Skip to main content

Science, Religion, and Naturalism: Metaphysical and Methodological Incompatibilities

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
International Handbook of Research in History, Philosophy and Science Teaching

Abstract

The debate about the relationship between science and religion shows no sign of abatement. Are science and religion in conflict? Are they just different? Or are they even complementary ways of approaching the world? This chapter examines the major arguments for and against the conflict thesis, focusing on the role of naturalism in science. It argues that both science and religion are epistemic fields, trying to come up with true knowledge of the world. In this sense they do have partly overlapping interests, in particular concerning the place of humans in the world. It argues further that in science, naturalism is to be understood as a metaphysical presupposition, not a methodological one, and it examines the methodological consequences of this view with respect to empirical testability and scientific explanation. The naturalist metaphysics and methodology of science is contrasted with the supernaturalist ontology and methodology of religion, concluding that science and religion are both metaphysically and methodologically incompatible. If science and religion are incompatible, it follows that religious education is not in accord with science education either.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 749.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 949.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 949.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    This contribution uses material published earlier in the journal Science & Education, namely, from Mahner and Bunge (1996a, b) and Mahner (2012).

  2. 2.

    Of course, there are approaches to teach religion in a very general sense of “spirituality,” whatever that exactly means (see, e.g., Stolberg and Teece 2011). Even so the presupposition is that this spirituality comprises more than what can be obtained in a comprehensive scientific worldview.

  3. 3.

    See, e.g., Clements (1990), Dawkins (2006), Dennett (2007), Edis (2007, 2008, 2009), Kanitscheider (1996), Kitcher (2004), Kurtz (2003), Mahner and Bunge (1996a, b), Martin (1997), Provine (2008), Rachels (1991), Smart (1967), Stenger (2007, 2011), and Suchting (1994).

  4. 4.

    See, e.g., Alston (2004), Barbour (2000), Clayton and Simpson (2008), Drees (1996), Gould (1999), Harrison (2010), Haught (1995), Peacocke (1993), Polkinghorne (1987), Rolston (1987), Ruse (2001a, 2011), Stenmark (2010), and Wentzel van Huyssteen (1998).

  5. 5.

    For critiques of Laudan’s view, see Mahner (2013) and Pigliucci (2013). For a comparison of concepts of religion, see Guthrie (1995). As for the demarcation of science in general, see Mahner (2007) and Thagard (2011).

  6. 6.

    It may be argued that attempts to split the world into two or more “worlds” are incoherent because, by definition, the world is everything that exists (Worrall 2004). However, if our metaphysics requires that not any old collection of causally unconnected things is itself a material thing and hence a real entity, worlds are real things (or, more precisely, systems) only inasmuch as their parts are causally connected, however weakly. Two causally unconnected universes would then be two different things, and there would be no supersystem of which they would be physical parts.

  7. 7.

    For the metaphysical and epistemological problems of the idea of divine intervention, see Fales (2010).

  8. 8.

    For an analysis of the various meanings of “meaning” in this context, see Martin (2002). For a critique of related noncognitive concepts of religion, see Philipse (2012).

  9. 9.

    In science education, Sinatra and Nadelson (2011) follow this approach by postulating different epistemologies for science and religion, that is, “epistemologies that have different roles and explain different aspects of the human condition” (p. 175). Obviously, and sadly, this is an instance of epistemological relativism.

  10. 10.

    See McCauley (2011), Orr (1999), and Worrall (2004).

  11. 11.

    See, e.g., Alston (1967), Drees (1996, 2008), and Hardwick (2003).

  12. 12.

    To the consistent naturalist, the attempt to naturalize religion reduces to a game of words:

    The bogus procedure is this: When there is something that clearly does not exist, but one wishes that it did exist and wants to be able to say that it does exist, then choose something real that is similar in some respects and give it the name of the nonexistent entity. Voilà! You have now proved the existence of something that doesn’t exist. Suppose one wants to prove that God exists. Find something awe-inspiring, or powerful, or infinite, or fundamental …. and call it “God”. Now God exists, and the various practices with respect to that God are “religious”. Unfortunately, in reality, all you’ve done is play with words and, thereby, pull off a shabby, unconvincing trick. (Pasquarello 2002, p. 51)

    This applies not only to religious naturalism but also to the various hermeneutic approaches in modern theology, such as Paul Tillich’s definition of God as “ultimate concern” (for a criticism of hermeneutic theology, see Chap. 5 in Albert 1985).

  13. 13.

    Peacocke’s (1993) panentheism does not seem to be a consistent naturalism, as it makes God only partly natural, so I shall not discuss his view here.

  14. 14.

    See Boyer (2001), Dennett (2007), and Guthrie (1995).

  15. 15.

    Further criticism of religious functionalism in Guthrie (1995).

  16. 16.

    See, e.g., Ecklund (2010), Gross and Simmons (2009), Larson and Witham (1998), and Margenau and Varghese (1992).

  17. 17.

    More on this in Vollmer (1990), Psillos (1999, 2003), Worrall (2004), and Ladyman (2012).

  18. 18.

    This is echoed by Plantinga who has the gall to call naturalism a quasi-religion because it fulfills this world view aspect: “It offers a way of interpreting ourselves to ourselves, a way of understanding our origin and significance at the deep level of religion. It tells us where we come from, what our prospects are, what our place in the universe is, whether there is life after death, and the like. We could therefore say that it is a ‘quasi-religion’” (Dennett and Plantinga 2011, p. 16f., see also Plantinga 2011). Needless to say, it is disingenuous to call a world view that has overcome religion a quasi-religion. A similar theological ploy is to compare the philosophical underpinnings of science to religious faith.

  19. 19.

    Modifiyng earlier analyses by Bunge (1983), Bunge and Mahner (2004), Mahner (2007), and Mahner and Bunge (1996a).

  20. 20.

    “Ontology” is used synonymously with “metaphysics” in this paper.

  21. 21.

    A very general ontological realism is probably the least controversial metaphysical presupposition of science (Bunge 1983, 2006; Alters 1997; Gauch 2009; Ladyman 2012), although there is an ongoing realism/antirealism debate in philosophy. However, this debate concerns mostly epistemological problems regarding the justification of more detailed realistic claims such as the status of unobservable entities and the truth of scientific theories. Thus, someone who rejects more specific forms of realism, such as scientific realism, usually is still an ontological realist. I shall not defend ontological realism in more detail here (for such a defense, see, e.g., Vollmer 1990), because both ontological naturalists and supernaturalists share a basic realist outlook anyway.

  22. 22.

    I submit that the mainstream view of laws in the philosophy of science is inadequate. Science calls for a (neo-)essentialist view of laws, according to which “the laws of nature are immanent in the things that exist in nature, rather than imposed on them from without. Thus, […] things behave as they do, not because they are forced or constrained by God, or even by the laws of nature, but, rather, because of the intrinsic causal powers, capacities and propensities of their basic constituents and how they are arranged” (Ellis 2002, p. 1). Thus

    not even an omnipotent God could change the laws of nature without changing the things on which they are supposed to act. Therefore, the idea that the laws of physics are contingent, and superimposed on intrinsically passive things that have identities that are independent of the laws of their behavior, is one that lies very uneasily with modern science. (Ellis 2002, p. 5)

    The lawful behavior of things neither entails that we can always represent them as law statements nor that every scientific explanation is a subsumption under some law. For example, due to the enormous variation of organisms, many biologists believe that there are no laws (= law statements) in biology. But this does not entail that organisms do not behave lawfully: it is just that it often makes not much sense to try to find general, let alone universal, law statements because their reference class is rather small, holding only for some subspecies, variety, or even smaller units, for example, that is, only for those organisms sharing the same lawful properties (more on laws in biology in Mahner & Bunge 1997, Ellis 2002). Finally, even some cases of randomness are lawful because they are based on stochastic propensities such as in quantum physics. That is, there are probabilistic laws. For the neo-essentialist approach to laws adopted here, see Bunge (1977), Mahner and Bunge (1997), Bunge and Mahner (2004), and Ellis (2002).

  23. 23.

    Note that “nothing” really means “nothing,” not some form of radiation or some other massless form of matter. For example, what is called particle annihilation is just a transformation of a particle with mass into one or more massless particles, that is, into some form of radiation. However, it seems that the ex-nihilo-nihil-fit principle is being challenged by cosmologists, who keep entertaining the idea that the universe originated from nothing (see, e.g., Stenger 2011). In particular, according to multiverse cosmology, some primordial “nothing” keeps randomly popping out universes. But since this “nothing” has at least one property, namely, the propensity to pop out universes, it doesn’t seem to be a genuine nothing which should have no properties at all and hence be unable to change.

  24. 24.

    The no-psi principle was one of Broad’s (1949) so-called basic limiting principles of science. Being a strong believer in the paranormal, Broad maintained that this basic limiting principle had been refuted by parapsychology. However, Broad was fooled by the sloppy and partly even fraudulent parapsychological research of his time.

  25. 25.

    This was already acknowledged by J. S. B. Haldane (1934), who stated that his “practice as a scientist is atheistic,” that is, when he sets up an experiment, he assumes “that no god, angel, or devil is going to interfere with its course” (p. vi).

  26. 26.

    As Fales (2010) argues, even God may not know whether his thinking is manipulated by some evil demon. Does this require a second-order God of higher power who guarantees the truth of God’s knowledge? If so, we would end up with an infinite regress of truth guarantors.

  27. 27.

    In his debate with Plantinga, Dennett has recently called naturalism a null hypothesis (Dennett and Plantinga 2011, p. 49). Plantinga had argued that science is compatible with theism, because science doesn’t explicitly state that there is no God. This shows that Plantinga is not familiar with the concept of a null hypothesis. The same seems to apply to Flanagan (2008, p. 437), who argues against “imperialist naturalism” that we would simply not know everything that there is or is not. Yet this is exactly the reason why we have to start with naturalism as a metaphysical null hypothesis.

  28. 28.

    Despite many theological defenses, the notions of omnipotence and omniscience are incoherent (Martin 1990), so that we have reason to reject characterizations of the supernatural that employ them.

  29. 29.

    See Boyer and Walker (2000), Boyer (2001), and McCauley (2011).

  30. 30.

    See, e.g., Augustine (2001), Boudry et al. (2010, 2012), Fales (2010), Fishman (2009), Monton (2009), Stenger (2007), and Tooley (2011).

  31. 31.

    See, e.g., Forrest (2000), Pennock (2000, 2001), and Spiegelberg (1951).

  32. 32.

    More on the problems of supernaturalist explanations in Pennock (2000), who also explores the consequences of supernaturalism for the legal system, which would have to reconsider the-devil-made-me-do-it arguments including historically superseded forms of evidence based on “higher insights” and revelations.

  33. 33.

    Note that the famous “theory of everything“ in theoretical physics is a misnomer, because it would not explain everything. It would just offer a unified theory of the fundamental forces of physics. But this would not even begin to explain all the emergent properties of higher-level systems.

  34. 34.

    Those supernaturalists who dislike the god-of-the-gaps approach for theological reasons have retreated to a transnatural conception of the supernatural, which is immune to any empirical refutation.

  35. 35.

    See, e.g., Mackie (1982), Martin (1990), Forrest (2000), Fales (2010), and Philipse (2012).

  36. 36.

    Philipse(2012) has recently shown that the inference-to-the-best-explanation approach of natural theology faces insurmountable problems, including the failure of Bayesianism, which is also championed by radical empiricists (e.g., Fishman 2009), who believe that scientific methodology has no metaphysical presuppositions.

  37. 37.

    It may be argued that the variation in the meaning of “God” is not problematic, because scientific concepts often start out with fuzzy and variable meanings too. Think of terms like “gene” or “atom.” However, the variations in the precise meanings of these concepts are adjustments guided by empirical research and theory development. These concepts could be made precise enough to even get hold of their referents: today, genes can be sequenced, and atoms can be photographed. The various concepts of God, by contrast, are not constricted and guided by empirical research, so there is no improvement in the sense of an approximation to reality. The conceptual “development” in theology is purely apologetic in that the traditional overnatural concepts of God have been transformed into transnatural ones, so that they can no longer conflict with science, or anything factual for that matter.

  38. 38.

    For further varieties of naturalism, see, e.g., De Caro and Macarthur (2008) and McMullin (2011).

  39. 39.

    That this is one of the main reasons behind MN has also been shown by Boudry et al. (2012).

  40. 40.

    MN in the first sense can be held either dogmatically or provisionally. In the latter case, we may provocatively propose the name “methodological methodological naturalism,” so as to point out the double meaning of “methodological.” Note also that Boudry et al. (2010, 2012) distinguish intrinsic MN (in the sense of a defining feature of science) from provisional MN. The latter would be what I have just called methodological MN. Here I defend provisional ON as an intrinsic feature of science.

  41. 41.

    For a defense of religious experience as a valid method, see, e.g., Alston (2004). For critical analyses of the concept of religious experience, see Fales (2004, 2010), Kitcher (2004), Martin (1990), and Proudfoot (1985).

  42. 42.

    Curiously, Smith (2012, p. 13) appears to realize this difference but he downplays it by saying that “in practice, however, the distinction is less stark.” Yet practice is irrelevant: demarcation is first of all a matter of methodology. The cognitive and sociological similarities of learning on the basis of authority in both science and religion cannot attenuate the methodological conflict.

  43. 43.

    Even more curiously, Plantinga (2011) argues that evolutionary theory is incompatible with metaphysical naturalism (see also Dennett and Plantinga 2011). A premise of this counterintuitive claim is that naturalists adopt an instrumentalist view of evolution, according to which natural selection favors at most cognitive faculties adequate for survival, not cognitive faculties furnishing truth, whether absolute or approximate. A purely natural evolution, then, entails that our cognitive faculties are not reliable in the sense of truth tracking. Plantinga is aware of the objection that a frog which manages to catch a fly must have correctly represented some property of its environment. But he claims that, even in the case of humans, the naturalist can talk only of appropriate behavior, not of true beliefs. He supports his case by resorting to antimaterialist arguments from the philosophy of mind, maintaining that any materialist conception of the brain and its functions, whether reductive or emergent, allows at best for appropriate behaviors, never beliefs, let alone true beliefs. True beliefs, so Plantinga’s presupposition, can be had only in a nonmaterialist conception of the mind and a nonnaturalist conception of evolution. And the naturalist, who believes in the truth of naturalism, is inconsistent because naturalist evolution does not allow for the very existence of true beliefs. The real conflict, then, is between evolution and naturalism, not theism and evolution or science in general. Yet as evolutionary epistemology shows (Vollmer 2005), which is ignored by Plantinga, the evolution of cognition does lead to approximately true representations of the world (see also Dennett’s reply in Dennett and Plantinga 2011). Also, naturalism requires a reconceptualization of concepts such as “knowledge” and “belief,” which renders the antimaterialist argument moot (Bunge 1983).

  44. 44.

    See Davson-Galle (2004), Irzik and Nola (2009), Matthews (1992, 2009), and Smith and Siegel (2004).

  45. 45.

    See, e.g., Guthrie (1995), Boyer and Walker (2000), Boyer (2001), Dennett (2007), McCauley (2011), and Shermer (2011). For a different view, see Subbotsky (2000) and Woolley (2000), who consider children’s minds as neutral and thus to be filled with either rational or irrational cultural input.

  46. 46.

    See, e.g., Humphrey (1999), Goode (2000), Orenstein (2002), Hergovich et al. (2005), Lindeman and Aarnio (2007), and Eder et al. (2010). Note that the relation between religious belief and belief in the paranormal is not straightforward but depends on many variables such as level of education, gender, church attendance, and even the nature of the paranormal claims. For example, whereas astrology is mostly ruled out by Christians, creationism is not; and regular church attendance seems to prevent belief in the paranormal, presumably because the more frequent contact with official dogma protects from belief in competing paranormal or supernatural claims, respectively.

  47. 47.

    For example, if science is strongly associated with technology, as in the questionnaire of Cobern et al. (2012), it may not be surprising that even orthodox believers see not much conflict between science and religion, except for ideologically contentious issues such as creationism or embryonic stem cell research. After all, even fundamentalists are glad to reap the benefits of modern technology. More importantly, personal views about the relation of science and religion, or even career choice, do not answer the de jure conflict problem concerning a consistent world view.

  48. 48.

    See, e.g., Nowell-Smith (1967), Mackie (1982), Martin (1990, 2002), and Rachels (1995).

References

  • Albert, H. (1985). Treatise on Critical Reason. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Albert, H. (2000). Kritischer Rationalismus. Tübingen: Mohr-Siebeck.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alston, W.P. (1967). Naturalistic Reconstructions of Religion. In P. Edwards (Ed.) The Encyclopedia of Philosophy, vol. 7 (pp. 145–147). London: Collier-Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alston, W.P. (2004). Religious Experience Justifies Religious Belief. In M.L. Peterson & Van Arragon, R.J. (Eds.) Contemporary Debates in Philosophy of Religion (pp. 135–145). Malden, MA: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alters, B.J. (1997). Whose Nature of Science? Journal of Research in Science Teaching 34, 39–55.

    Google Scholar 

  • Augustine, K. (2001). A Defense of Naturalism. http://www.infidels.org/library/modern/keith_augustine/thesis.html. Accessed 18 January 2010.

  • Ayer, A. (1990/1936) Language, Truth, and Logic. London: Penguin Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barbour, I. (2000). When Science Meets Religion. Enemies, Strangers, or Partners? New York: HarperOne.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barrett, J.L. & Keil, F.C. (1996). Conceptualizing a Nonnatural Entity: Anthropomorphism in God Concepts. Cognitive Psychology 31, 219–247.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bartley, W.W. (1984). The Retreat to Commitment. LaSalle, IL: Open Court.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boudry, M., Blancke, S. & Braeckman, J. (2010). How Not to Attack Intelligent Design Creationism: Philosophical Misconceptions About Methodological Naturalism. Foundations of Science 15, 227–244.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boudry, M., Blancke, S. & Braeckman, J. (2012). Grist to the Mill of Anti-evolutionism: The Failed Strategy of Ruling the Supernatural Out of Science by Philosophical Fiat. Science & Education, DOI 10.1007/s11191-012-9446-8.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boyer, P. (2001). Religion Explained: The Evolutionary Origins of Religious Thought. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boyer, P. & Walker, S. (2000). Intuitive Ontology and Cultural Input in the Acquisition of Religious Concepts. In K. Rosengren, C.N. Johnson & P.L. Harris (Eds.) Imagining the Impossible. Magical, Scientific, and Religious Thinking in Children (pp. 130–156). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Broad, C.D. (1949). The Relevance of Psychical Research to Philosophy. Philosophy 24, 291–309.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. (1977). Treatise on Basic Philosophy, vol. 3: Ontology I: The Furniture of the World. Dordrecht: D. Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. (1983). Treatise on Basic Philosophy, vol. 6: Epistemology & Methodology II: Understanding the World. Dordrecht: D. Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. (2006). Chasing Reality. Strife over Realism. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. & Mahner, M. (2004). Über die Natur der Dinge. Materialismus und Wissenschaft. Stuttgart: Hirzel-Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Byl, J. (1985). Instrumentalism: A Third Option. Journal of the American Scientific Affiliation 37, 11–18. Online: http://www.asa3.org/ASA/PSCF/1985/JASA3-85Byl.html. Accessed August 24, 2012.

  • Clarke, S. (2009). Naturalism, Science and the Supernatural. Sophia 48, 127–142.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clayton, P. & Simpson, Z.R. (Eds.) (2008) The Oxford Handbook of Religion and Science. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clements, T.S. (1990). Science vs. Religion. Buffalo, NY: Prometheus Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cobern, W.W., Loving, C., Davis, E.B. & Terpstra, J. (2012). An Empirical Examination of the Warfare Metaphor with Respect to Pre-Service Elementary Teachers. Journal of Science Education and Technology, DOI 10.1007/s10956-012-9408-6

    Google Scholar 

  • Davson-Galle, P. (2004). Philosophy of Science, Critical Thinking, and Science Education. Science & Education 13, 503–517.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dawkins, R. (2006). The God Delusion. Boston: Houghton Mifflin.

    Google Scholar 

  • De Caro, M., & Macarthur, D. (2008) Introduction: The Nature of Naturalism. In M. De Caro & D. Macarthur (Eds.) Naturalism in Question (pp. 1–17). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Delamontagne, R.G. (2010). High Religiosity and Societal Dysfunction in the United States During the First Decade of the Twenty-First Century. Evolutionary Psychology 8, 617–657.

    Google Scholar 

  • Delamontagne, R.G. (2012). Overgeneralization: The Achilles Heel of Apocalyptic Atheism? Free Inquiry 32(6), 38–41.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. (2007). Breaking the Spell: Religion as a Natural Phenomenon. London: Penguin Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. & Plantinga, A. (2011). Science and Religion. Are They Compatible? New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Descartes, R. (1641). Meditationes. http://www.wright.edu/cola/descartes/mede.html. Accessed 17 January 2010.

  • Donahue, M.J. & Nielsen, M.E. (2005). Religion, Attitudes, and Social Behavior. In R.F. Paloutzian & C.P. Park (Eds.) Handbook of the Psychology of Religion and Spirituality (pp. 274–291). New York: Guilford Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Drees, W. (1996). Religion, Science, and Naturalism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Drees, W. (2008). Religious Naturalism and Science. In P. Clayton & Z.R. Simpson (Eds.) The Oxford Handbook of Religion and Science (pp. 108–123). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ecklund, E.H. (2010). Science vs. Religion: What Scientists Really Think. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eder, E., Turic, K., Milasowsky, N., Van Adzin, K. & Hergovich, A. (2010). The Relationships Between Paranormal Belief, Creationism, Intelligent Design and Evolution at Secondary Schools in Vienna (Austria). Science & Education, DOI 10.1007/s11191-010-9327-y

    Google Scholar 

  • Edis, T. (2007). An Illusion of Harmony. Science and Religion in Islam. Amherst, NY: Prometheus Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Edis, T. (2008). Science and Nonbelief. Amherst, NY: Prometheus Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Edis, T. (2009). Modern Science and Conservative Islam: An Uneasy Relationship. Science & Education 18, 885–903.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ellis, B. (2002). The Philosophy of Nature. A Guide to the New Essentialism. Chesham, UK: Acumen.

    Google Scholar 

  • Einstein, A. (1999). The World As I See It. Secaucus, NJ: Citadel Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Evans, J.H. (2011). Epistemological and Moral Conflict Between Religion and Science. Journal for the Scientific Study of Religion 50, 707–727.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fales, E. (2004). Do Mystics See God? In M.L. Peterson & R.J. Van Arragon (Eds.) Contemporary Debates in Philosophy of Religion (pp. 145–158). Malden, MA: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fales, E. (2010) Divine Intervention. Metaphysical and Epistemological Puzzles. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fishman, Y.I. (2009). Can Science Test Supernatural Worldviews? Science & Education 18, 813–837.

    Google Scholar 

  • Flanagan, O. (2008). Varieties of Naturalism. In P. Clayton & Z.R. Simpson (Eds.) The Oxford Handbook of Religion and Science (pp. 430–452). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Flew, A. (1972). The Presumption of Atheism. http://www.positiveatheism.org/writ/flew01.htm. Accessed 21 February 2011. [originally published in Canadian Journal of Philosophy 2, 29–46]

  • Forrest, B. (2000). Methodological Naturalism and Philosophical Naturalism: Clarifying the Connection. http://www.infidels.org/library/modern/barbara_forrest/naturalism.html, Accessed 27 February 2011 [originally published in Philo 3(2), 7–29].

  • Freddoso, A.J. (1991). God’s General Concurrence With Secondary Causes: Why Conservation Is Not Enough. In J. E. Tomberlin (Ed.) Philosophy of Religion, pp. 553–585. Atascadero, CA: Ridgeview Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gauch, H.G. (2009). Science, Worldviews, and Education. Science & Education 18, 667–695.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gervais, W.M. & Norenzayan, A. (2012). Analytic Thinking Promotes Religious Disbelief. Science 336, 493–496.

    Google Scholar 

  • Glennan, S. (2009). Whose science and whose religion? Reflections on the relations between scientific and religious worldviews. Science & Education, 18, 797–812.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goode, E. (2000). Paranormal Beliefs. A Sociological Introduction. Prospect Heights, IL: Waveland Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gould, S.J. (1999). Rocks of Ages: Science and Religion in the Fullness of Life. New York: Ballantine.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gross, N. & Simmons, S. (2009). The Religiosity of American College and University Professors. Sociology of Religion 70: 101–109.

    Google Scholar 

  • Guthrie, S.E. (1995). Faces in the Clouds. A New Theory of Religion. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haldane, J. B. S. (1934). Fact and Faith. London: Watts.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hardwick, C.D. (2003). Religious Naturalism Today. Zygon - Journal of Religion and Science 38, 111–116.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harrison, P. (Ed.) (2010). The Cambridge Companion to Science and Religion. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haught, J.F. (1995). Science and Religion: From Conflict to Conversation. Mahwah, NJ: Paulist Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hergovich, A., Schott, R. & Arendasy, M. (2005). Paranormal Belief and Religiosity. Journal of Parapsychology 69, 293–303

    Google Scholar 

  • Humphrey, N. (1999). Leaps of Faith. Science, Miracles, and the Search for Supernatural Consolation. New York: Copernicus.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hunsberger, B., Alisat, S., Pancer, S.M. & Pratt, M. (1996). Religious Fundamentalism and Religious Doubts: Content, Connections, and Complexity of Thinking. International Journal for the Psychology of Religion 6, 201–220.

    Google Scholar 

  • Irzik, G. & Nola, R. (2009). Worldviews and their Relation to Science. Science & Education 18, 729–745.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kanitscheider, B. (1996). Im Innern der Natur. Darmstadt: Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. (2004). The Many-Sided Conflict Between Science and Religion. In W.E. Mann (Ed.) The Blackwell Guide to the Philosophy of Religion (pp. 266–282). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Knodel, H. (Ed. 1985). Neues Biologiepraktikum. Linder Biologie (Lehrerband). Stuttgart: J.B. Metzler.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kurtz, P. (Ed.) (2003). Science and Religion: Are They Compatible? Amherst, NY: Prometheus Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ladyman, J. (2012). Science, Metaphysics, and Method. Philosophical Studies 160, 31–51.

    Google Scholar 

  • Larson, E.J. & Witham, L. (1998). Leading scientists still reject God. Nature 394, 313.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laudan, L. (1983). The Demise of the Demarcation Problem. In R. S. Cohen & L. Laudan (Eds.)., Physics, Philosophy, and Psychoanalysis, (pp. 111–127). Dordrecht: D. Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levine, M. (2011). Pantheism. http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/pantheism. Accessed July 29th, 2012.

  • Lindeman, M. & Aarnio, K. (2007). Superstitious, Magical, and Paranormal Beliefs. An Integrative Model. Journal of Research in Personality 41, 731–744.

    Google Scholar 

  • Loesberg, J. (2007). Kant, Hume, Darwin, and Design: Why Intelligent Design Wasn´t Science Before Darwin and Still Isn’t. Philosophical Forum 38, 95–123.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lowe, E.J. (2011). The Rationality of Metaphysics. Synthese 178, 99–109.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mackie, J.L. (1982). The Miracle of Theism. Arguments for and against the Existence of God. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mahner, M. (2007). Demarcating Science from Non-Science. In T.A.F. Kuipers (Ed.) Handbook of the Philosophy of Science, vol. 1: General Philosophy of Science – Focal Issues (pp. 515–575). Amsterdam: North Holland Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mahner, M. (2012). The Role of Metaphysical Naturalism in Science. Science & Education 21, 1437–1459.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mahner, M. (2013). Science and Pseudoscience: How to Demarcate after the (Alleged) Demise of the Demarcation Problem? In M. Pigliucci & M. Boudry (Eds.) Philosophy of Pseudoscience: Reconsidering the Demarcation Problem. Chicago: Chicago University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mahner, M. & Bunge, M. (1996a). Is Religious Education Compatible with Science Education? Science & Education 5, 101–123.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mahner, M. & Bunge, M. (1996b). The Incompatibility of Science and Religion Sustained: A Reply to Our Critics. Science & Education 5, 189–199.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mahner, M. & Bunge, M. (1997) Foundations of Biophilosophy. Berlin: Springer Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Margenau, H. & Varghese, R.A. (Eds.) (1992). Cosmos, Bios, Theos. LaSalle, IL: Open Court.

    Google Scholar 

  • Martin, M. (1990). Atheism - A Philosophical Justification. Philadelphia: Temple University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Martin, M. (1991). Science Education and Moral Education. In M. Matthews (Ed.) History, Philosophy, and Science Education. Selected Readings (pp. 102–113). New York: Teachers College Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Martin, M. (1997). Is Christian Education Compatible with Science Education? Science & Education 6, 239–249.

    Google Scholar 

  • Martin, M. (2002). Atheism, Morality, and Meaning. Amherst, NY: Prometheus Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Matthews, M.R. (1992). History, Philosophy, and Science Teaching: The Present Rapprochement. Science & Education 1, 11–47.

    Google Scholar 

  • Matthews, M.R (2009). Teaching the Philosophical and Worldview Components of Science. Science & Education 18, 697–728.

    Google Scholar 

  • McCauley, R.N. (2011). Why Religion Is Natural and Science Is Not. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McMullin, E. (2011). Varieties of Methodological Naturalism. In B.L. Gordon & W.A. Dembski (Eds.) The Nature of Nature, Examining the Role of Naturalism in Science (pp. 82–94). Wilmington, DE: ISI Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Monton, B. (2009). Seeking God in Science. An Atheist Defends Intelligent Design. Peterborough: Broadview Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nielsen, K. (1985). Philosophy & Atheism. Buffalo, NY: Prometheus Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nowell-Smith, P.H. (1967). Religion and Morality. In P. Edwards (Ed.), The Encyclopedia of Philosophy, vol. 7, (pp. 150–158). London: Collier-Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Hear, A. (1993). Science and Religion. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 44, 505–516.

    Google Scholar 

  • Orenstein, A. (2002). Religion and Paranormal Belief. Journal for the Scientific Study of Religion 41, 301–311.

    Google Scholar 

  • Orr, H.A. (1999). Gould on God. Can Religion and Science be Happily Reconciled? http://bostonreview.net/BR24.5/orr.html, Accessed July 23rd, 2012.

  • Papineau, D. (2007). Naturalism. http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/naturalism. Accessed 16 January 2010.

  • Pasquarello, T. (2002). God: 12000. The Faith of a Rebeliever. Free Inquiry 22(4), 50–53.

    Google Scholar 

  • Paul, G.S. (2005) Cross-National Correlations of Quantifiable Societal Health with Popular Religiosity and Secularism in the Prosperous Democracies. Journal of Religion & Society 7, 1–17. http://moses.creighton.edu/JRS/2005/2005-11.pdf

  • Peacocke, A. (1993). Theology for a Scientific Age. Minneapolis: Fortress Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pennock. R.T. (2000). Tower of Babel. The Evidence Against the New Creationism. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pennock, R.T. (2001). Naturalism, Evidence, and Creationism: The Case of Phillip Johnson. In R.T. Pennock (Ed. 2001) Intelligent Design Creationism and Its Critics (pp. 77–97). Cambridge, MA: MIT-Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pennock, R.T. (2009). Can’t Philosophers Tell the Difference Between Science and Religion? Demarcation Revisited. Synthese, doi:10.1007/s11229-009-9547-3

  • Philipse, H. (2012) God in the Age of Science? A Critique of Religious Reason. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pigliucci, M. (2013). The Demarcation Problem: A (belated) Response to Laudan. In M. Pigliucci & M. Boudry (Eds.) Philosophy of Pseudoscience: Reconsidering the Demarcation Problem. Chicago: Chicago University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Plantinga, A. (2001) Methodological Naturalism? In R.T. Pennock (Ed. 2001) Intelligent Design Creationism and Its Critics (pp. 339–361). Cambridge, MA: MIT-Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Plantinga, A. (2011). Where the Conflict Really Lies. Science, Religion, and Naturalism. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Platvoet, J.G. & Molendijk, A.L. (Eds.) (1999). The Pragmatics of Defining Religion. Leiden: Brill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Polkinghorne, J. (1987). One World: The Interaction of Science and Theology. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Proudfoot, W. (1985). Religious Experience. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Provine, W.B. (2008). Evolution, Religion, and Science. In P. Clayton & Z.R. Simpson (Eds.) The Oxford Handbook of Religion and Science (pp. 667–680). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Psillos, S. (1999). Scientific Realism: How Science Tracks Truth. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rachels, J. (1991). Created from Animals. The Moral Implications of Darwinism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rachels, J. (1995). The Elements of Moral Philosophy. New York: McGraw-Hill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ratzsch, D. (1996). Tightening Some Loose Screws: Prospects for a Christian Natural Science. In J.M. van der Meer (Ed.) Facets of Faith and Science, vol. II (pp. 175–190). Lanham, MD: University Press of America.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ratzsch, D. (2004). The Demise of Religion: Greatly Exaggerated Reports From the Science/Religion “Wars”. In M.L. Peterson & R.J. Van Arragon (Eds.) Contemporary Debates in Philosophy of Religion (pp. 72–87). Malden, MA: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rolston, H. (1987). Science and Religion. A Critical Survey. New York: Random House.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ruse, M. (2001a). Can a Darwinian Be a Christian? The Relationship Between Science and Religion. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ruse, M. (2001b). Methodological Naturalism under Attack. In R.T. Pennock (Ed.) Intelligent Design Creationism and Its Critics (pp. 363–385). Cambridge, MA: MIT-Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ruse, M. (2011). Science and Spirituality: Making Room for Faith in the Age of Science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, C.A. (2002). The Conflict of Science and Religion. In G.B. Ferngren (Ed.) Science and Religion: A Historical Introduction (pp. 3–12). Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sarkar, S. (2011). The Science Question in Intelligent Design. Synthese 178, 291–305.

    Google Scholar 

  • Saroglou, V. (2002). Religion and a Sense of Humor: An a priori Incompatibility? Theoretical Considerations from a Psychological Perspective. Humor 15, 191–214.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schopenhauer, A. (1951). Essays from the Parerga and Paralipomena. London: George Allen & Unwin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schopenhauer, A. (1974). Parerga and Paralipomena. Short Philosophical Essays, vol. 2 (transl. by E.F.J. Payne). Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schrader, D. E. (2000) Theology and Physical Science. A Story of Developmental Influence at the Boundaries. In K. Rosengren, C.N. Johnson, & P.L. Harris (Eds.) Imagining the Impossible. Magical, Scientific, and Religious Thinking in Children (pp. 372–404). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scott, E.C. (1998). Two Kinds of Materialism. Keeping them Separate Makes Faith and Science Compatible. Free Inquiry 18(2), 20.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sherkat. D.E. (2007). Religion and Higher Education: The Good, the Bad, and the Ugly. Social Science Research Council, http://religion.ssrc.org/reforum/Sherkat.pdf. Accessed 16 September 2012.

  • Shermer, M. (2011). The Believing Brain. New York: Times Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sinatra, G.M. & Nadelson, L. (2011). Science and Religion: Ontologically Different Epistemologies. In R.S. Taylor & M. Ferrari (Eds.) Epistemology and Science Education: Understanding the Evolution vs. Intelligent Design Controversy (pp. 173–193). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smart, J.J.C. (1967). Religion and Science. In P. Edwards (Ed.) The Encyclopedia of Philosophy, vol. 7, (pp. 158–163). London: Collier-Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, K.C. (2001). Appealing to Ignorance Behind the Cloak of Ambiguity. In R.T. Pennock (Ed. 2001) Intelligent Design Creationism and Its Critics (pp. 705–735). Cambridge, MA: MIT-Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, M.U. (2012). The Role of Authority in Science and Religion with Implications for Introductory Science Teaching and Learning. Science & Education, DOI 10.1007/s11191-012-9469-1

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, M.U. & Siegel, H. (2004). Knowing, Believing, and Understanding: What Goals for Science Education? Science & Education 13, 553–582.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spiegelberg, H. (1951). Supernaturalism or Naturalism: A Study in Meaning and Verifiability. Philosophy of Science 18, 339–368.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spilka, B., Hood, R.W. & Gorsuch, R.L. (1985). The Psychology of Religion. An Empirical Approach. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stenger, V. J. (2007). God: The failed hypothesis. How science shows that God does not exist. Amherst, NY: Prometheus Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stenger, V. J. (2011). The Fallacy of Fine-Tuning. Why the Universe Is Not Designed for Us. Amherst, NY: Prometheus Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stenmark, M. (2010). Ways of Relating Science and Religion. In P. Harrison (Ed.) The Cambridge Companion to Science and Religion (pp. 278–295). Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stolberg, T. and G. Teece (2011). Teaching Religion and Science. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Subbotsky, E. (2000) Phenomenalistic Perception and Rational Understanding in the Mind of an Individual. In K. Rosengren, C.N. Johnson, & P.L. Harris (Eds.) Imagining the Impossible. Magical, Scientific, and Religious Thinking in Children (pp. 35–74). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Suchting, W.A. (1994) Notes on the Cultural Significance of the Sciences. Science & Education 3, 1–56.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tan, J. (2006). Religion and Social Preferences. An Experimental Study. Economic Letters 90, 60–67.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thagard, P. (2011). Evolution, Creation, and the Philosophy of Science. In R.S. Taylor & M. Ferrari (Eds.) Epistemology and Science Education: Understanding the Evolution vs. Intelligent Design Controversy (pp. 20–37). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tooley, M. (2011). Naturalism, Science, and Religion. In B.L. Gordon & W.A. Dembski (Eds.) The Nature of Nature, Examining the Role of Naturalism in Science (pp. 880–900). Wilmington, DE: ISI Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vollmer, G. (1990). Against Instrumentalism. In P. Weingartner & G.J.W. Dorn (Eds. 1990) Studies on Mario Bunge’s Treatise (pp 245–259). Amsterdam: Rodopi.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vollmer, G. (2005). How Is It that We Can Know this World? New Arguments in Evolutionary Epistemology. In V. Hösle & C. Illies (Eds.) Darwinism & Philosophy (pp. 259–274). Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wentzel van Huyssteen, J. (1998). Duet or Duel? Theology and Science in a Postmodern World. Harrisburg, PA: Trinity Press International.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woolley, J.D. (2000). The Development of Beliefs About Direct Mental-Physical Causality in Imagination, Magic, and Religion. In K. Rosengren, C.N. Johnson, & P.L. Harris (Eds.) Imagining the Impossible. Magical, Scientific, and Religious Thinking in Children (pp. 99–129). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Worrall, J. (2004). Science Discredits Religion. In M.L. Peterson & R.J. Van Arragon (Eds.) Contemporary Debates in Philosophy of Religion (pp. 59–72). Malden, MA: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yinger, J.M. (1970). The Scientific Study of Religion. New York: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Martin Mahner .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2014 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Mahner, M. (2014). Science, Religion, and Naturalism: Metaphysical and Methodological Incompatibilities. In: Matthews, M. (eds) International Handbook of Research in History, Philosophy and Science Teaching. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-7654-8_56

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics