Skip to main content

The Evil Twin: The Basics of Complement-Toposes

  • Conference paper
  • First Online:
New Directions in Paraconsistent Logic

Part of the book series: Springer Proceedings in Mathematics & Statistics ((PROMS,volume 152))

Abstract

In this paper I describe how several notions and constructions in topos logic can be dualized, giving rise to complement-toposes with their paraconsistent internal logic, instead of the usual standard toposes with their intuitionistic logic.

For Christian Edward Mortensen, long-distance mentor, in his 70th birthday.

This paper is conceptually the first one of a tetralogy gathering up my logico-philosophical investigations on topos logic, deeply motivated by the philosophy behind Universal Logic: The other papers are [12, 15, 16], in that order. However, insofar as each paper is self-contained for it can be read independently, the reader might find several similarities between them in their introductions, speaking of the general motivation, or their presentations of the basics of topos logic, but each deals with special, specific problems. This paper has been written under the support from the CONACyT project CCB 2011 166502 “Aspectos filosóficos de la modalidad,” as well as from the PAPIIT project IA401015 “Tras las consecuencias. Una visión universalista de la lógica (I).” I thank Axel Barceló-Aspeitia, Jean-Yves Béziau, Carlos César Jiménez, Chris Mortensen, Zbigniew Oziewicz, Ivonne Pallares-Vega and now countless referees for their comments, suggestions or encouragement over the years I have spent working on this topic. Diagrams were drawn using Paul Taylor’s diagrams package v. 3.94.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    I use the word ‘slogan’ here pretty much in the sense of van Inwagen: “a vague phrase of ordinary English whose use is by no means dictated by the mathematically formulated speculations it is supposed to summarize” [51, p. 163], “but that looks as if it was,” I would add.

  2. 2.

    And maybe also of (S4), due mostly to the appearance of Hegelian terminology (“objective”), very frequent in Lawvere but not in other topos-theorists. Omitting that, one can add [2, 18] as supporters of this slogan.

  3. 3.

    A discussion of other topics in philosophy of logic, like the issue of meaning variance or the discussion of the connections between degenerate categories and trivialism, is certainly worth, but that is material for separate work.

  4. 4.

    This elucidation of toposes in logical terms follows closely [1].

  5. 5.

    As Awodey has noted, this is Russell’s notion of propositional function, for example in The Principles of Mathematics Sect. 22 or Principia Mathematica, pp. 14 and 161.

  6. 6.

    Note by the way that, unlike many authors, I prefer the equalizers presentation of logic, not the pullbacks one.

  7. 7.

    This is not as odd as it might seem at first sight; see [14].

  8. 8.

    Nice introductions to this category can be found in [30, 53].

  9. 9.

    I will omit operations on \(_{S}\Omega \) for simplicity, since it does not constitute a fundamental missing in the theme of the internal logic.

  10. 10.

    For brevity, I often will talk only of “connectives,” since their standard character can be obviated in this chapter, and their arity and order will be made explicit only when needed.

  11. 11.

    See for example [18, Sect. 6.6].

  12. 12.

    I have made a little abuse of notation, for I used ‘\(_{S}p\)’ in both \(\models _{_{S}\mathcal {E}}\) and \(\models _{I}\). In rigor, \(_{S}p\) is a morphism which corresponds to a formula \((_{S}p)^{*}\) in a possibly different language, but there is no harm if one identifies them. A proof can be found in [18, see Sect. 8.3 for the soundness part and Sect. 10.6 for the completeness part].

  13. 13.

    It must be said that some categories might not have enough structure to support some of the logical notions mentioned here. For example, an object in a category might have no minimal subobject distinct from the maximal one (so no proposition always false is distinct from always true) or might have no coproducts (and therefore, would lack disjunctions), etc.

  14. 14.

    The difference is clearly explained in [18, Sect. 7.3].

  15. 15.

    For more on this, see Sect. 18.3.

  16. 16.

    In Hegel’s Science of Logic, logic is divided into two parts, one of which is the logic of Being, the objective logic. Being is thought of here as an outer world beyond any particular subjective mind but still conceptually informed (and thus with a logic): It is “objectified spirit.” The other part is the logic of thinking, the subjective logic (Hegel calls it thus because thinking requires a thinking subject, more or less like a subjective right is the right of a subject). Hegel’s subjective logic is what today (and also in Hegel’s times) is commonly called ‘logic.’ An excellent treatment of the connections between Lawvere’s and Hegel’s views on logic can be found in [47]. Further clarification of the term ‘objective’ as applied to logic by Lawvere comes also from Hegel, but not from his work in logic but from his work on ethics, especially in Philosophy of Right (intended to be read with his Science of Logic as background), which is essentially a developed version of the section “Objective Spirit” in the Encyclopaedia of the Philosophical SciencesPhilosophy of Spirit. According to Hegel, the objective spirit consists of collective, social practices, whereas the subjective spirit is the individual. Part of Lawvere’s “historical and dialectical realism” is that mathematical entities exist objectively, like being in the Logic, but that existence is determined in mathematical experience as a whole, including its collective practice (like the objective spirit)—not in a Platonic realm independent of any subject, nor in merely subjective, individual, experience.

  17. 17.

    For simplicity I will omit quantifiers here and in the following section.

  18. 18.

    For more details on what follows, see [31].

  19. 19.

    These constructions are mathematical manifestations of the double-negation translation of classical zero-order logic into intuitionistic zero-order logic which works by inserting \(\lnot \lnot \) in relevant places. See the first section of [9] for more about these translations.

  20. 20.

    It is important to set their individual contributions. Of the ten diagrams in [39, Chap. 11], Mortensen drew the first one and the final five, while Lavers drew the remaining four. The diagram for the dual-conditional never was explicitly drawn, but it was discussed in [39, p. 109]. The full story, as told by Mortensen in personal communication, is as follows. Mortensen gave a talk at the Australian National University (Canberra) in late 1986, on paraconsistent topos logic, arguing the topological motivation for closed set logic. He defined a complement-topos, drew the first three diagrams from Inconsistent Mathematics, Chap. 11, that is including the complement versions of \(_{S}true\) and paraconsistent negation, and criticized Goodman’s views on the conditional. But it was not seen clearly at that stage how the logic would turn out. Peter Lavers was present (also Richard Routley, Robert K. Meyer, Michael A. McRobbie, Chris Brink and others). For a couple of days in Canberra, Mortensen and Lavers tried without success to thrash it out. Mortensen returned home to Adelaide and two weeks later Lavers’ letter arrived in Adelaide, in which he stressed that inverting the order is the key insight to understanding the problem, drew the diagrams for conjunction and disjunction, and pointed out that subtraction is the right topological dual for the conditional. Mortensen then responded with the four diagrams for the S5 conditional, and one for quantification (last five diagrams in Inconsistent Mathematics, Chap. 11). A few months later (1987) Mortensen wrote the first paper, with Lavers as co-author, and sent it to Saunders Mac Lane and William Lawvere (also Routley, Meyer, Priest). Mac Lane replied but Lawvere did not. A later version of that paper became the eleventh chapter of Inconsistent Mathematics. I thank Prof. Mortensen for providing me this information.

  21. 21.

    Mortensen and Lavers use the names complement-classifier and complement-topos, which are now the names set in the literature (cf. [13, 39, 40, 52]). Although the use of ‘dual topos’ would be appropriate here but misleading given the usual understanding of ‘dual category,’ I think there is no similar problem for the classifier of a complement-topos.

  22. 22.

    The same remark on note 7 in Sect. 18.2 applies here.

  23. 23.

    Again, for brevity I often will talk only of “connectives,” since their dual character can be obviated, and their arity and order will be made explicit only when needed.

  24. 24.

    This is a controversial point. Mortensen thinks that functionality is mathematically prior to, and a more important matter than some logical notions. Someone might object to this by saying that ordinary math books use conditional constantly, and for example use definitions stated as conditionals so that one constantly quantifies into conditional contexts, and every time one proves that some object does not have a defined property one is negating a conditional. Seemingly, this cannot all be pushed into the metalanguage without severe contortions.

  25. 25.

    I have attempted such a categorial description of this kind of duality in [12].

  26. 26.

    Again, I have made a little abuse of notation, for I used ‘\(_{D}p\)’ in both \(\models _{_{D}\mathcal {E}}\) and \(\models _{I}\). In rigor, \(_{D}p\) is a morphism which corresponds to a formula \((_{D}p)^{*}\) in a possibly different language.

  27. 27.

    By abuse of notation but to simplify reading I will not indicate that the order here is dual to that in standard toposes, unless there is risk of confusion.

  28. 28.

    Inconsistency-tolerant categorial structures are studied further in [39, Chap. 12, written by William James] and in [22].

  29. 29.

    Thus, as Vasyukov [52, p. 292] points out: “(...) in Set we always have paraconsistency because of the presence of both types of subobject classifiers (...)” just as we always have in it (at least) intuitionistic logic. The presence of paraconsistency within classical logic is not news. See for example [7], where some paraconsistent negations in S5 and classical first-order logic are defined.

  30. 30.

    It is easy to verify that after making all the necessary changes, i.e., changing \(_{S}true_{{S}^{\downarrow \downarrow }}\) for \(_{D}{} \textit{false}_{{S}^{\downarrow \downarrow }}\), etc., the names are ordered in the same way as they are in \(_{S}{{S}^{\downarrow \downarrow }}\).

  31. 31.

    A dualization of Kripke semantics for intuitionistic logic similar to that presented here was studied in [48]. Shramko maintains the Popperian reading to provide a “logic of refutation”; the crucial distinction lies in the condition for \(\sim \). Moreover, Shramko, like Goodman, also omits the discussion of subtraction. Goré [20, p. 252] even says that “[Goodman] annoyingly fails to give the crucial clause for satisfiability for his ‘pseudo-difference’ connective.”

  32. 32.

    An interior operator is an operator which is multiplicative, idempotent, and deflationary, i.e., \(x\ge jx\). A closure operator is additive (\(j(x\cup y) = jx\cup jy\)), idempotent and inflationary.

  33. 33.

    Such dualization is (the zero-order part of) the mapping \(\star \) discussed in [50, p. 444], which builds upon one described in [10].

  34. 34.

    As I have said before, Mac Lane knew about complement-toposes via Mortensen. His stance was that they were just the old toposes, but he gave no argument. I have been trying to figure out why did Mac Lane thought that and this is the best I can imagine. I think this would be part of what a mainstream topos- or category-theorist would say at first glance on complement-toposes (and in my experience, this is what they invariably say).

  35. 35.

    Although de Queiroz does not make explicit his use of the last of them. As a side remark, the converse of that theorem does not hold.

  36. 36.

    There is another problem in de Queiroz’s analysis of Brouwerian connectives in a topos. For example, the following diagram

    given as definition of Brouwerian subtraction in [11, p. 131] makes no sense. de Queiroz’s definition implies that the equalizer of \(p\vee q\) and the first projection p is \(e_{1} \! : \! \le \! \rightarrowtail \! \Omega \times \Omega \), but it is not correct for when one dualizes

    $$(p\supset q) = true \, \text {if and only if} \, (p\wedge q) = p$$

    one obtains

    $$(q-p) = false \, \text {if and only if}\, (p\curlyvee q) = p,$$

    and not

    $$(p-q) = true \, \text {if and only if} \, (p\vee q) = p.$$

    Briefly, de Queiroz’s definition gives us that Brouwerian subtraction is true in crucial cases where it should be false. Note that one cannot save de Queiroz’s proposal by reverting \(p-q\) as \(q-p\) in his suggested truth condition: In that case the truth conditions of \(\supset \) and \(-\) would coincide and no connective different from \(\supset \), let alone its dual, would have been defined.

  37. 37.

    This logic and the corresponding algebra were defined in [42] and extensively investigated in [43, 46] and now in practically every text on “dual intuitionistic logic” (although it is not properly a dual-intuitionistic logic). A gentle introduction can be found in [21].

  38. 38.

    Or bi-Heyting algebras, as has been widely called recently mainly by influence of Reyes and Zolfaghari. See for example [45].

  39. 39.

    A proof that every pair of subobjects in a topos has a union can be found in [8, Proposition 5.10.1]. Here is a sketch. Consider any two subobjects \(i \! : \! : S \! \longrightarrow \! O\) and \(j \! : \! : T \! \longrightarrow \! O\) of O in a topos \(\mathcal {E}\). Take their coproduct \(S+T\) and the morphism \(f \! : \! S+T \! \longrightarrow \! O\). As every morphism in a topos, f factors uniquely into an epimorphism followed by a monomorphism (see [8, Corollary 5.9.4]) \(f = k\circ p \! : \! S+T \! \twoheadrightarrow \! I \! \rightarrowtail \! O\). Morphisms from S and T to I, composed with i and j, imply that these are included in k (Ik is thus the smallest subobject of O which contains both Si and Tj.) A similar reasoning can be applied to show that every pair of subobjects in a topos has an intersection using products.

  40. 40.

    The next objection can be seen as trying to defend the original definition of negation against the suggested by complement-toposes, but this time using extra-categorial considerations.

  41. 41.

    Yet in [22] it is argued, with [27], that inconsistency-tolerant constructions in sheaf categories in general are not categorically natural (are not preserved by pullbacks along morphisms). A similar point was behind de Queiroz’s objection and the theorems by Reyes et al. I do not know whether there are still hidden “standard” assumptions behind the results in [22]; I will leave the investigation of that for future work.

References

  1. Awodey, S.: Structure in mathematics and logic: a categorical perspective. Philos. Math. 4(3), 209–237 (1996)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  2. Awodey, S.: Continuity and logical completeness: an application of sheaf theory and topoi. In: Johan van Benthem, M.R., Heinzmann, G., Visser, H. (eds.) The Age of Alternative Logics. Assesing Philosophy of Logic and Mathematics Today, pp. 139–149. Springer, The Netherlands (2006)

    Google Scholar 

  3. Bell, J.L.: Lectures on the foundations of mathematics. http://publish.uwo.ca/~jbell/foundations%20of%20mathematics.pdf

  4. Bell, J.L.: From absolute to local mathematics. Synthese 69, 409–426 (1986)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  5. Bell, J.L.: Toposes and Local Set Theories: An Introduction. Oxford Clarendon Press (1988)

    Google Scholar 

  6. Bell, J.L.: Oppositions and paradoxes in mathematics and philosophy. Axiomathes 15(2), 165–180 (2005)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  7. Béziau, J.-Y.: S5 is a paraconsistent logic and so is first-order classical logic. Logical Investigations 9, 301–309 (2002)

    Google Scholar 

  8. Borceux, F.: Handbook of Categorical Algebra. Volume 3: Categories of Sheaves.In: Encyclopedia of Mathematics and its Applications, vol. 50. Cambridge University Press (1994)

    Google Scholar 

  9. Carnielli, W.A., Coniglio, M.E., D’Ottaviano, I.M.L.: New dimensions on translations between logics. Log. Univers. 3(1), 1–18 (2009)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  10. Czermak, J.: A remark on Gentzen’s calculus of sequents. Notre Dame J. Form. Logic 18(3), 471–474 (1977)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  11. de Queiroz, G.d.S.: On the duality between intuitionism and paraconsistency. Ph.D. thesis, Universidade Estadual de Campinas (1998). In Portuguese

    Google Scholar 

  12. Estrada-González, L.: Quaternality in a topos-theoretical setting. Unpublished typescript, 201X

    Google Scholar 

  13. Estrada-González, L.: Complement-topoi and dual intuitionistic logic. Australas. J. Logic 9, 26–44 (2010)

    Google Scholar 

  14. Estrada-González, L.: Models of possibilism and trivialism. Logic Log. Philos. 22(4), 175–205 (2012)

    Google Scholar 

  15. Estrada-González, L.: Disputing the many-valuedness of topos logic. In: Béziau, J.-Y., D’Ottaviano, I.M.L., Costa-Leite, A. (eds.) Aftermath of the Logical Paradise, pp. 193–213. CLE-Universidade Estadual de Campinas, Campinas (2015)

    Google Scholar 

  16. Estrada-González, L.: From (paraconsistent) topos logic to Universal (topos) logic. In: Koslow, A., Buchsbaum, A.R.d.V. (eds.) The Road to Universal Logic. Festschrift for Jean-Yves Béziau, vol. 2, pp. 263–295. Birkhäuser (2015)

    Google Scholar 

  17. Goldblatt, R.: Grothendieck topology as geometric modality. Math. Logic Q. 27(31–35), 495–529 (1981)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  18. Goldblatt, R.: Topoi: The Categorial Analysis of Logic. Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics, vol. 98. North Holland Publishing Co., Amsterdam (1984). Revised edition

    Google Scholar 

  19. Goodman, N.: The logic of contradiction. Zeitschrift für Mathematische Logik und Grundlagen der Mathematik 27(8–10), 119–126 (2002)

    Google Scholar 

  20. Goré, R.P.: Dual intuitionistic logic revisited. In: Proceedings of the International Conference on Automated Reasoning with Analytic Tableaux and Related Methods. Lecture Notes In Computer Science, vol. 1847, pp. 252–267. Springer, London (2000)

    Google Scholar 

  21. Iturrioz, L.: Les algèbres de Heyting-Brouwer et de Łukasiewicz trivalentes. Notre Dame J. Form. Logic 17(1), 119–126 (1981)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  22. James, W., Mortensen, C.: Categories, sheaves, and paraconsistent logic. Unpublished typescript (1997)

    Google Scholar 

  23. Lawvere, F.W: Quantifiers and sheaves, In: Berger, M., Dieudonné, J., Leray, J., Lions, J.L., Malliavin, P., and Serre, J.P. (eds.) Actes du Congrés International des Mathematiciens, 329–334, Nice, Gauthier-Villars (1970)

    Google Scholar 

  24. Lawvere, F.W.: Continuously variable sets: algebraic geometry = geometric logic. In: Rose, H.E., Shepherdson, J.C. (eds.) Logic Colloquium ‘73 (Bristol, 1973), pp. 135–156. North Holland, Amsterdam (1975)

    Google Scholar 

  25. Lawvere, F.W.: Variable quantities and variable structures in topoi. In: Heller, A., Tierney, M. (eds.) Algebra, Topology, and Category Theory. A Collection of Papers in Honor of Samuel Eilenberg, pp. 101–131. Academic Press (1976)

    Google Scholar 

  26. Lawvere, F.W.: Introduction. In: Lawvere, F.W., Schanuel, S.H. (eds.) Categories in Continuum Physics. Springer (1982)

    Google Scholar 

  27. Lawvere, F.W.: Intrinsic co-Heyting boundaries and the Leibniz rule in certain toposes. In: Carboni, A., Pedicchio, M.C., Rosolini, G. (eds.) Proceedings of the 1990 Meeting on Category Theory held in Como, Italy. Lecture Notes in Mathematics, vol. 1488, pp. 279–281. Springer (1991)

    Google Scholar 

  28. Lawvere, F.W.: Tools for the advancement of objective logic: closed categories and toposes. In: Macnamara, J., Reyes, G.E. (eds.) The Logical Foundations of Cognition, pp. 43–56. Oxford University Press (1994)

    Google Scholar 

  29. Lawvere, F.W., Rosebrugh, R.: Sets for Mathematics. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (2003)

    Book  MATH  Google Scholar 

  30. Lawvere, F.W., Schanuel, S.H.: Conceptual Mathematics. A First Introduction to Categories. Cambridge University Press (2000). Second reprint

    Google Scholar 

  31. Mac Lane, S., Moerdijk, I.: Sheaves in Geometry and Logic: A First Introduction to Topos Theory. Springer (1992)

    Google Scholar 

  32. Macnab, D.S.: An Algebraic Study of Modal Operators on Heyting Algebras, with Applications to Topology and Sheafification. Ph.D. thesis, University of Aberdeen (1976)

    Google Scholar 

  33. Macnab, D.S.: Modal operators on Heyting algebras. Algebra Univers. 12(1), 5–29 (1981)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  34. Marcos, J.a.: Ineffable inconsistencies. In: Béziau, J.-Y., Carnielli, W.A. (eds.) Paraconsistency with No Frontiers, pp. 301–311. Elsevier, Amsterdam (2006)

    Google Scholar 

  35. McKinsey, J.C.C., Tarski, A.: Some theorems about the sentential calculi of Lewis and Heyting. J. Symb. Logic 13(1), 1–15 (1948)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  36. McLarty, C.: Book review: John Bell. Introduction to toposes and local set theory. Notre Dame J. Form. Logic 31(1), 150–161 (1989)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  37. McLarty, C.: Elementary Categories. Elementary Toposes. Oxford Clarendon Press, Toronto (1995)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  38. McLarty, C.: Two constructivist aspects of category theory. Philosophia Scientiæ 27(Cahier spécial 6), 95–114 (2006)

    Google Scholar 

  39. Mortensen, C.: Inconsistent Mathematics. Kluwer Mathematics and Its Applications Series. Kluwer Academic Publishers (1995)

    Google Scholar 

  40. Mortensen, C.: Closed set logic. In: Brady, R.T. (ed.) Relevant Logics and Their Rivals, vol. II, pp. 254–262. Ashgate Publishing, Aldershot (2003)

    Google Scholar 

  41. Popper, K.: On the theory of deduction, parts I and II. Indagationes Mathematicae 10, 173–183 and 322–331 (1948)

    Google Scholar 

  42. Rauszer, C.: Semi-Boolean algebras and their applications to intuitionistic logic with dual operations. Fundam. Math. 83, 219–249 (1974)

    MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  43. Rauszer, C.: An algebraic and Kripke-style approach to a certain extension of intuitionistic logic. Diss. Math. 167, 1–62 (1980)

    MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  44. Reyes, G., Zawadowski, M.: Formal systems for modal operators on locales. Stud. Logica 52(4), 595–613 (1993)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  45. Reyes, G., Zolfaghari, H.: Topos-theoretic approaches to modality. In: Carboni, A., Pedicchio, M.C., Rosolini, G. (eds.) Proceedings of the 1990 Meeting on Category Theory held in Como, Italy. Lecture Notes in Mathematics, vol. 1488, pp. 359–378. Springer (1991)

    Google Scholar 

  46. Reyes, G., Zolfaghari, H.: Bi-Heyting algebras, toposes and modalities. J. Philos. Logic 25(1), 25–43 (1996)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  47. Rodin, A.: Axiomatic Method and Category Theory. http://arxiv.org/pdf/1210.1478v1.pdf

  48. Shramko, Y.: Dual intuitionistic logic and a variety of negations: the logic of scientific research. Stud. Logica 80(2–3), 347–367 (2005)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  49. Tierney, M.: Sheaf theory and the continuum hypothesis. In: Lawvere, F.W. (ed.) Toposes, Algebraic Geometry and Logic. Lecture Notes in Mathematics, vol. 274, pp. 13–42. Springer (1972)

    Google Scholar 

  50. Urbas, I.: Dual intuitionistic logic. Notre Dame J. Form. Logic 37(3), 440–451 (1996)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  51. van Inwagen, P.: Metaphysics. Westview Press, Boulder, Colorado (2008). Third Edition

    Google Scholar 

  52. Vasyukov, V.: Structuring the universe of universal logic. Log. Univers. 1(2), 277–294 (2007)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  53. Vigna, S.: A guided tour in the topos of graphs. Technical Report 199–7, Università di Milano, Dipartimento di Scienze dell’Informazione (1997). http://vigna.dsi.unimi.it/papers.ToposGraphs.pdf

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Luis Estrada-González .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2015 Springer India

About this paper

Cite this paper

Estrada-González, L. (2015). The Evil Twin: The Basics of Complement-Toposes. In: Beziau, JY., Chakraborty, M., Dutta, S. (eds) New Directions in Paraconsistent Logic. Springer Proceedings in Mathematics & Statistics, vol 152. Springer, New Delhi. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-81-322-2719-9_18

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics