Skip to main content

Encountering Otherness

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Continental Philosophy and Philosophy of Religion

Part of the book series: Handbook of Contemporary Philosophy of Religion ((HCPR,volume 4))

Abstract

Differentiation or alterity – often expressed as “the other” – are terms that have been a preoccupation for much of French philosophy during the second half of the twentieth century. A number of scholars have attributed the theme of otherness – with both its positive and negative connotations – to the combined influence of G.W. Hegel, Edmund Husserl and Martin Heidegger (e.g., Schrift 2006; Baugh 2003). Different philosophers will, of course, make somewhat idiosyncratic appropriations and combinations in their particular interpretations of the mode of otherness, thus preventing any cohesive definition or consistent usage of its terminology – though indeed certain overlaps do occur. All of the philosophers who feature in this volume have engaged with variant understandings of the idea of otherness.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 139.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Levinas also refers in this same interview to his first essay on Husserl, published in 1929, when he was 22, in Revue Philosophique: “On the Ideas of Edmund Husserl.” This has recently been republished in Discovering Existence with Husserl (1998 [1967]). His doctoral thesis The Theory of Intuition in Husserl’s Phenomenology, was defended in 1930 at the University of Strasbourg. It was published in English in 1973.

  2. 2.

    Levinas further elaborates elsewhere: “There is a reflection upon oneself that wants to be radical. It does not only take into consideration that which is intended by consciousness. From this moment on, the object in phenomenology is reconstituted in its world and in all the forgotten intentions of the thinking that absorbed itself into it. It is a manner of thinking concretely. There is in this manner a rigor, but also an appeal to listen acutely for what is implicit” (2001: 93–94).

  3. 3.

    Levinas expands on his initial reaction to Heidegger and his work: “The entire book, Being and Time, was so extraordinary, because this being abandoned to Being, this care for being, leads indeed to the way in which everything possesses meaning. In 1927 it appeared to us as if he were beginning with a kind of Darwinian struggle for existence” (2001: 136).

  4. 4.

    Levinas later describes this work in relation to his disagreements with Heidegger. “This theme is already formulated in Existence and Existents. It is my first book, a taking up in another form of De l’évasion. This horror of anonymous being, obsession with this anonymity, this unceasingness; a bit like the nothing that annihilates (why does it not stay calm?). And already the radical difference is outlined, that which I will later call the fundamental dissymmetry between me and the other” (2001: 46).

  5. 5.

    Another criticism that Levinas makes of Heidegger concerns his preoccupation with one’s own being. “But what does fearing for the other mean in his theory of Befindlichkeit? To me, it is an essential moment.… Fearing for the other doesn’t enter into the Heideggerean analysis of Befindlichkeit because in that theory – a very admirable theory of double intentionality – all emotion, all fear, is finally emotion for oneself, fear for oneself” (2001: 177).

  6. 6.

    Levinas elaborates on the shortcomings of phenomenology in this connection. “Phenomenological description … whatever analysis of the relationship with the other, it may contribute, will not suffice. Qua phenomenology it remains within … the world of the solitary ego which has no relationship with the other qua other, for whom the other is another one, an alter ego known by sympathy, that is, by a return to oneself” (1978 [1947]: 85).

  7. 7.

    Even one of Levinas’s translators acknowledges this that Levinas himself is not entirely consistent in his use of a/autre and A/Autrui. In my usage of o/Other, I have tried to keep faithful to the context in which the term is used by either Levinas or those who quote from him.

  8. 8.

    In Kojève’s interpretation of the master-slave relationship in Hegel, human interaction was depicted as a battle unto death. However, on the wider social and political stage as distinct from the personal level, as Baugh describes it: “The ‘fight-to-the-death’ is merely a stage of inter-subjective relations; it is transcended in work and humanity’s technological mastery of nature… which ushers in the universal homogeneous stage, … a classless society comprising the whole of humanity.” [Kojève 1946: 354–356] (Baugh 2003: 99).

  9. 9.

    Baugh does admit, however: “It is certainly possible that Sartre read the important chapter on master and slave when it appeared in Mesures (January 1939)” (Baugh 2003: 98).

  10. 10.

    There is a less absolutist stance on Sartre’s work when he became more Marxist and also endeavored to develop an ethics that acknowledged the exploited status of many people.

  11. 11.

    In his posthumously published, Notebooks for an Ethics, Sartre admits that the quest for absolute freedom is an unrealistic one and that one needs to acknowledge the vulnerability of others. He states: “The other’s end can appear to me as an end only in and through the indication of my adopting that end. In choosing to help someone, I engage myself in action, but still recognize the end as not mine. To will this end in ‘good faith’ I must will the end to be realized by another.” (Sartre 1992: 277–280)

  12. 12.

    See Ricoeur the chapter on Ricoeur earlier in the volume for further details of his wartime detainment.

  13. 13.

    In Oneself as Another Ricoeur depicts a multifaceted reading of otherness, which he understands broadly as those dimensions of the world which can evade our conscious and/or voluntary control – and thus provide evidence not just of human fragility but also introduces questions regarding any façade of mastery. Under the heading of the involuntary, Ricoeur situates the body and conscience as well as relations with other human beings (1992: 317–356). I will restrict myself in this context to the relation to other persons.

  14. 14.

    It is in this sense with his emphasis on the uniqueness and irreducibility of the other person that I believe Ricoeur surpasses the basic maneuvers of the Hegelian dialectic in its later form. Indeed, Ricoeur often refers to Hegel’s early Jena writings where he did allow for human love between a man and woman as an illustration of the dialectic. It is to this dimension of Hegel that Ricoeur appeals rather than to Phenomemology of Spirit or his later political works (1992: 296).

  15. 15.

    Ricoeur voices his own appraisal of this postulate of “appresentation.” “Husserl gave the name ‘appresentation’ to this givenness in order to express, on the one hand, that unlike representations in signs or images, the givenness of the other is an authentic givenness and, on the other hand, that unlike the originary, immediate givenness of the flesh to itself, the givenness of the other never allows me to live the experience of others and, in this sense, can never be converted into originary presentation” (1992: 333). Ricoeur regards this negatively.

  16. 16.

    Ricoeur expands on his objections in Oneself as Another: “Like each of us, he [Husserl] understands, prior to any philosophy, the word ‘other’ as meaning other than me. Having said this, the fifth meditation [Cartesian meditations] stems from the bold stroke of the preceding meditation, a stroke by which the mediating ego reduces this common knowledge to the status of a prejudice, and so holds it to be unfounded. The mediating ego will therefore begin by suspending, hence by rendering entirely problematic, all that ordinary experience owes to others in order to discern that which, in experience reduced to the sphere of ownness, makes the positioning of others just as apodictic as the positioning of itself. Thus movement of thought is entirely comparable to Descartes’s hyperbolic doubt” (1992: 331).

  17. 17.

    Derrida describes the location of this otherness: “[T]his otherness is not necessarily something which comes to Greek philosophy from ‘outside,’ that is, from the non-Hellenic work. From the beginnings of Greek philosophy, the self-identity of the Logos is already fissured and divided. I think one can discern signs of such fissures of ‘différance’ in every great philosopher: the ‘Good beyond Being’ (epikeina tes ousias) of Plato’s Republic, for example, or the confrontation with the ‘Stranger’ in The Sophist are already traces of an alterity which refuses to be totally domesticated” (Derrida in Kearney 1984: 117).

  18. 18.

    There are echoes of Levinas in this statement. While initially Derrida seemed to defend Husserl against Levinas’s criticisms of him, by the mid-sixties he had recognized the strength of Levinas’s position on the subject of the other, though he maintained certain reservations and did not accept it in its entirety. As Françoise Dastur states: “In his (quite critical) essay on Levinas, ‘Violence and Métaphysique,’ first published in 1964.… Derrida apparently wanted still to defend Husserl against Levinas.… But in 1967 in Speech and Phenomena, he situates himself no longer inside phenomenology and philosophy, but at the ‘margins’ of them, in proximity both to the Levinasian ‘heterology,’ and to the Heideggerian ‘de-struction’ of onto-theology” (Dastur 2006: 52).

  19. 19.

    Derrida then continues: “But the problem is that such a non-site cannot be defined or situated by means of philosophical language” (1984: 108). A certain distance from philosophy is needed then, so as “to interrogate it” (109).

  20. 20.

    Foucault further notes that: “Christianity, in introducing salvation as salvation beyond this life, will somehow unbalance or at least upset the whole theme of care for self” (1991: 9). It is from this point onwards that care of the self began to be regarded as selfish.

  21. 21.

    Pierre Hadot in Philosophy as a Way of Life (1995) examines the various philosophically inspired forms of self discipline that Greek and Roman thinkers adopted in a pre-Christian era. He did not necessarily agree with Foucault’s adaptation of his ideas, especially those of a contestatory nature.

  22. 22.

    Marion’s theology has been basically described as neo-Platonic in that it basically posits a God that is unknowable. In his work God Without Being ([1982] 1991), Marion posits that it is love alone that will foster a relationship and insight into this dimension that far surpass the claims of reason. It would also seem that there is a Kierkegaardian influence at work here as well.

  23. 23.

    De Beauvoir’s own understanding of otherness in relation to Sartre’s thought including the modes of transcendence do present certain problems of interpretation. See de Beauvoir (1977: 16).

  24. 24.

    Kristeva clarifies this remark also with reference to her reception in the United States. “I believe that much of what has been written in the United States about my conception has been inaccurate. People have either defined and glorified the “semiotic” as if it were a female essence or else claimed that I do not grant enough autonomy to this ‘essence’” (269). For more details on the “semiotic,” see the chapter on Kristeva.

  25. 25.

    Kristeva, interestingly, qualifies this remark with the observation: “But I know that certain American feminists do not think well of such an idea, because they want a positivist notion of woman. But one can be positive starting with this permanent marginality, which is the motor of change” (45).

Bibliography

  • Baugh, Bruce. 2003. French Hegel: From surrealism to postmodernism. New York, NY: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beauvoir, Simone de. 1962 [1960]. The prime of life (trans: Green, Peter). New York, NY: World Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beauvoir, Simone de. 1989 [1949]. The second sex (trans: Parshley, H.). New York, NY: Alfred A. Knopf.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boothroyd, David. 1996. Foucault’s alimentary philosophy: Care of the self and responsibility for the other. Man and World 29: 361–386.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Butler, Judith P. 1987. Subjects of desire: Hegelian reflections in twentieth-century France. New York, NY: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Caputo, John D., and Michael J. Scanlon. 1999. Introduction. In God, the gift, and postmodernism, ed. John D. Caputo and Michael J. Scanlon, 1–53. Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Green, Karen. 2002. The other as another other. Hypatia 17/4: 1–15.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cordner, Christopher. 2008. Foucault, ethical self-concern and the other. Philosophia 36: 593–609.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cusset, François. 2008 [2003]. French theory. How Foucault, Derrida, Deleuze & Co. transformed the intellectual life of the United States. Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dastur, Françoise, 2006. Derrida and the question of presence. Research in Phenomenology 36: 45–62.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Derrida, Jacques. 1981 [1972]. Positions (trans: Bass, Alan). Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Deleuze, Gilles. 1983 [1962]. Nietzsche and philosophy (trans: Tomlinson, Hugh). Minneapolis, MN. University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Deleuze, Gilles. 1994a [1968]. Difference and repetition (trans: Patton, Paul). New York, NY: Columbia Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Deleuze, Gilles, and Felix Guattari. 1994b [1991]. What is philosophy? (trans: Tomlinson, H., and Burchell, G.). New York, NY: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Descombes, Vincent. 1980. Modern French philosophy (trans: Scott-Fox, L., and Harding, J.M.). Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dreyfus, Hubert L., and Paul Rabinow. 1982. Michel Foucault: Beyond structuralism and hermeneutics. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fell, Joseph P. 1979. Heidegger and Sartre: An essay on being and place. New York, NY: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foucault, Michel. 1970. The order of things: An archaeology of the human sciences. London: Tavistock.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foucault, Michel. 1973. Madness and civilization (trans: Howard, R.). London: Tavistock.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foucault, Michel. 1988. Technologies of the self. In Technologies of the self: A seminar with Michel Foucault, ed. L.H. Martin et al., 16–49. Amherst, MA: University of Massachusetts Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foucault, Michel. 1991. The ethic of care for the self as a practice of freedom (trans: Gauthier, J.D.). In The final Foucault, ed. J. Bernauer and D. Rasmussen, 1–20. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foucault, Michel. 1999. About the beginning of the hermeneutics of the self. (trans: Keenan, T., and Blasius, M.). In Religion and culture, ed. J. Carrette, 158–181. New York, NY: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hadot, Pierre. 1995. Philosophy as a way of life, ed. Arnold I. Davidson. Oxford, MA: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, Martin. 1962 [1927]. Being and time (trans: Macquarie, J.). New York, NY: Harper.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, Martin. Letter on humanism, (1977 [1947]). In Basic writings, ed. David Farell Krell. (trans: Capuzzi, Frank, and Grey, J. Glenn), 190–242. New York, NY: Harper and Row.

    Google Scholar 

  • Horner, Robin. 2005. Jean-Luc Marion: A theo-logical introduction. London: Ashgate.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, Edmund. 1960 [1931]. Cartesian meditations (trans: Cairns, D.). The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.

    Google Scholar 

  • Irigaray, Luce. 1993 [1987]. Sexes and genealogies (trans: Gill, G.C.). New York, NY: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Irigaray, Luce. 1996 [1992]. I love to you (trans: Martin, A.). New York, NY: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Joy, Morny. 2006. Divine Love: Luce Irigaray, women, gender and religion. Manchester: Manchester University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kearney, Richard. 1984. Jacques Derrida. In Dialogues with contemporary continental thinkers, The phenomenological heritage, 105–133. Manchester: Manchester University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kearney, Richard. 1986. Dialogue with Emmanuel Levinas. In Face to face with Levinas, ed. Richard A. Cohen, 13–33. Albany, NY: SUNY Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kearney, Richard. 2004. On life stories. In Paul Ricoeur: The owl of Minerva, 157–169. London: Ashgate.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kojève, Alexandre. 1947. Introduction à la lecture de Hegel. Paris: Gallimard.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kristeva, Julia. 1986. The Kristeva reader, ed. Toril Moi. New York, NY: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kristeva, Julia. 1987. In the beginning was love: Psychoanalysis and faith (trans: Goldhammer, Arthur). New York, NY: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kristeva, Julia. 1991. Strangers to ourselves (trans: Roudiez, Leon S.). New York, NY: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kristeva, Julia. 1996. Julia Kristeva: Interviews, ed. Ross Mitchell Guberman. New York, NY: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kristeva, Julia. 2002. Intimate revolt (trans: Herman, J.). New York, NY: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kristeva, Julia. 2009. This incredible need to believe (trans: Brahic, Beverley B.). New York, NY: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levinas, Emmanuel. 1969. Totality and Infinity: An essay on exteriority (trans: Lingis, A.). Pittsburgh, PA: Duquesne University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levinas, Emmanuel. 1973 [1930]. The theory of intuition in Husserl’s phenomenology (trans: Orianne, A.). Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levinas, Emmanuel. 1978 [1947]. Existence and existents. (trans: Lingis, A.). The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levinas, Emmanuel. 1981. Otherwise than being; or, beyond essence (trans: Lingis, A.). Boston, MA and Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levinas, Emmanuel. 1998 [1986]. Of god who comes to mind (trans: Bergo, Bettina) 3–14. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levinas, Emmanuel. 2001 [1998]. Is it righteous to be? Interviews with Emmanuel Levinas, ed. Jill Robbins. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levinas, Emmanuel. 2003 [1935–1936]. On evasion: De l’évasion (trans: Bergo, B.). Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marion, Jean-Luc. 1991 [1982]. God without being (trans: Carlson, Thomas A.). Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marion, Jean-Luc. 2002 [2001]. In excess: Studies of saturated phenomena. (trans: Horner, Robyn, and Berraud, Vincent). New York, NY: Fordham University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marion, Jean-Luc. 2007 [2003]. The erotic phenomenon (trans: Lewis, Stephen E.), Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Martin, Rux. 1988. Truth, power, self: An interview with Michel Foucault. In Technologies of the self, ed. Luther Martin et al., 9–15. Amherst, MA: University of Massachussetts Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Racevskis, Karlis. 1991. Michel Foucault, Rameau’s nephew, and the question of identity. In The final Foucault, ed. J. Bernauer and D. Rasmussen, 21–33. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ricoeur, Paul. 1967. Husserl: An analysis of his phenomenology (trans: Ballard, E.G., and Embree, L.E.). Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ricoeur, Paul. 1992 [1990]. Oneself as another (trans: Pellauer, D.). Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roudinesco, Elisabeth. 1990 [1986]. Jacques Lacan & Co (trans: Mehlmann, Jeffrey). Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roudinesco, Elisabeth. 2008 [2005]. Philosophy in turbulent times (trans: McCuaig, William). New York, NY: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sartre, Jean-Paul. 1992 [1943]. Being and nothingness (trans: Barnes, H.). New York, NY: Washington Square Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sartre, Jean-Paul. 1992 [1983]. Notebooks for an ethics (trans: Pellauer, David). Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schrift, Alan D. 2006. Twentieth-century French philosophy: Key themes and thinkers. Oxford, MA: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schroeder, William R. 1984. Sartre and his predecessors: The self – the other. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Morny Joy .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2011 Springer Science+Business Media B.V.

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Joy, M. (2011). Encountering Otherness. In: Joy, M. (eds) Continental Philosophy and Philosophy of Religion. Handbook of Contemporary Philosophy of Religion, vol 4. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-0059-8_10

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics