Skip to main content

Why There Still Has to be a Language of Thought

  • Chapter
Computers, Brains and Minds

Part of the book series: Australasian Studies in History and Philosophy of Science ((AUST,volume 7))

Abstract

“But why”, Auntie asked with perceptible asperity, “does it have to be a language?” Auntie speaks with the voice of the Establishment, and her intransigence is something awful. She is, however, prepared to make certain concessions in the present case. First, she concedes that there are beliefs and desires and that there is a matter of fact about their intentional contents; there’s a matter of fact, that is to say, about which proposition the intentional object of a belief or a desire is. Second, Auntie accepts the coherence of physicalism. It may be that believing and desiring will prove to be states of the brain, and if they do that’s OK with Auntie. Third, she is prepared to concede that beliefs and desires have causal roles, and that overt behavior is typically the effect of complex interactions among these mental causes. (That Auntie was raised as a strict behaviorist goes without saying. But she hasn’t been quite the same since the 60’s. Come to think of it, which of us has?) In short, Auntie recognizes that psychological explanations need to postulate a network of causally related intentional states. “But why”, she asks with perceptible asperity, “does it have to be a language?” Or, to put it more succinctly than Auntie often does, what — over and above mere Intentional Realism — does the Language of Thought Hypothesis buy? That is what this paper is about.1

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. D.C. Dennett (1978) ‘A Cure for the Common Code?’, Brainstorms, Bradford Books.

    Google Scholar 

  2. R.J. Matthews (1984) ‘Troubles with Representationalism’, Social Research LI, No. 4, pp. 1065–1197. E.P. Stabler (1983) ‘How Are Grammars Represented?’, The Behavioural and Brain Sciences VI, pp. 391–421.

    Google Scholar 

  3. W. Demopoulos and R.J. Matthews (1980) ‘On the Hypothesis that Grammars are Mentally Represented’, The Behavioural and Brain Sciences III, pp. 405–406.

    Google Scholar 

  4. A slightly different version of this paper appears as an appendix in J.A. Fodor (1987) Psychosemantics, Bradford/MIT.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1989 Kluwer Academic Publishers

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Fodor, J.A. (1989). Why There Still Has to be a Language of Thought. In: Slezak, P., Albury, W.R. (eds) Computers, Brains and Minds. Australasian Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, vol 7. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-1181-9_2

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-1181-9_2

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-94-010-7026-3

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-009-1181-9

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics