Skip to main content

Practical Applications

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
The Price of Precaution and the Ethics of Risk

Part of the book series: The International Library of Ethics, Law and Technology ((ELTE,volume 6))

  • 875 Accesses

Abstract

We have now reached the point of inquiry where it is time to relate the various theoretical lines of reasoning presented in earlier chapters to actual practices of making risky decisions. In particular, we need to reconsider the issue about what PP should amount to in actual political decision making regarding environmental action and the use and introduction of technology. In doing this, I will proceed in a sort of ‘down-top’ order, starting with the issue of what the theory developed in the preceding chapter might say about a number of particular activities in isolation from the issue of policy. After this, the discussion will move on to the primary policy level and discuss what my theory implies regarding PP and its implementation within the political and regulative systems of a nation. As a final, I will then conclude by considering a number of implications on a more overarching global and long-term level of policy making.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    In Western consumerist societies of today, I would suggest, this growth is mainly indirectly effected by actual consumption (through the use of resources created by the consumerist system for other purposes, such as health care and public health, education, social security, public safety, et cetera). This since people in these societies as a rule live on such a high level of material wealth that the marginal value of each new brand or product may be assumed to be microscopically small. However, in other consumerist societies, such as developing countries, the continuous consumption of new goods may still by itself be an important contributor to many people’s quality of life.

  2. 2.

    For example, in the case of less energy consuming products, the end result may be even larger energy consumption than before due to an increased market for the product created by lower prices made possible by the energy saving production process.

  3. 3.

    This notion was introduced by German sociologist Ulrich Beck (1992).

  4. 4.

    Unless, of course, there are reasons for believing that the growth itself would change the political situation into one where more people are allowed to enjoy more well-being up to a point that may justify the extra risks.

  5. 5.

    This presupposes the absence of dynamic effects in the form of negative growth , for example, due to those better off in such a society becoming motivated to emigrate (personally and/or financially). Below, such prospects will be noted as one of many factors supporting the idea that precautionary policies should ideally be at work on a global rather than merely multi-lateral, national or regional level.

  6. 6.

    Assuming, of course, that they are to any benefit at all.

  7. 7.

    Of course, the very distribution may bring risks of its own, which then will have to be taken into account in decisions on its size and shape.

  8. 8.

    See, for example, Glover (1986) and Parfit (1984, Chapter 3).

  9. 9.

    This claim does not assume that any conceivable market gap will be automatically filled, only that gaps resulting from measures that impede a formerly active part of the market are very likely to be filled.

  10. 10.

    They would simply be slaughtered, held in slavery or at least robbed of all their possessions.

  11. 11.

    Hobbes (1651).

  12. 12.

    For facts on this issue, see IPCC (2007). The side-effects include, among other things, massive migration from large areas that become uninhabitable due to climate change , severe strain on traditional industries, and resulting risks of grave social unrest and war. It should be observed that it is highly probable that these effects will saliently affect also developed nations.

  13. 13.

    This claim is consistent with the existence of the so-called climate scepticism , expressed by a minor group of researchers (mostly not in the relevant scientific fields), who doubt the conclusions drawn, e.g. by IPCC . However, none of those doubts disprove the risks created by green-house gas emissions, global warming and climate change and – for the most part – concern minor details in the scientific discourse. Some climate sceptics also criticise the political initiatives taken to handle these risks, and thus seem to assume some (undeclared) theory on the ethics of risk and precautionary policy. My discussion in this subsection may be seen as a response to such debaters, with the difference that I present and defend a transparent and worked out theory on the ethics of risk and precaution on which the analysis of climate change policy is based.

  14. 14.

    United Nation’s Framework Convention on Climate Change (1997).

  15. 15.

    Rummukainen (2005) and IPCC (2007).

  16. 16.

    This argument must be kept separate from an argument based on desert considerations often wielded by representatives of developing countries. That argument claims that rich countries are overproducers of pollution , while developing countries are not, since it is mainly the past pollution of developed nations that has given rise to the climate change problem now being faced by all nations – simply put: ‘it is their fault not ours!’. This claim assumes desert to be a valid normative consideration, but such an assumption is not a part of my theory. Since desert is a classic suggestion in debates about justice , however, this is another instance of how my theory is able to produce results of relevance from the point of view of justice without making any particular assumption about what is a just distribution of risks.

  17. 17.

    In such a process, it may be claimed that the idea of directing policies towards the fostering of precautionary virtue s among the electorate of the nations involved has an important role to play.

  18. 18.

    This last effect might be thought to be countered by a system for price control working in favour of less affluent countries. However, it seems unlikely that this would be accepted by developed countries, since they could then just as well have accepted to be endowed with less pollution rights from the very beginning, and as a bonus escaped the transition costs of upholding the price control system. Alternatively, these same nations may accept such a system but engineer it to their own benefit, much as has been done in other areas of global trade (cf. Pogge 2008).

  19. 19.

    About a month after the failure of the COP-16 meeting in Cancún , Mexico , in 2010.

  20. 20.

    For a basic outline of the game theoretical features of Chicken , see Resnik (1987).

  21. 21.

    For a basic outline of the game theoretical features of The Prisoners’ Dilemma , see Resnik (1987).

  22. 22.

    The importance of this strategy for establishing mutually benefiting cooperative schemes in situations with radically opposed interests has been brilliantly described and analysed by Robert Axelrod (1984).

  23. 23.

    While making the last corrections to this book, the hazard at the Fukushima nuclear power plants, classified as serious as Chernobyl, was still under way.

  24. 24.

    The development of so-called Generation IV nuclear reactors still being mainly at the drawing board stage, it is also unclear whether these sort of possibilities will bring new risk factors in the actual running of plants.

  25. 25.

    I am here ignoring the doubts about the economic efficiency of nuclear power based on its potential insurance premium costs (which are astronomical and in most cases have been non-transparent due to them being carried primarily not by the industry, but by the nations housing the power plants). As will be seen, this benefit of the doubt will not prevent critical assessment of nuclear power from a precautionary point of view.

  26. 26.

    See, e.g., the overview in Stork (2009). It should be underlined, that temporary enthusiastic bursts of individual scientists or groups (for a recent example, see Palmer (2010)) regarding the prospect of fusion technology has been a repeated pattern in the marketing of this domain of science, just as in the case of gene therapy (to be discussed in the next subsection), for several decades. Awaiting solid evidence, all such forecasts are to be taken with a substantial grain of salt. Something similar holds regarding the recent hype of the possible practical applications of synthetic biology (the feasibility of which very much remains to be demonstrated) – see, e.g., Synthetic Biology & Bioenergy.

  27. 27.

    Unless we acknowledge a line of reasoning central to certain branches of classic revolutionary left-wing political theory; that boosting the flaws of an allegedly bad system may speed up the process of having it abolished. In the present case: making climate change problems much more serious much sooner than necessary may be a good thing in that such a development may motivate populations and political leaders to take effective measures against having the destructive process proceed even further. I trust that pointing out the flaws of this argument would be to overstate the obvious.

  28. 28.

    Gibson et al. (2010) and Pennisi (2010). Another recent development in this trend of ‘precision micro technology’ is so-called nanotechnology – a field where the aim is to precisely control, manipulate and design extremely small entities (such as molecules, atoms or even sub-atomic particles). Although already applied in certain processes for the construction of materials, nanotechnology is still even more in the experimental stage than biotechnology . However, in the future, this line of development will most likely offer an even wider span of possible applications than current biotechnology and with these applications will, of course, follow new risks of various kinds. I believe, however, that much of what is said in this section about biotechnology will be applicable to nanotechnological risks as well. See, for example, Hunt and Mehta (2006), and O’Mathúna (2009) for introductions to nanotechnology, its possible risks and benefits, and the ethical considerations actualised by it.

  29. 29.

    One example of such an idea that has already been put into some practice is the so-called Golden Rice . This genetically modified type of rice is an example of designer food that may have a more far-reaching potential than merely attract the interest of already affluent consumers. However, its potential for solving important problems such as malnutrition is debatable. See, e.g., Mayer (2005).

  30. 30.

    Synthetic Biology & Bioenergy.

  31. 31.

    Alternatively (as regards, e.g., Craig Venter ’s vision of a limitless source of non-polluting fuel through synthetic microorganisms, see Synthetic Biology & Bioenergy), the economic potential of such developments, and thus attractiveness for investors, would require far-reaching patenting and commercial secrecy surrounding the work – factors that in turn tend to slow down, or even impede, the realisation of the applications (since scientific development works best when data and methods can be shared freely) and increase risks (since societal oversight and control becomes more difficult).

  32. 32.

    In fact, if we consider the whole potential market for genetically modified products, the risks and uncertainties will plausibly be many times greater and this for two reasons. First, more risk-factors simply means that risks are accumulated into a higher total risk-level. Second, the more risk-factors that are present, that higher the risk for synergetic interactions between these that elevate the risks even more, or introduce additional risks of their own.

  33. 33.

    For a recent overview accessible to the lay person, see Häyri (2010, chapter 8). One strand of biotechnology that has been so applied for a rather long time, though, is techniques enabling the extraction of elementary biological (primarily genetic) information about humans. Applications of this kind, such as presymptomatic genetic testing and prenatal diagnosis , create quite a lot of ethical issues in their own right . See, for example Juth (2005), as well as Munthe (1996b, 1999c and 2007).

  34. 34.

    Tännsjö (1990, 1993).

  35. 35.

    Mayr (1942).

  36. 36.

    See the brief but excellent overview, description and further references given in Malmqvist (2008, especially pp. 26–27).

  37. 37.

    See, for example, Glover (1984), Harris (1998), Munthe (2000), and Tännsjö (1993).

  38. 38.

    See, e.g., Agar (2004) and Boström and Roache (2007). In addition, these debaters – as well as somewhat more cautious ones (e.g., Buchanan et al. 2002) – tend to project a surprisingly unreflected and/or simplified idea of what may actually constitute an enhancement . There are many examples given of both physical (such as strength and endurance) and cognitive/intellectual abilities (such as memory or computational skill) with no necessary or obvious connection to what makes life better for a person and the boosting of which may in fact make life worse. For elaboration of this type of point, see Shickle (2000).

  39. 39.

    Boström and Roache (2007).

  40. 40.

    Cf. the considerations discussed at the end of Chapter 5.

  41. 41.

    In Chapter 5, I suggested that, perhaps, relative and non-relative determinants of an acceptable or decent mix of risks and chances should be balanced against each other in some way. Obviously, such an idea would further complicate the application of the relative progressiveness idea to the cases at hand.

  42. 42.

    Sandin (2004, p. 24), and Ahteensuu (2008).

  43. 43.

    This conclusion seems to be in line with Ahteensuu ’s point (2008).

  44. 44.

    Sandin and Hansson (2002). Peterson (2006) seems to be assuming something similar when setting out his formal conditions for any satisfactory version of PP.

  45. 45.

    The choice of this term is inspired by the use of the same notion in debates on the methodology of medical ethics (see, e.g., Davis 1995). However, in that context, principlism is juxtaposed to casuistry and virtue based ethics (with regard to what basic normative outlook to adopt to medical ethical issues), rather than the use of practical policy procedures for solving some of the problems involved in the practical application of moral ideals.

  46. 46.

    Not to be conflated with Rawls ’ notion of procedural normative theories of justice (see Rawls 1971) or positions, e.g., in health care and research ethics inspired by this notion that have recently attracted criticism (see, e.g., Ashcroft 2008).

  47. 47.

    Seen from this perspective, one might say that the idea of principlism expresses the impossible dream of making political decisions without politics.

  48. 48.

    See, e.g., Tännsjö (1999) for an account of legal security along these lines.

  49. 49.

    This gives room for some legal insecurity until such coherent practices have been established. If the time-frame for this is not too long, it is hard to see this as a powerful objection, however. For example, compare with the case of agencies for the licensing of pharmaceuticals . When these were created around the world (in the 1960s) and given the power to decide which pharmaceuticals are legal and which are not, not much of coherent practice was in place, but with time such practice developed.

  50. 50.

    A reminder to the reader is in order: “proven” may be interpreted in a variety of ways. See further, Chapter 2.

  51. 51.

    I owe Ingmar Persson for bringing my attention to this.

  52. 52.

    The exception is one of the rigidity approaches – rigidity of aggregation – touched upon in Chapter 5.

  53. 53.

    See Andersson (2007) , for a recent exposition and critical discussion of this issue.

  54. 54.

    Cf. Rawls ’ argument that his theory of justice can only be applied to ‘well-ordered’ societies and therefore is inapplicable to global distributive issues (Rawls 1971).

  55. 55.

    There is an immense literature on this subject, which has been debated at least since the seventeenth century. In this context, I refer the reader to a few works which are useful both through their intellectual content and/or their provision of references for further study: Archibugi et al. (1998), Beitz (1979), Dower (2003), Held (1995), Heater (1996), Hinsley (1963), Pogge (2008), Rawls (1999), Singer (2002), and Tännsjö (2008).

  56. 56.

    An influential expression of this sort of criticism can be found in Rawls (1999).

  57. 57.

    Recently, this has led Ingmar Persson (2008) to argue that liberal democracy itself constitutes a major hurdle for effective global as well as national environmental policy.

  58. 58.

    The basic connection between democracy as a political ideal and the extent to which people have an opportunity to influence political decisions affecting themselves is explored and defended in Arrhenius (2005).

  59. 59.

    There are, however, considerable differences between democratic countries as to the nature of such a constitution (in some cases it is not even written down) and the possibilities of changing or amending it through democratic means. For details, see, e.g., the International Constitutional Law (ICL) web resource.

  60. 60.

    Mill (1982).

  61. 61.

    This perceived threat to liberal values is stressed by Sunstein (2005, Chapter 9).

References

  • Agar N. Liberal Eugenics: In Defence of Human Enhancement. London: Blackwell, 2004.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ahteensuu M. “In Dubio Pro Natura? A Philosophical Analysis of the Precautionary Principle in Environmental and Health Risk Governance.” PhD diss., Turku: Department of Philosophy, University of Turku, 2008.

    Google Scholar 

  • Andersson P. “Humanity and Nature: Towards a Consistent Holistic Environmental Ethics.” PhD diss., Göteborg: Acta Universitatis Gothoburgensis, 2007.

    Google Scholar 

  • Archibugi D., D. Held, and M. Köhler, eds. Re-imagining Political Community: Studies in Cosmopolitan Democracy. London: Polity Press, 1998.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arrhenius G. “The Boundary Problem in Democratic Theory.” In Democracy Unbound: Basic Explorations I, edited by F. Tersman. Stockholm: Department of Philosophy, Stockholm University, 2005.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ashcroft R.E. “Fair Process and the Redundancy of Bioethics: A Polemic.” Public Health Ethics 1 (1) (2008): 3–9.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Axelrod R. The Evolution of Cooperation. New York: Basic Books, 1984.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beck U. Risk Society: Towards a New Modernity. London: Sage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beitz C.R. Political Theory and International Relations. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1979.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boström N. and R. Roache. “Ethical Issues in Human Enhancement.” In New Waves in Applied Ethics, edited by J. Ryberg and T.S. Petersen. Hampshire: Palgrave Macmillan, 2007.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan A., D.W. Brock, N. Daniels, and D. Wikler. From Chance to Choice: Genetics and Justice. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2002.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davis R.B. “The Principlism Debate: A Critical Overview.” Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 20 (1) (1995): 85–105.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dower N. An Introduction to Global Citizenship. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, 2003.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gibson D.G., J.I. Glass, C. Lartigue, V.N. Noskov, R.-Y. Chuang, M.A. Algire, G.A. Benders, M.G. Montague, L. Ma, M.M. Moodie, C. Merryman, S. Vashee , R. Krishnakumar, N. Assad-Garcia, C. Andrews-Pfannkoch, E.A. Denisova, L. Young, Z.-Q. Qi, T.H. Segall-Shapiro, C.H. Calvey, P.P. Parmar, C.A. Hutchison III., H.O. Smith, and J.C. Venter. “Creation of a Bacterial Cell Controlled by a Chemically Synthesized Genome.” Science 329 (5987) (2010): 52–56.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Glover J. What Sort of People Should there Be? Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1984.

    Google Scholar 

  • Glover J. “It Makes No Difference Whether or Not I Do It.” In Applied Ethics, edited by P. Singer. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1986.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harris J. Clones, Genes, and Immortality: Ethics and the Genetic Revolution. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1998.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heater D. World Citizenship and Government. London: Macmillan Press, 1996.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Held D. Democracy and the Global Order. From the Modern State to Cosmopolitan Governance. Cambridge: Polity Press, 1995.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hinsley F.H. Power and the Pursuit of Peace. Theory and Practice in the History of Relations Between States. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1963.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hobbes T. Leviathan. 1651.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hunt G. and M.D. Mehta, eds. Nanotechnology: Risk, Ethics and Law. Sterling, VA: Earthscan, 2006.

    Google Scholar 

  • Häyri M. Rationality and the Genetic Challenge: Making People Better? Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2010.

    Google Scholar 

  • IPCC (Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change). IPCC Fourth Assessment Report: Climate Change 2007 (AR4), Geneva: IPCC, 2007. Available online: http://www.ipcc.ch/publications_and_data/publications_and_data_reports.htm

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Juth N. Genetic Information: Values and Rights. The Morality of Presymptomatic Genetic Testing. Göteborg: Acta Universitatis Gothoburgensis, 2005.

    Google Scholar 

  • Malmqvist E. “Good Parents, Better Babies: An Argument about Reproductive Technologies, Enhancement and Ethics.” PhD diss., Linköping: Linköping University, 2008.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mayer J.E. “The Golden Rice Controversy: Useless Science or Unfounded Criticism?” BioScience 55 (9) (2005): 726–7.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mayr E. Systematics and the Origin of Species. New York: Columbia University Press, 1942.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mill J.S. On Liberty. London: Penguin, 1982.

    Google Scholar 

  • Munthe C. “Preimplantation Genetic Diagnosis: Ethical Aspects.” In Encyclopedia of Life Sciences. Chichester: John Wiley & Sons, 2007.

    Google Scholar 

  • Munthe C. Pure Selection: The Ethics of Preimplantation Genetic Diagnosis and Choosing Children Without Abortion. Göteborg: Acta Universitatis Gothoburgensis, 1999c.

    Google Scholar 

  • Munthe C. “Selected Champions: Making Winners in the Age of Genetic Technology.” In Values in Sport, edited by C.M. Tamburrini and T. Tännsjö. London & New York: E&FN Spon, 2000.

    Google Scholar 

  • Munthe C. The Moral Roots of Prenatal Diagnosis: Ethical Aspects of the Early Introduction and Presentation of Prenatal Diagnosis in Sweden. Göteborg: Centre for Research Ethics, 1996b.

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Mathúna D. Nanoethics: Big Ethical Issues with Small Technology. London: Continuum International Publishing Group, 2009.

    Google Scholar 

  • Palmer J. “Laser Fusion Test Results Raise Energy Hopes.” BBC News, January 28, 2010. Available online: http://news.bbc.co.uk/2/hi/8485669.stm

  • Parfit D. Reasons and Persons, 2nd printing. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1984.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pennisi E. “Synthetic Genome Brings New Life to Bacterium.” Science 328 (5981) (2010): 958–9.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Persson I. “Kan den liberala demokratin stoppa sin miljöförstörelse” [Can Liberal Democracy Stop Its Own Environmental Destruction?]. Tidskrift för politisk filosofi 12 (3) (2008): 7–26.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peterson M. “The Precautionary Principle Is Incoherent.” Risk Analysis 26 (3) (2006): 595–601.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pogge T. World Poverty and Human Rights: Cosmopolitan Responsibilities and Reforms. Cambridge: Polity Press, 2008.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls J. A Theory of Justice. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1971.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls J. The Law of Peoples. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1999.

    Google Scholar 

  • Resnik M.D. Choices: An Introduction to Decision Theory. Minneapolis & London: University of Minnesota Press, 1987.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rummukainen M. “Reflections on the Uncertainty in Climate Scenarios.” Paper presented at the conference Uncertainty and Active Risk Management in Agriculture and Forestry, Swedish Agricultural University, Alnarp, May 25–26, 2005.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sandin P. Better Safe than Sorry: Applying Philosophical Methods to the Debate on Risk and the Precautionary Principle. Stockholm: Royal Institute of Technology, 2004.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sandin P. and S.-O. Hansson. “The Default Value Approach to the Precautionary Principle.” Human and Ecological Risk Assessment 8 (3) (2002): 463–71.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shickle D. “Are ‘Genetic Enhancements’ Really Enhancements?” Cambridge Quarterly of Health Care Ethics 9 (3) (2000): 342–52.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Singer P. One World. The Ethics of Globalization. New Haven: Yale University Press, 2002.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stork D. “22nd IAEA Fusion Energy Conference: summary of contributions on Fusion Technology and ITER Activities”. Nuclear Fusion 49: 104002104026, 2009.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sunstein C.R. Laws of Fear: Beyond the Precautionary Principle. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2005.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Tännsjö T. Global Democracy: The Case for a World Government. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, 2008.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tännsjö T. Coercive Care: The Ethics of Choice in Health and Medicine. London & New York: Routledge, 1999.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tännsjö T. “Should We Change the Human Genome?” Theoretical Medicine 14 (1993): 231–47.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tännsjö T. Conservatism for Our Time. London: Routledge, 1990.

    Google Scholar 

  • United Nation’s Framework Convention on Climate Change 1997, Report of the Conference of the Parties on its third Session, held at Kyoto from 1 to 11 December 1997. FCCC/CP/1997/7/Add.1, Bonn 1997: UNFCCC.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Christian Munthe .

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2011 Springer Science+Business Media B.V.

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Munthe, C. (2011). Practical Applications. In: The Price of Precaution and the Ethics of Risk. The International Library of Ethics, Law and Technology, vol 6. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-1330-7_6

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics