Skip to main content

Public Reason

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
NGOs as Legitimate Partners of Corporations

Part of the book series: Issues in Business Ethics ((IBET,volume 36))

  • 701 Accesses

Abstract

We need a conception of public reason that specifies what can be put forward by NGOs as political actors in the postnational constellation vis-à-vis corporations. A plea is made for a conception of public reason which promotes an unconstrained public dialogue. The background against which to assess public reason is the “fact of reasonable pluralism” (Rawls), i.e. the assumption that modern societies are characterized by the lack of a shared moral view on questions of the good life. It is argued that the liberal restrictions of the content of public reason have a number of implications which make it difficult for NGOs to adopt an emancipatory role as actors in the public sphere, and that liberalism in particular frees the interaction between NGOs and corporations from conforming to the requirements of public reason. Deliberative democracy agrees with feminist thinkers that public reason must be unrestricted since interests of actors must be discursively clarified even if they disagree. Any a priori restriction of what is acknowledged as part of public reason risks to oppress less powerful actors and to exclude them from public debate.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Even though it has been stated above that liberalism does not assign NGOs to the public sphere in a broad sense, in a liberal-constitutionalist analysis NGOs are part of the public sphere if they are embedded in an institutional context.

  2. 2.

    See Moon (2003) on the exemplary difference between Rawls’ and Habermas’ conceptions of public reason. See also Habermas (1996b: 313) on the importance of distinguishing the procedural and the substantive dimension and Gaus: “Political liberalism stresses justification of [substantive] basic political principles that can be the focus of an overlapping consensus among irreconcilable comprehensive doctrines, while deliberative democrats stress an open-ended discourse that validates political claims” (Gaus, 1997: 197).

  3. 3.

    Pluralistic theories of democracy “emphasize the role of democratic negotiation and bargaining among citizens or among groups of interest” (Besson and Martí, 2006: xviii). The most prominent representative of pluralistic accounts of democracy is Dahl (1956; 1978).

  4. 4.

    Rawls actually makes free institutions responsible for the diversity of reasonable comprehensive doctrines. He says that the diversity of reasonable comprehensive doctrines in a modern society is the result of free practical reason that operates in a society with free institutions (Rawls, 1993: 36f.).

  5. 5.

    On public reason and liberal overlapping consensus see also Benhabib (2002: 108ff.) and Horton (2003).

  6. 6.

    Similarly, Jean Cohen claims that “[a] relatively thin conception of national identity, together with political processes that accommodate diversity and acknowledge the equal claim of all to participate and to live openly according to their evaluations, could foster rather than undermine social inclusion, trust and social solidarity” (Cohen, 1999b: 228).

  7. 7.

    Joshua Cohen first contends that “the fact of reasonable pluralism appears to require a procedural conception because it deprives us of a background of shared moral or religious premises that could give determinate content to the idea of popular authorization or constrain the substance of genuinely collective choices” (Cohen, 1996: 96, emphasis added). But in a further step he criticizes this assumption and sketches a view that combines the assumption of reasonable pluralism with a more substantive conception of democracy. This includes among other principles, freedom of expression and religious freedom (Cohen, 1996: 103, 105). Yet, by defining these principles as substantive restrictions to public reason, commitments based on these principles become immune to public reason and to public policy (Dryzek, 2000: 11). Besides such attempts to justify liberal rights through deliberative principles, Dryzek names two other ways in which deliberative democracy converges with constitutional liberalism: the claim that liberal constitutions promote deliberation on the one hand, and the view that constitution-making is itself a deliberative process on the other hand (Dryzek, 2000: 10ff.).

  8. 8.

    As Benhabib states, with his “conversational restraint” on public dialogue Ackerman confines public dialogue to “productive ends” and thereby excludes certain conceptions of the good life from the agenda of public debate, which in effect become privatized (Benhabib, 1992: 97).

  9. 9.

    Habermas states that substantively delimiting “a sphere for a privately autonomous pursuit of individual interests and life plans (…) once and for all from the public sphere oriented to the ‘common weal’” is just as impossible as delimiting “the ‘intimate sphere’ (…) like a core inside the wider private sphere” (Habermas, 1996b: 314).

  10. 10.

    Rawls concedes that proving that the liberal conception of public justice is not too restrictive is an intractable task. But he claims that this is not a serious problem because most of the questions on which a well-ordered constitutional democratic society needs to find agreement can be settled by reference to political values alone (Rawls, 1997: 803). He cites as an example the debate whether school prayers should be admitted in public schools. He admits that it might be thought that a liberal position would deny the admissibility of prayers in public schools, but he then demonstrates that this question can be addressed with exclusively political arguments (Rawls, 1997: 794f.).

  11. 11.

    Rawls claims that forms of nonpublic reason “belong to the internal life of the many associations in civil society… Since we seek a shareable public basis of justification for all citizens in society, giving justifications to particular persons and groups here and there until all are covered fails to do this” (Rawls, 1997: 800). Benhabib criticizes Rawls on this point and states that “the constitutional-democratic state and the institutions of civil society are (…) not as sharply separable as some of Rawls’ formulations suggest” (Benhabib, 1996b: 76).

  12. 12.

    The impression that the locus of political interaction plays an important role for liberalism fits well with the observation, made in the section on the deliberative conception of the public sphere in the postnational constellation (see section “The Deliberative Conceptualization of the Public Sphere in the Postnational Constellation” (Chapter 6)), that the deliberative model does not define political interaction by the locus or by the actors involved but rather by the discursive character of the interaction.

  13. 13.

    Yet we must not equate nonpublic reasons with private reasons; nonpublic reasons of civil society are “social, and certainly not private” (Rawls, 1993: 220).

  14. 14.

    Whereas Rawls states that public reason holds for citizens when they “vote in elections when constitutional essentials and matters of basic justice are at stake” and “when they engage in political advocacy in the public forum” (Rawls, 1993: 215), Charney suggests an expansion of the applicability of public reason to “those venues where debate or advocacy occurs on matters of potential legislation concerning citizens in general and the arguments – the reasons invoked – are intended to apply to any and all citizens.” He thus widens the range of venues which are subject to public reason (Charney, 1998: 101).

  15. 15.

    As McCarthy points out, in “Political Liberalism” Rawls connects public uses of reason with governmental and quasi-governmental venues which include political campaigns and voting (Rawls, 1993: 215–6). He connects nonpublic uses with non-governmental venues such as churches, universities and voluntary associations in civil society (Rawls, 1993: 213, 220). He thus assigns nonpublic uses of reason explicitly to the unofficial networks in which people debate public matters. These are the networks which Habermas in turn considers to be the nervous system of the political public sphere (McCarthy, 1994: 50).

  16. 16.

    More about different styles of reasoning will be said in Chapter 14.

  17. 17.

    Yet Rawls expresses his belief that a well-ordered constitutional democratic society “can resolve the second kind of conflict, which deals with conflicts between citizens’ fundamental interests – political, economic, and social”. This belief rests upon the hope that if reasonable principles of justice are accepted and recognized as reasonable and if the political and social institutions satisfy them, then the “second kind of conflict need not arise, or arise so forcefully” (Rawls, 1997: 805). The problem is that the interaction between NGOs and corporations in the postnational constellation characteristically occurs in the institutional vacuum where there are no (or not yet) political and social institutions that could satisfy reasonable principles of justice.

  18. 18.

    The conventional occlusion of matters of the good life from public debate reflects the domination of “male voices” in drawing the boundary between public and private, because assigning these issues to the private sphere legitimizes women’s oppression and exploitation in the private realm (Benhabib, 1992: 110). As feminists have consistently argued, areas in life that are not being subjected to the principles of public reason are potential sites of injustice (Cooke, 2000: 960). The initial criticism of feminist thinkers was aimed not only at the liberal model but also at Habermas’ earlier restrictions of public reason. They reproached Habermas for relying on “overly rigid boundaries (…) between matters of justice and those of the good life, public interests versus private needs, privately held values and publicly shared norms” (Benhabib, 1992: 111). However, in the meantime Habermas has revised his conception of public reason and emphasises that every topic should be subject to deliberation (Habermas, 1996b: 312f.).

  19. 19.

    It is important to note though that this argument is open to criticism. After all, it took the Civil War to end slavery in the US, which suggests that a deliberative outcome with these “Southern gentlemen” was not likely.

References

  • Ackerman, B. “Why Dialogue?” The Journal of Philosophy 86 (1) (1989): 5–22.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Benhabib, S. Situating the Self: Gender, Community and Postmodernism in Contemporary Ethics. Cambridge (UK): Polity Press, 1992.

    Google Scholar 

  • Benhabib, S. “Toward a Deliberative Model of Legitimacy”. In Democracy and Difference, edited by S. Benhabib, 67–94. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1996b.

    Google Scholar 

  • Benhabib, S. The Claims of Culture: Equality and Diversity in the Global Era. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2002.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bohman, J. “Public Reason and Cultural Pluralism: Political Liberalism and the Problem of Moral Conflict”. Political Theory 23 (2) (1995): 253–79.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bohman, J. “Survey Article: The Coming of Age of Deliberative Democracy”. Journal of Political Philosophy 6 (4) (1998): 400–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bohman, J. “Citizenship and Norms of Publicity: Wide Public Reason in Cosmopolitan Societies”. Political Theory 27 (2) (1999): 176–202.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Charney, E. “Political Liberalism, Deliberative Democracy, and the Public Sphere”. The American Political Science Review 92 (1) (1998): 97–110.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, J. “Procedure and Substance in Deliberative Democracy”. In Democracy and Difference: Contesting the Boundaries of the Political, edited by S. Benhabib, 95–109. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1996.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, J.L. “Trust, Voluntary Association and Workable Democracy: The Contemporary American Discourse of Civil Society. In Democracy and Trust, edited by M.E. Warren, 208–48. Cambridge (UK) et al.: Cambridge University Press, 1999b.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Cooke, M. “Five Arguments for Deliberative Democracy”. Political Studies 48 (5) (2000): 947–69.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cortina, A. “The General Public as the Locus of Ethics in Modern Society”. In Facing Public Interest: The Ethical Challenge to Business Policy and Corporate Communications, edited by P. Ulrich and C. Sarasin, 43–58. Dordrecht et al.: Kluwer, 1995.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dahl, R.A. A Preface to Democratic Theory. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1956.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dahl, R.A. “Pluralism Revisited”. Comparative Politics 10 (2) (1978): 191–203.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dryzek, J.S. Deliberative Democracy and Beyond. Liberals, Critics, Contestations. New York: Oxford University Press, 2000.

    Google Scholar 

  • Forst, R. “The Rule of Reasons. Three Models of Deliberative Democracy”. Ratio Juris 14 (4) (2001): 345–78.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gaus, G.F. “Reason, Justification, and Consensus: Why Democracy Can’t Have It All”. In Deliberative Democracy: Essays on Reason and Politics, edited by J. Bohman and W. Rehg, 205–42. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1997.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gaus, G.F. Contemporary Theories of Liberalism: Public Reason as a Post-enlightenment Project. London: Sage, 2003.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gutmann, A., and D. Thompson. Why Deliberative Democracy? Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2004.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, J. Between Facts and Norms. Cambridge (UK): Polity Press, 1996b.

    Google Scholar 

  • Horton, J. “Rawls, Public Reason and the Limits of Liberal Justification”. Contemporary Political Theory 2 (1) (2003): 5–23.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Johnson, J. “Arguing for Deliberation: Some Skeptical Considerations”. In Deliberative Democracy, edited by J. Elster, 161–84. Cambridge (UK) et al.: Cambridge University Press, 1998.

    Google Scholar 

  • Martí, J.L. “The Epistemic Conception of Deliberative Democracy Defended. Reasons, Rightness and Equal Political Autonomy”. In Deliberative Democracy and Its Discontents, edited by S. Besson and J.L. Martí, 27–56. Aldershot: Ashgate, 2006.

    Google Scholar 

  • McCarthy, T. “Kantian Constructivism and Reconstructivism: Rawls and Habermas in Dialogue”. Ethics 105 (1) (1994): 44–63.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moon, J.D. “Rawls and Habermas on Public Reason: Human Rights and Global Justice”. Annual Review of Political Science 6 (2003): 257–74.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Palazzo, G. Die Mitte der Demokratie: über die Theorie deliberativer Demokratie von Jürgen Habermas. Baden-Baden: Nomos-Verlags-Gesellschaft, 2002.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. “The Idea of an Overlapping Consensus”. Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 7 (1) (1987): 1–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. Political Liberalism. New York/Chichester: Columbia University Press, 1993.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. “The Idea of Public Reason Revisited”. The University of Chicago Law Review 64 (3) (1997): 765–807.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ulrich, P. Integrative Economic Ethics. Foundations of a Civilized Market Economy. Cambridge (UK) et al.: Cambridge University Press, 2008.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Fraser, N. “Rethinking the Public Sphere: A Contribution to the Critique of Actually Existing Democracy”. Social Text (25/26) (1990): 56–80.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peters, B. “On Public Deliberation and Public Culture”. Reflections on the Public Sphere. InIIS-Arbeitspapier 97 (7). 1997. Accessed November 20, 2006. http://www.iniis.uni-bremen.de/.

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Dorothea Baur .

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2012 Springer Science+Business Media B.V.

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Baur, D. (2012). Public Reason. In: NGOs as Legitimate Partners of Corporations. Issues in Business Ethics, vol 36. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-2254-5_7

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics