Skip to main content

Vague Persons

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Vague Objects and Vague Identity

Part of the book series: Logic, Epistemology, and the Unity of Science ((LEUS,volume 33))

  • 786 Accesses

Abstract

This chapter defends certain recent kinds of accounts of personal identity that I call non-traditionalist. These non-traditionalist accounts aim to make sense of resilient disagreements between disputants by appealing to certain features of language, the world, or our knowledge thereof, more familiarly found in the literature on vagueness. Recently, however, it has been argued that when we reflect on the nature of persons at, and across, time, we see that problems arise for two of the three standard accounts of vagueness, namely, for both semanticism and epistemicism. Though not intended as such, these arguments would, if successful, be equally powerful objections to many non-traditionalist accounts of personal identity. This chapter argues that these objections fail, both as objections to the standard accounts of vagueness and, therefore, as objections to non-traditionalist accounts of personal identity. Instead, it argues that non-traditionalist views are live contenders in the debate over personal identity and their consideration is suggestive of new ways of thinking about diachronic prudence. In particular, they offer independent support to the idea that the distribution of utility of person-stages, and not merely the sum of the utility of person-stages, matters to wellbeing.

With thanks to Sam Baron, David Braddon-Mitchell, Michael Duncan, Johann Harriman and James Norton for the helpful discussion of these issues.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Or, if you prefer, many of our ordinary predicates appear to be such that their extension is not a precise set of objects.

  2. 2.

    A paradigm defender of which is Williamson (1994).

  3. 3.

    Defenders of which include Lewis (1986), Lewis (1993), Hyde (1997), Fine (1975), and Beall and Colyvan (2001).

  4. 4.

    Defenders of such a view include Barnes and Williams (2011), Williams (2008) Smith (2005), and Akiba (2004).

  5. 5.

    Olson (1997b) describes some such views as being relativist and offers a critique of views of this kind.

  6. 6.

    See, for instance, Braddon-Mitchell and Miller (2004).

  7. 7.

    See, for instance, Braddon-Mitchell and West (2001).

  8. 8.

    For further discussion of these kinds of no-fault disputes, see Robinson (2004) and Miller (2013).

  9. 9.

    For discussion of the various kinds of conventionalism, see Miller (2009).

  10. 10.

    A paradigm example of this is Sider (2001b).

  11. 11.

    Where this is the case I will say that it is indeterminate whether P survives E at t. More generally, I will say that where ‘P’ is semantically imprecise such that there are candidates O1…O n that are equally eligible to be the referent of ‘P’, then the reference of ‘P’ is indeterminate. Moreover, if some, but not all, of the candidates have feature F, then I will say it is indeterminate whether P is F. It is determinate that P is F iff every candidate to be the referent of ‘P’ is F. One could embrace semantic indecision without also accepting these claims about indeterminacy and determinacy but nothing of import to the paper hangs on such a choice.

  12. 12.

    To say that at most one of the parties to the dispute is correct is not, of course, to say that that party is in any position to know that they are correct.

  13. 13.

    One might contend that they are really not involved in any dispute at all in this case, since they are not truly disagreeing with one another. In that case one might say that (2) is strictly speaking false, but we can explain why it seems to be true.

  14. 14.

    Some aspects of the problem of the many, for instance, lend themselves to type I disputes.

  15. 15.

    The following discussion is framed in terms of a four-dimensionalist, and largely perdurantist, view about persisting objects. I take it, however, that nothing in principle debars one from translating everything said here into terminology that is friendly to a three-dimensionalist perspective on persistence. (See, e.g. Miller 2005.)

  16. 16.

    For more discussion of the problem of the many, see Weatherson (2003) Unger (1980), McKinnon (2002), Lowe (1982), and Lewis (1993).

  17. 17.

    For this solution to the problem of the many, see Weatherson (2003), and for a contrary view, see McKinnon (2002).

  18. 18.

    See, for instance, Williamson (1994).

  19. 19.

    See Sider (2001a, b) for a defence of this view.

  20. 20.

    See, for instance, Olson (1997a) and Snowdon (1990). For a contrary view, see Noonan (1999).

  21. 21.

    Olson (2002) makes both objections.

  22. 22.

    This is Smith’s shorthand for the claim that follows.

  23. 23.

    See Sider (2001a, b) and Hawley (2001) for an introduction to stage theoretic semantics. See also Rychter (2012) and Viebahn (2013) for further details.

  24. 24.

    See, for instance, Broome (1994) and Parfit (1984).

  25. 25.

    See Broome for a good discussion of these issues.

  26. 26.

    This terminology is borrowed from David Braddon-Mitchell, in conversation.

  27. 27.

    See Velleman (1991) and Slote (1982) for a discussion of these issues.

References

  • Akiba, K. (2004). Vagueness in the world. Noûs, 38, 407–429.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barnes, E. J., & Williams, J. R. G. (2011). A theory of metaphysical indeterminacy. In K. Bennett & D. W. Zimmerman (Eds.), Oxford studies in metaphysics (Vol. 6). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beall, J. C., & Colyvan, M. (2001). Heaps of gluts and Hyde-ing the sorites. Mind, 110, 401–408.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Braddon-Mitchell, D., & Miller, K. (2004). How to be a conventional person. The Monist, 87(4), 457–474.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Braddon-Mitchell, D., & West, C. (2001). Temporal phase pluralism. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 62(1), 1–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Broome, J. (1994). Discounting the future. Philosophy and Public Affairs, 23(2), 128–156.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fine, K. (1975). Vagueness, truth and logic. Synthese, 30, 265–300.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hawley, K. (2001). How things persist. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hyde, D. (1997). From heaps and gaps to heaps of gluts. Mind, 106, 440–460.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1986). On the plurality of worlds. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1993). Many, but almost one. In J. Bacon, K. Campbell, & L. Reinhardt (Eds.), Ontology, causality and mind: Essays in honour of D. M. Armstrong. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lowe, E. J. (1982). The paradox of the 1,001 cats. Analysis, 42, 27–30.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McKinnon, N. (2002). Supervaluations and the problem of the many. The Philosophical Quarterly, 52, 320–339.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Miller, K. (2005). The metaphysical equivalence of three and four dimensionalism. Erkenntnis, 62(1), 91–117.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Miller, K. (2009). Deciphering personal-identity conventionalism. In E. Casetta, & A. Varzi (Eds.), Special issue Rivista di Estetica “Convenzioni”. 44:2 59–85.

    Google Scholar 

  • Miller, K. (2013). “Personal identity” minus the persons’. Philosophical Studies, 166(1), 91–109.

    Google Scholar 

  • Noonan, H. (1999). Identity, constitution and microphysical supervenience. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 99, 273–288.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Olson, E. (1997a). The human animal: Personal identity without psychology. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Olson, E. (1997b). Relativism and persistence. Philosophical Studies, 88, 141–162.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Olson, E. (2002). Thinking animals and the reference of ‘I’. Philosophical Topics, 30, 189–208.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Parfit, D. (1984). Reasons and persons. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Robinson, D. (2004). Failing to agree or failing to disagree? Personal identity quasi-relativism. The Monist, 87(4), 512–536.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rychter, P. (2012). Stage theory and proper names. Philosophical Studies, 161(3), 367–379.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sider, T. (2001a). Criteria of personal identity and the limits of conceptual analysis. Philosophical Perspectives, 15, 189–209. Metaphysics..

    Google Scholar 

  • Sider, T. (2001b). Four-dimensionalism: An ontology of persistence and time. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Slote, M. (1982). Goods and lives. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 63, 311–326.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, N. J. J. (2005). A plea for things that are not quite all there: Or, is there a problem about vague composition and vague existence? Journal of Philosophy, 102(8), 381–421.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, D. (2007). Vague singulars, semantic indecision and the metaphysics of persons. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 74(3), 569–585.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Snowdon, P. (1990). Persons, animals, and ourselves. In C. Gill (Ed.), The person and the human mind. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Unger, P. (1980). The problem of the many. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 5, 411–467.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Velleman, J. D. (1991). Well-being and time. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 72(1), 48–77.

    Google Scholar 

  • Viebahn, E. (2013). Counting stages. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 91(2), 311–324.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weatherson, B. (2003). Many many problems. Philosophical Quarterly, 53(213), 481–501.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williams, J. R. G. (2008). Multiple actualities and ontically vague identity. The Philosophical Quarterly, 58(230), 134–154.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, T. (1994). Vagueness. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Kristie Miller .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2014 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Miller, K. (2014). Vague Persons. In: Akiba, K., Abasnezhad, A. (eds) Vague Objects and Vague Identity. Logic, Epistemology, and the Unity of Science, vol 33. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-7978-5_5

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics