Skip to main content

Visual Common Sense

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Law, Culture and Visual Studies

Abstract

Pictures can tell us a lot, but not as much as we tend to think they do. A ­particular common sense attitude toward pictures, naïve realism, tends to make people overconfident in their interpretations of visual evidence and less receptive to alternative viewpoints, as well as to entrench the effects of other, first-order biases. Borrowing from anthropologist Clifford Geertz’s classic analysis of common sense, I begin by describing naïve realism about pictures as the exemplar of visual common sense, and I offer an example of it in judicial decision making. I then explain its psychological bases and its various implications for legal judgment. First, it is a special instance of naïve realism generally, a fundamental and familiar phenomenon in cognitive and social psychology. Second, the claim that naïve realism about ­pictures results from inattention to context and subjectivity, yielding a sense of assurance that our understandings are correct and that alternatives needn’t be taken as seriously, is congruent with the causes and effects of overconfidence generally. Third, the literature on processing fluency provides further support for the claim that seeing visual evidence would tend to generate overconfidence in the beliefs and judgments associated with that evidence, especially for naïve realists. I conclude by arguing that even in the age of Photoshop and YouTube, when people ought to be increasingly sophisticated about their visual culture, naïve realism about pictures remains a common and psychologically powerful default, and therefore of great significance for legal decision making.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 429.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 549.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 549.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Thus, pictures that don’t look to laypeople like ordinarily observable reality, such as many sorts of forensic scientific images, are unlikely candidates for naïve realism because they can’t be as readily incorporated into a useful internal representation of relevant reality. On the other hand, to the extent that these kinds of “expert images” (Dumit 2004) do resemble what laypeople think of as reality, they may appeal to naïve habits of viewing and comprehension, as the example of fMRIs indicates (Feigenson 2009).

  2. 2.

    This is an example of the aboutness principle (Higgins 1998), discussed below.

  3. 3.

    Our brains develop through infancy, childhood, and early adulthood to adapt to our interpersonal and cultural environments. Then, as adults with reduced neuroplasticity but greater conceptual and physical abilities, we try to make our worlds adapt to what our brains have come to expect. This is what psychiatrist and neuroscientist Bruce Wexler describes as brain-world consonance in the ontogenetic sense. Neuroscientist Leif Finkel (1992) has eloquently captured the discrepancy between the mind-world agreement that our consciousness seems spontaneously to yield and the underlying neurophysiology of perception: “The world, to a large extent, is a vision of our own creation. We inhabit a mixed realm of sensation and interpretation, and the boundary between them is never openly revealed to us. And amid this tenuous situation, our cortex makes up little stories about the world, and softly hums them to us to keep us from getting scared at night” (404).

  4. 4.

    Naïve realism about pictures is not about mistaking the picture for direct access to reality in the sense of being fooled into thinking that one is really present at the depicted events, as in the mythologized report of early cinema goers hurrying from the theater to avoid the approach of the train on the screen (Gunning 1995). Naïve realism is about believing that one’s understanding of reality is objectively correct, to the exclusion of all others, because one’s understanding simply copies that reality.

  5. 5.

    The phrase positive illusions, for instance, describes people’s unrealistic but sometimes beneficial optimism about potential health and other outcomes (Taylor and Brown 1988).

  6. 6.

    Kruglanski (2004) offers a helpful framework for understanding the relationship between overconfidence and closed mindedness or cognitive closure. He explains that people are generally subject to competing cognitive motivations, the need for closure and the need to avoid closure. Forming beliefs and reaching judgments always involve a trade-off between, on the one hand, keeping an open mind, seeking out additional information, and entertaining other points of view (i.e., avoiding closure) and, on the other, stopping the information search, ceasing to consider alternative viewpoints, and concluding the cognitive task (i.e., seeking closure). Both are essential to knowledge formation; each presents benefits and risks. Being overly confident leads to closed mindedness by reducing the perceived costs of premature closure, which include the possibility of being wrong (“fear of invalidity”) and the potential for conflict with relevant decision making norms (such as the standard jury instruction to keep an open mind).

  7. 7.

    The extensive research on confirmation bias, the “selective search, recollection, or assimilation of information that lends spurious support to a hypothesis under consideration” (Arkes 1991, 489; see Lord et al. 1979), also supports this reciprocal relationship. Arkes (1991) observes that “a primary reason for unwarranted confidence is that subjects can generate supporting reasons for their decisions much more readily than contradictory ones” (Id, 489, discussing Koriat et al. 1980). So the biased generation of arguments is reasoned to be a cause of overconfidence in a hypothesis. But since the hypothesis is posited to be “under consideration” as part of an ongoing process, it seems that (increasing) confidence in the hypothesis may cause as well as result from bias in the assimilation of further information.

  8. 8.

    “[C]onfident people engag[e] in less thought than people lacking in confidence. One reason for this is that when people feel confident in their current views, there is little need to seek additional information that might lead to change” (Briñol et al. 2010, 23).

  9. 9.

    This, of course, is the aboutness principle (Higgins 1998), discussed above.

  10. 10.

    The construct that comes closest is magic window realism, “the central, but not the sole, component of perceived reality” in the media effects literature (Potter 1988, 27). Magic window “is concerned with the degree to which a viewer believes television content is an unaltered, accurate representation of actual life” (Id, 26). People who score high on the magic window dimension think that television “provides them with a view of how things really are. They believe that television news shows are accurate, complete, unbiased, and objective pictures of ‘the way it is’” (Potter 1986, 162). To the extent that media effects researchers employ magic window and other dimensions of perceived reality primarily to measure people’s ability to distinguish factual from dramatic or fictional programming, however, their measure does not get at quite the same thing as naïve realism about pictures as presented in this chapter, which concerns the extent to which people think that various factual conclusions and evaluative judgments can be uncontroversially read off from an indisputably factual evidentiary picture.

  11. 11.

    Relatedly, psychologist Neal Roese and his colleagues (2006) found that showing mock jurors animations as opposed to diagrams of a vehicular accident case made them twice as susceptible to hindsight bias. The authors speculated: “Our research indicates that the clarity of computer animation can obscure the underlying uncertainty of accident reconstruction, creating a biased feeling of knowing” (308). That is, seeing the animation gave mock jurors a stronger impression that they knew how the accident occurred (as the IOED research would indicate), which made them more likely to believe that, from an ex ante perspective, it would occur (hindsight bias).

  12. 12.

    More recently, however, Nick Schweitzer and colleagues found that showing mock jurors neuroimages did not affect their judgments in criminal cases (Schweitzer et al. 2011).

  13. 13.

    The same inference may also have been prompted by the visual hindsight bias if jurors, knowing that the roof did soon collapse, reasoned that the commanders on the scene should have realized that it would, based on visual evidence that, viewed without the benefit of hindsight, was highly ambiguous.

  14. 14.

    Research shows, for instance, that people have assimilated standard film editing conventions to the point that they don’t notice cuts (the illusion of continuity; Kraft 1986), believing that highly edited Hollywood productions present the depicted reality more or less directly – as long as the structure of the film sufficiently conforms to narrative conventions to allow them to fill in the blanks with their story knowledge (Miller 1990).

  15. 15.

    Indeed, postmodernist anxiety about the possibility of ever having any kind of access to the “really real” may even impel people toward the sense of security offered by the objectivism of naïve realism (cf. Sherwin et al. 2006).

  16. 16.

    It might be thought that even if people start out as naïve realists about pictures, their naïveté and any ensuing overconfidence need not be a major concern for the law because that naïveté can be readily corrected. A detailed analysis of the prospects for debiasing jurors of naïve realism is beyond the scope of this chapter, so I can merely offer my belief that it appears possible in ­principle and, to some extent, in practice (see Feigenson and Spiesel 2009).

References

  • Alba, J., and J. Hutchinson. 2000. Knowledge calibration: What consumers know and what they think they know. Journal of Consumer Research 27: 123–156.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • All Facebook. 2011. Facebook will have 100 billion photos this summer [online]. http://www.allfacebook.com/infographic-facebook-will-have-100-billion-photos-this-summer-2011-02. Visited 6 Jan 2012.

  • Arkes, H. 1991. Costs and benefits of judgment errors: Implications for debiasing. Psychological Bulletin 110(3): 486–498.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baron, J. 1994. Thinking and deciding, 2nd ed. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baumeister, R. 1998. The self. In Handbook of social psychology, vol. 1, 4th ed, ed. D. Gilbert, S. Fiske, and G. Lindzey, 680–740. New York: McGraw-Hill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Begg, I., A. Anas, and S. Farinacci. 1992. Dissociation of processes in belief: Source recollection, statement familiarity, and the illusion of truth. Journal of Experimental Psychology. General 121(4): 446–458.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Benkler, Y. 2006. The wealth of networks. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bjork, R. 1999. Assessing our own competence: Heuristics and illusions. In Attention and performance XVII: Cognitive regulation of performance: Interaction of theory and application, ed. D. Gopher and A. Koriat, 435–459. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blanton, H., B. Pelham, T. DeHart, and M. Carvallo. 2001. Overconfidence as dissonance reduction. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology 37: 373–385.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boyes, M., and M. Chandler. 1992. Cognitive development, epistemic doubt, and identity formation in adolescence. Journal of Youth and Adolescence 21(3): 277–303.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bright, D., and J. Goodman-Delahunty. 2006. Gruesome evidence and emotion: Anger, blame, and jury decision-making. Law and Human Behavior 30(2): 183–202.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Briñol, P., R. Petty, and J. Barden. 2007. Happiness versus sadness as a determinant of thought confidence in persuasion: A self-validation analysis. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 93(5): 711–727.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Briñol, P., K. DeMarree, and R. Petty. 2010. Processes by which confidence (vs. doubt) influences the self. In Handbook of the uncertain Self, ed. R. Arkin, K. Oleson, and P. Carroll, 13–35. New York: Psychology Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cho, H., N. Schwarz, and H. Song. 2008. Images and preferences: A feelings-as-information analysis. In Visual marketing: From attention to action, ed. M. Wedel and R. Peters, 259–276. New York: Lawrence Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clore, G., and W. Parrott. 1994. Cognitive feelings and metacognitive judgments. European Journal of Social Psychology 24: 101–115.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Douglas, K., D. Lyon, and J. Ogloff. 1997. The impact of graphic photographic evidence on mock jurors’ decisions in a murder trial: Probative or prejudicial? Law and Human Behavior 21(5): 485–502.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dumit, J. 2004. Picturing personhood. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feigenson, N. 2009. Brain imaging and courtroom evidence: On the admissibility and persuasiveness of fMRI. In Law, mind and brain, ed. M. Freeman and O. Goodenough, 23–54. London: Ashgate.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feigenson, N. 2010. Audiovisual communication and therapeutic jurisprudence: Cognitive and social psychological dimensions. International Journal of Law and Psychiatry 33(5–6): 336–340.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Feigenson, N., and C. Spiesel. 2009. Law on display: The digital transformation of legal persuasion and judgment. New York: New York University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Festinger, L. 1957. A theory of cognitive dissonance. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Finkel, L. 1992. The construction of perception. In Incorporations, ed. J. Crary and S. Kwinter, 393–405. Cambridge, MA: Zone Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fischhoff, B. 1975. Hindsight is not equal to foresight: The effect of outcome knowledge on judgment under uncertainty. Journal of Experimental Psychology. Human Perception and Performance 1(3): 288–299.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Geertz, C. 1983. Local knowledge. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert, D. 1991. How mental systems believe. American Psychologist 46(2): 107–119.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert, D. 1998. Ordinary personology. In Handbook of social psychology, vol. 2, 4th ed, ed. D. Gilbert, S. Fiske, and G. Lindzey, 89–150. New York: McGraw Hill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gill, M., W. Swann, and D. Silvera. 1998. On the genesis of confidence. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 75(5): 1101–1114.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gilovich, T., and D. Griffin. 2010. Judgment and decision making. In Handbook of social psychology, vol. 1, 5th ed, ed. S. Fiske, D. Gilbert, and G. Lindzey, 542–588. Hoboken: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gunning, T. 1995. An aesthetic of astonishment: Early film and the (In)credulous spectator. In Viewing positions, ed. L. Williams, 114–133. New Brunswick: Rutgers University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harley, E. 2007. Hindsight bias in legal decision making. Social Cognition 25(1): 48–63.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harley, E., K. Carlsen, and G. Loftus. 2004. The saw-it-all-along effect: Demonstrations of visual hindsight bias. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition 30(5): 960–968.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Higgins, E.T. 1998. The aboutness principle: A pervasive influence on human inference. Social Cognition 16(1): 173–198.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hoffrage, U. 2004. Overconfidence. In Cognitive illusions, ed. R. Pohl, 235–254. Hove: Psychology Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Howard, J., and J. Sheth. 1969. The theory of buyer behavior. New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Janis, H. 1982. Groupthink. Boston: Wadsworth.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jost, J., J. Glazer, A. Kruglanski, and F. Sulloway. 2003. Political conservatism as motivated social cognition. Psychological Bulletin 129(3): 339–375.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kagan, J. 1972. Motives and development. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 22(1): 51–66.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, D., and S. Frederick. 2002. Representativeness revisited: Attribute substitution in intuitive judgment. In Heuristics and biases: The psychology of intuitive judgment, ed. T. Gilovich, D. Griffin, and D. Kahneman, 49–81. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Kassin, S., and C. Fong. 1999. ‘I’m innocent!’: Effects of training on truth and deception in the interrogation room. Law and Human Behavior 23(5): 499–516.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Keil, F., L. Rozenblit, and C. Mills. 2004. What lies beneath? Understanding the limits of understanding. In Thinking and seeing, ed. D. Levin, 227–249. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelley, C., and D. Lindsay. 1993. Remembering mistaken for knowing: Ease of retrieval as a basis for confidence in answers to general knowledge questions. Journal of Memory and Language 32: 1–24.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Koehler, D. 1994. Hypothesis generation and confidence in judgment. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition 20(2): 461–469.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Koriat, A. 1993. How do we know that we know? The accessibility model of the feeling of knowing. Psychological Review 100(4): 609–639.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Koriat, A., S. Lichtenstein, and B. Fischhoff. 1980. Reasons for confidence. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Learning and Memory 6(2): 107–118.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kraft, R. 1986. The role of cutting in the evaluation and retention of film. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition 12(1): 155–163.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kruglanski, A. 2004. The psychology of closed mindedness. New York: Psychology Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lazarus, R. 1991. Emotion and adaptation. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levin, I., C. Chapman, and R. Johnson. 1988. Confidence in judgments based on incomplete information: An investigation using both hypothetical and real gambles. Journal of Behavioral Decision Making 1: 29–41.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lord, C., L. Ross, and M. Lepper. 1979. Biased assimilation and attitude polarization: The effects of prior theories on subsequently considered evidence. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 37(11): 2098–2109.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McCabe, D., and A. Castel. 2008. Seeing is believing: The effect of brain images on judgments of scientific reasoning. Cognition 107: 343–352.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McGlone, M., and J. Tofighbakhsh. 2000. Birds of a feather flock conjointly (?): Rhyme as reason in aphorisms. Psychological Science 11(5): 424–428.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Miller, J. 1990. Moving pictures. In Images and understanding, ed. H. Barlow, C. Blakemore, and M. Weston-Smith, 180–192. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Connor, M. 1989. Models of human behaviour and confidence in judgement. International Journal of Forecasting 5: 159–169.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Oppenheimer, D. 2008. The secret life of fluency. Trends in Cognitive Science 12(6): 237–241.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Petty, R., and D. Wegener. 1999. The elaboration likelihood model: Current status and controversies. In Dual-process theories in social psychology, ed. S. Chaiken and Y. Trope, 41–72. New York: Guilford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Potter, W. 1986. Perceived reality and the cultivation hypothesis. Journal of Broadcasting and Electronic Media 30(2): 159–174.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Potter, W. 1988. Perceived reality in television effects research. Journal of Broadcasting and Electronic Media 32(1): 23–41.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reber, R., and N. Schwarz. 1999. Effects of perceptual fluency on judgments of truth. Consciousness and Cognition 8: 338–342.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Robinson, R., D. Keltner, A. Ward, and L. Ross. 1995. Actual versus assumed differences in construal: ‘Naive realism’ in intergroup perception and conflict. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 68: 404–417.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roese, N., F. Fessel, A. Summerville, J. Kruger, and M. Dilich. 2006. The propensity effect: When foresight trumps hindsight. Psychological Science 17: 305–310.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ross, L., D. Greene, and P. House. 1977. The ‘false consensus effect’: An egocentric bias in social perception and attribution processes. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology 13: 279–301.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ross, L., M. Lepper, and A. Ward. 2010. History of social psychology: Insights, challenges, and contributions to theory and application. In Handbook of social psychology, vol. 1, 5th ed, ed. D.Gilbert Fiske and G. Lindzey, 3–50. Hoboken: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rozenblit, L., and F. Keil. 2002. The misunderstood limits of folk science: An illusion of explanatory depth. Cognitive Science 26: 521–562.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Russakovskii, A. 2008. How to find out the number of videos on YouTube [online]. http://beerpla.net/2008/08/14/how-to-find-out-the-number-of-videos-on-youtube/. Visited 7 Jan 2012.

  • Sanbonmatsu, D., F. Kardes, and P. Herr. 1992. The role of prior knowledge and missing information in multiattribute evaluation. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes 51: 76–91.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scholl, B., D. Simons, and D. Levin. 2004. ‘Change blindness’ blindness: An implicit measure of a metacognitive error. In Thinking and seeing, ed. D. Levin. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schweitzer, N., M. Saks, E. Murphy, A. Roskies, W. Sinnott-Armstrong, and L. Gaudet. 2011. Neuroimages as evidence in a mens rea defense: No impact. Psychology, Public Policy, and Law 17: 357–393.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scott v. Harris, 550 U.S. 372. 2007.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sherwin, R., N. Feigenson, and C. Spiesel. 2006. Law in the digital age: How visual communication technologies are transforming the practice, theory, and teaching of law. Boston University Journal of Science and Technology Law 12: 227–270.

    Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, S., and J. Brown. 1988. Illusion and well-being: A social psychological perspective on mental health. Psychological Bulletin 103: 193–210.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Trout, J. 2002. Scientific explanation and the sense of understanding. Philosophy of Science 69: 212–233.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wexler, B. 2006. Brain and culture. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Winkielman, P., N. Schwarz, R. Reber, and T. Fazendeiro. 2003. Cognitive and affective consequences of visual fluency: When seeing is easy on the mind. In Persuasive imagery, ed. L. Scott and R. Batra, 75–89. Mahwah: Lawrence Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Neal Feigenson .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2014 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht.

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Feigenson, N. (2014). Visual Common Sense. In: Wagner, A., Sherwin, R. (eds) Law, Culture and Visual Studies. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-90-481-9322-6_5

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics