Skip to main content

Social Objects without Intentions

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Institutions, Emotions, and Group Agents

Part of the book series: Studies in the Philosophy of Sociality ((SIPS,volume 2))

Abstract

It is often seen as a truism that social objects and facts are the product of human intentions. I argue that the role of intentions in social ontology is commonly overestimated. I introduce a distinction that is implicit in much discussion of social ontology, but is often overlooked: between a social entity’s “grounds” and its “anchors.” For both, I argue that intentions, either individual or collective, are less essential than many theorists have assumed. Instead, I propose a more worldly—and less intellectualist—approach to social ontology.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    I will use “entity” to avoid the tedious repetition of “facts or objects,” where it is sufficiently unambiguous.

  2. 2.

    Searle gives slightly more detailed X-conditions in Searle (1995, pp. 45–56). But this is the explicit constitutive rule he gives, and it is fine for our purposes. In the next sections of this paper, I point out that none of Searle’s proposals give plausible X-conditions for dollars, but for the moment I am concerned with clarifying the form of constitutive rules. I use the term ‘ground’, following Fine (2001), Correia (2005), and others. Grounding is usually understood as holding between sets of facts. But we can also speak of objects, as well as facts, having grounds. A natural way to understand this is to take the grounds of an object, such as the Federal Reserve, to be the grounds of the fact The Federal Reserve exists.

  3. 3.

    This general approach is endorsed by others, including Tuomela (2002) and Hindriks (2008). I discuss Tuomela’s more nuanced views below.

  4. 4.

    Part of the problem may be that Thomasson wants a general formula to account for the generation of both abstract and concrete objects. Here I only consider concreta.

  5. 5.

    I have left out the “context” parameter as well. If it is appropriate for some sort of object, a contextual restriction can always be included among the generation conditions. But I see no reason to assume that, for a community, a constitutive rule must only apply to objects in the context of the community in question. I discuss this below (in connection with “cowrie money”). This also differs from Hindriks’ formalization (Hindriks 2008, p. 134n143).

  6. 6.

    Voluntary manslaughter is either killing with malice aforethought but with mitigating circumstances, or else killing with a different intention—to cause bodily harm but not to kill.

  7. 7.

    One consideration that puts pressure on this is the question of “freestanding Y-terms.” Cf. Smith (2003). Searle responds to this challenge in Searle (2010) by replacing pieces of paper and blips in the “X-term” position with human mental states. I discuss this further below.

  8. 8.

    One way of addressing the dependence of the Bureau of Engraving and Printing on intention may be, as Searle does, to introduce iterated constitutive rules. But the other cases I’ve mentioned, such as the intentional requirements for issuance, or for murder, are not treatable in this way.

  9. 9.

    In Searle (2010), he changes his terminology from “collective acceptance” to “collective recognition.” His notion of collective recognition seems to be close to Tuomela’s notion of collective acceptance, inasmuch as it does not entail belief. I discuss collective acceptance below.

  10. 10.

    They do not, of course, use the term ‘anchor’.

  11. 11.

    Plato ascribes this view to Hermogenes in Cratylus 384d, and Aristotle advances a similar view in De Interp. 16b19. Pufendorf (1673), Book I, ch. 10, distinguishes tacit from explicit agreement about conventions.

  12. 12.

    Searle also discusses this in Smith and Searle (2003, p. 208).

  13. 13.

    It is always an option for the convention-theorist to weaken the conditions on what counts as a convention. Millikan, for instance, proposes a rather weak set of conditions, where attitudes are not required at all for a convention to be in place. If hers is the correct analysis of convention, and if constitutive rules are conventions in this sense, then intentions are even more unnecessary for grounding constitutive rules than I am arguing here. I have criticized aspects of her theory in Epstein (2006).

  14. 14.

    It is not clear which of the various measures economists use for the quantity of money should be identified as the number of dollars outstanding—economists are likely to use “M1”, which consists of notes and coins, bank reserves, traveler’s checks, demand deposits, and other checkable deposits. Or they may use the “monetary base” or “total currency,” which consists only of notes, coins, and bank reserves. For none of these does electronic money have anything to do with it: these measures were in place long before electronic money, and it would be easy to have a dollar-based economy with only checks—no notes, coins, or electronics.

  15. 15.

    It is also troubling that Searle feels the need to extend this new account to institutional entities like corporations. It seems likely that if this is necessary, then other institutional entities, such as restaurants, universities, churches, nations, and so on, will be subject to the same considerations.

  16. 16.

    Moreover, plenty of commonplaces about the functions of money are false. For instance, it is widely held that for an instrument to be money, it must be legal tender for future payments. There are many forms of money, however, for which this is not true (e.g. money issued by individual banks in Brazil). And even for dollars, however, there is a spate of exceptions to bills (especially large ones) being legal tender, both in law and in practice.

  17. 17.

    For instance: Diamond (1984), He et al. (2008), Kahn et al. (2005), Kiyotaki and Moore (2002), Kiyotaki and Wright (1993), and Kocherlakota (1998).

  18. 18.

    If we take it as an ordinary counterfactual, of course, it is a statement about grounds as opposed to anchors, and is straightforwardly false. But if we are to be all charitable, it should be taken to be a counterfactual claim about anchoring.

References

  • Baker, L.R. 2004. The ontology of artifacts. Philosophical Explorations 7(2): 99–111.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bearman, P.S., J. Moody, and K. Stovel. 2004. Chains of affection: The structure of adolescent romantic and sexual networks. The American Journal of Sociology 110(1): 44–91.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Burge, T. 1975. On knowledge and convention. Philosophical Review 84(2): 249–255.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Correia, F. 2005. Existential dependence and cognate notions. Munich: Philosophia Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Diamond, P.A. 1984. Money in search equilibrium. Econometrica 52: 1–20.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Epstein, B. 2006. Review of language: A biological model by Ruth Millikan. Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews. http://ndpr.nd.edu/news/25029-language-a-biological-model/. Last accessed 10 Jan 2012.

  • Fine, K. 2001. The question of realism. Philosopher’s Imprint 1(1): 1–30.

    Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith, P. 1996. Complexity and the function of mind in nature. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • He, P., L. Huang, and R. Wright. 2008. Money, banking, and monetary policy. Journal of Monetary Economics 55: 1013–1024.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hindriks, F. 2008. The status account of corporate agents. In Concepts of sharedness: Essays on collective intentionality, ed. H.B. Schmid, K. Schulte-Ostermann, and N. Psarros, 119–144. Frankfurt: Ontos.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hume, D. 1978 [1740]. A treatise of human nature. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kahn, C., J. McAndrews, and W. Roberds. 2005. Money is privacy. International Economic Review 46: 377–404.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kiyotaki, N., and J. Moore. 2002. Evil is the root of all money. The American Economic Review 92(2): 62–66.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kiyotaki, N., and R. Wright. 1993. A search-theoretic approach to monetary economics. The American Economic Review 83(1): 63–77.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kocherlakota, N. 1998. Money is memory. Journal of Economic Theory 81: 232–251.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D.K. 1969. Convention: A philosophical study. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Millikan, R.G. 1984. Language, thought, and other biological categories: New foundations for realism. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Millikan, R.G. 1999. Historical kinds and the ‘special sciences’. Philosophical Studies 95: 45–65.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pufendorf, S. 1991 [1673]. On the duty of man and citizen according to natural law, translated by M. Silverthorne, edited by J. Tully. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J.R. 1995. The construction of social reality. New York: Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J.R. 2010. Making the social world: The structure of human civilization. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, B. 2003. John Searle: From speech acts to social reality. In John Searle, ed. B. Smith, 1–33. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, B., and J.R. Searle. 2003. The construction of social reality: An exchange. American Journal of Economics and Sociology 62(1): 285–309.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thomasson, A. 2003. Foundations for a social ontology. ProtoSociology 18–19: 269–290.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomasson, A. 2007. Artifacts and human concepts. In Creations of the mind: Theories of artifacts and their representation, ed. E. Margolis and S. Laurence, 52–73. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tuomela, R. 2000. Belief versus acceptance. Philosophical Explorations 2: 122–137.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tuomela, R. 2002. The philosophy of social practices: A collective acceptance view. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Tuomela, R. 2003. Collective acceptance, social institutions, and social reality. American Journal of Economics and Sociology 62: 123–165.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tuomela, R. 2007. The philosophy of sociality: The shared point of view. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Walton, K. 1990. Mimesis as make-believe: On the foundations of the representational arts. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ylikoski, P., and P. Mäkelä. 2002. We-attitudes and social institutions. In Social facts and collective intentionality, ed. G. Meggle, 459–474. Frankfurt: Dr. Hänsel-Hohenhausen AG.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Brian Epstein .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2014 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Epstein, B. (2014). Social Objects without Intentions. In: Konzelmann Ziv, A., Schmid, H. (eds) Institutions, Emotions, and Group Agents. Studies in the Philosophy of Sociality, vol 2. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-6934-2_4

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics