “logos of the aesthetic world” requires its own appropriate constitutional investigations that eventually lead to “logics” in another sense “among which the highest and most inclusive would be the logic of the absolute science, the logic of transcendental-phenomenological philosophy itself.” (Ibid., p. 291) In another connection, I have tried to formulate the same situation in a rather different way; cf. “Phenomenology, History and Myth,” pp. 262ff.

    Google Scholar 

  110. See above, section 10f.

    Google Scholar 

  111. See F. Kersten, “The Life-World Revisited,” pp. 48ff. See also Grathoff, “Das Problem der InterSubjektivität bei Aron Gurwitsch und Alfred Schütz,” pp. 96ff. and the distinction between the life-world and the “work-world;” the former pertains constitutively to the aesthetics and the latter to the analytics (see ibid., pp. 104ff. for an inventory of those sorts of actional intendings included in the analytics). To express the relationship between them in transcendental terms, we may say that the work-world is the “appearance” of something primordial, the life-world, thus something secondarily constituted. The work-world then includes in its essence the life-world, but the converse in not necessarily the case.

    Google Scholar 

  112. Formal and Transcendental Logic, p. 289.

    Google Scholar 

  113. See ibid., section 95; Cartesian Meditations, section 55. Husserl tends to use the term, “Ichgemeinschaft” (equivalently, “Allgemeinschaft”), “community of egos,” to designate something similar to the constituting of what Tönnies called Gemeinbesitz, the possessing in common of a shared world in common. See Gurwitsch, Encounters in the Social World, pp. 117ff., 125ff.

    Google Scholar 

  114. See Husserl, Formal and Transcendental Logic, section 95; Ideas, I, section 135.

    Google Scholar 

  115. See Husserl, Erfahrung und Urteil, sections 17ff., 34, 40ff., 61ff.

    Google Scholar 

  116. See above, pp. 38ff.

    Google Scholar 

  117. Husserl, Formal and Transcendental Logic, pp. 270f.

    Google Scholar 

  118. Ibid., p. 272.

    Google Scholar 

  119. Ibid., p. 275

    Google Scholar 

  120. Above, pp. 17f.

    Google Scholar 

  121. Cartesian Meditations, P. 156.

    Google Scholar 

  122. Above, p. 106.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1989 Kluwer Academic Publishers

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Kersten, F. (1989). Time, Space, Other. In: Phenomenological Method: Theory and Practice. Contributions to Phenomenology, vol 1. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-2265-5_9

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-2265-5_9

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-94-010-7515-2

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-009-2265-5

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics