Skip to main content

The Contingency of Willing: A Vijñānavāda Critique of Schopenhauer and Nietzsche

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Ethics without Self, Dharma without Atman
  • 561 Accesses

Abstract

Much has been written in the past century, and particularly in the last few decades, on the degrees to which Schopenhauer and Nietzsche were influenced by their acquaintances with South Asian Buddhist thought. In addition, comparative philosophy scholars have, apart from historical issues of influence, speculated about various ways in which Schopenhauerian or Nietzschean thought might have some significant resonance with various systems of classical Buddhism. However, considerably less has been written about how the works of Schopenhauer and Nietzsche might be assessed from Buddhist perspectives. In this essay, I wish to critically examine these two seminal nineteenth century thinkers on the basis of what ended up becoming one of the most important schools of Buddhist thought, namely early South Asian Vijńānavāda. I will demonstrate that Schopenhauer, with some qualification, argues that, though the ascetic can “deny the will-to-live” in a final act of world-renunciation, the will as thing in itself remains the ground of the world’s existence. For Nietzsche, the act of willing remains what I will call an “incorrigible” element of our existence, for even the act of interpreting on the part of would-be ascetics is a function of their will(s) to power and life. Classical Vijńānavāda thinkers, however, given their special reformulations of standard Abhidharma Buddhist frameworks, maintain that willing is a contingent function of the human psyche and conduct, and that eliminating it through practice is indeed the key to genuine and lasting awakening. In the end, Schopenhauer’s and Nietzsche’s differing conceptions of the will are thus profoundly un-Buddhist.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    There is an extensive literature on Schopenhauer and Indian thought that stretches all the way back to the late nineteenth century, but some of the most thorough studies recently have been done by App (1998a and b) and myself (Berger 2004). In the case of Nietzsche, a number of insightful investigations can be found in Graham Parkes’ edited volume Nietzsche and Asian Thought, including Hulin (1993) and Sprung (1993) . Incisive hermeneutic analysis of their respective receptions of Indian thought can always be found in the work of the late Wilhelm Halbfass (1988) .

  2. 2.

    Once again, the literature comparing Schopenhauer’s system to classical Hindu and Buddhist thought has a longer history, but the quality of these efforts is often low, as for instance in the work of Dauer (1969). Recently, Nietzsche’s work has received more comparative attention on the part of predominantly East Asian thinkers, but there have been some interesting attempts to find affinities between his ideas and some South Asian Buddhist systems, such as in Martin (1993), Morrison (1999) and van der Braak (2011) .

  3. 3.

    A bit more critical assessment of Schopenhauer’s characterizations of Brāhmiṇical thought has been undertaken, including comments by Radhakrishnan (1929) and a brilliant essay by Hacker (1995) . Interestingly, Jay Garfield (2002) has offered a kind of stage theory about how Berkeley, Schopenhauer and Nietzsche came close to approximating positions taken in Vijñānavāda.

  4. 4.

    Schopenhauer 1966a, xv–xvi.

  5. 5.

    Schopenhauer 1974, 187; see also 1966a 356–7 and 1966b, 584.

  6. 6.

    Nietzsche 1967b, 161, 1990, 42, 1967c, 180.

  7. 7.

    1966a, 411–12; 1966b, 629.

  8. 8.

    1967a, 59; 1964a, 74; 1974, 165–6.

  9. 9.

    Schopenhauer 1966a, 100, 105, 110–11.

  10. 10.

    This slow but sure shift in Schopenhauer’s position on will has been convincingly demonstrated in the works of Julian Young (1987) and John Atwell (1995).

  11. 11.

    Schopenhuaer, 1966b, 35; 196–7.

  12. 12.

    Schopenhauer 1966b 197.

  13. 13.

    Schopenhauer 1966b, 325.

  14. 14.

    See Schopenhauer, 1999, 69; 136–45 and 1964a, 363–73.

  15. 15.

    1969a, 365; 1999, 209.

  16. 16.

    1969a, 372–3.

  17. 17.

    1999, 193.

  18. 18.

    1966a, 378–9; 403.

  19. 19.

    1966a, 411.

  20. 20.

    Schopenhauer 1966a, 412.

  21. 21.

    Ibid., 391–2.

  22. 22.

    The notion that the various attempts by Nietzsche to affirm the will to life were alternative “formulae,” sidestepping the question of how much metaphysical currency should be put into any of them, was argued by Maudmarie Clark (1990, 282) some time ago, and I find this analysis of Nietzsche’s works convincing.

  23. 23.

    1967a, 59.

  24. 24.

    Nietzsche, 1964b,270–71.

  25. 25.

    1966a, 140–41.

  26. 26.

    1995, 137–42.

  27. 27.

    1967a, 17.

  28. 28.

    1997, 110.

  29. 29.

    Nietzsche, 1964a, 26–7.

  30. 30.

    1990, 11 (40)42 and 12 (1)58.

  31. 31.

    This debate was to a large extent initiated by the variant readings of Nietzsche in Heidegger (1979), Foucault (1984) and Derrida (1989) but continues to be waged in the secondary literature in the works of such scholars as Nehamas (1985) and Richardson (2002).

  32. 32.

    1974, 128.

  33. 33.

    1964a, 226.

  34. 34.

    Nietzsche 1967c, 267.

  35. 35.

    1967c, 550.

  36. 36.

    Ibid.

  37. 37.

    Ibid., 339. These “quanta” in Nietzsche’s ruminations take the place of classical mechanistic “atoms” when nature is considered most carefully.

  38. 38.

    1964a, 51–2.

  39. 39.

    1964b, 164.

  40. 40.

    1964a, 32–3.

  41. 41.

    Bodhi (2005) 337, Kochumuttom (1982), 64, 66.

  42. 42.

    Bodhi (2005) 333, Kochumuttom (1982), 135.

  43. 43.

    Waldron 1994, 230, Kochumuttom (1982), 68.

  44. 44.

    See Jiang (2006), 41–6 on how the Vijñānavādins better addressed “the problem of continuity” created by the Buddhist doctrine of impermanence than other scholastic movements of Buddhist thought (Kochumuttom 1982), 136.

  45. 45.

    Madhyānta Vibhāga 1:9–10 (Kochumuttom 1982), 136.

  46. 46.

    Trimśātika 2–4 (Kochumuttom 1982), 138.

  47. 47.

    See Sthiramati’s Madhyānta Vibhāga Kārika Bhāṣya Tikā 1:11 (Kochumuttom 1982), 138.

  48. 48.

    Trimśātika 5–6.

  49. 49.

    Trimśātika 7.

  50. 50.

    Trimśātika 9–11.

  51. 51.

    Ibid.

  52. 52.

    1966a, 141–2.

  53. 53.

    Schopenhauer 1966a, 98–9.

  54. 54.

    1966a, 105.

  55. 55.

    1967b, 119.

  56. 56.

    1974, 148, 49.

References

  • App, Urs. 1998a. Notes and Excerpts by Schopenhauer Related to Volumes 1-9 of the Asiatick Researches. Schopenhauer Jahrbuch 79 (1998): 11–33.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1998b. Schopenhauers Begegnung mit dem Buddhismus. Schopenhauer Jahrbuch 79 (1998): 35–56.

    Google Scholar 

  • Atwell, John E. 1995. Schopenhauer: On the Character of the World: The Metaphysics of Will. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berger, Douglas L. 2004. “The Veil of Māyā:” Schopenhauer’s System and Early Indian Thought. Binghamton: Global Academic Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bodhi, Bhikkhu. (trans.). 2005. In the Buddha’s Words: An Anthology of Discourses from the Pāli Canon. Boston: Wisdom Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, Maudmarie. 1990. Nietzsche on Truth and Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dauer, Dorothea. 1969. Schopenhauer as Transmitter of Buddhist Ideas. Berne: Herbert Lang.

    Google Scholar 

  • Derrida, Jacques. 1989. Interpreting Signatures (Nietzsche/Heidegger): Two Questions. In Dialogue and Deconstruction: The Gadamer-Derrida Encounter. Trans. Diane P. Michelfelder and Richard E. Palmer. Albany: SUNY Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Garfield, Jay L. 2002. Empty Words: Buddhist Philosophy and Cross-Cultural Interpretation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hacker, Paul. 1995. Schopenhauer and Hindu Ethics. In Philology and Confrontation: Paul Hacker on Traditional and Modern Vedānta. Ed. and Trans. Wilhelm Halbfass, 273–318. Albany: SUNY Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Halbfass, Wilhelm. 1988. India and Europe: An Essay in Understanding. Albany: SUNY Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, Martin. 1979. Nietzsche, vol. I–IV. Trans. David Farrell Krell. San Francisco: Harper.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hulin, Michael. 1993. Nietzsche and the Suffering of the Indian Ascetic. In Nietzsche and Asian Thought, ed. Graham Parkes, 64–75. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jiang, Tao. 2006. Contexts and Dialogue: Yogācāra Buddhism and Modern Psychology on the Subliminal Mind. Honolulu: University of Hawai’i Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kochumuttom, Thomas A. 1982. A Buddhist Doctrine of Experience: A New Translation and Interpretation of the Works of Vasabandhu the Yogācārin. Motilal Banarassidas: Delhi.

    Google Scholar 

  • Martin, Glen T. 1993. Deconstruction and Breakthrough in Nietzsche and Nāgārjuna. In Nietzsche and Asian Thought, ed. Graham Parkes, 91–113. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Morrison, Robert G. 1999. Nietzsche and Buddhism: A Study in Nihilism and Ironic Affinities. Clarendon: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nehamas, Alexander. 1985. Nietzsche: Life as Literature. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nietzsche, Friedrich. 1964a. Beyond Good and Evil. Trans. Helen Zimmern. New York: Russell and Russell.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1964b. The Joyful Wisdom. Trans. Thomas Common, New York: Russell and Russell.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1967a. The Birth of Tragedy and the Case of Wagner. Trans. Walter Kaufmann. New York: Random House.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1967b. On the Genealogy of Morals/Ecce Homo. Trans. Walter Kaufmann, New York: Random House.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1967c. The Will to Power. Trans. Walter Kaufmann and R.J. Hollingdale. London: Weidenfeld and Nicholson.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1974. The Twilight of the Idols/The Antichrist. Trans. Anthony M. Ludovici. New York: Gordon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1990. Sämtliche Werke, Kritische Studienausgabe, vol. 10 of 15, ed. Georgio Colli and Mozino Montinari. München: Deutscher Taschenbuch Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Radhakrishnan, Sarvapali. 1929. Indian Philosophy, vol. 1 of 2. Delhi: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Richardson, John. 2002. Nietzsche’s System. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schopenhauer, Arthur. 1966a and b. The World as Will and Representation, vol. 1 and 2. Trans. E.F.J. Payne. New York: Dover Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1974. On the Fourfold Root of the Principle of Sufficient Reason. Trans. E.F.J. Payne. La Salle: Open Court.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1999. On the Basis of Morality. Trans. E.F.J. Payne. Cambridge: Hackett Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sprung, Mervyn. 1993. Nietzsche’s Trans-European Eye. In Nietzsche and Asian Thought, ed. Graham Parkes. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • van der Braak, Andre. 2011. Nietzsche and Zen: Self-Overcoming Without a Self. Plymouth: Lexington Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Waldron, William. 1994. How Innovative is the Ālayavijñāna? The Ālayavijñāna in the Context of Canonical and Abhidharma Vijñāna Theory. Journal of Indian Philosophy 11: 199–258.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Young, Julian. 1987. Willing and Unwilling: A Study in the Philosophy of Arthur Schopenhauer. Dordrecht: Martinus Nijhoff.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Douglas L. Berger .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2018 Springer International Publishing AG, part of Springer Nature

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Berger, D.L. (2018). The Contingency of Willing: A Vijñānavāda Critique of Schopenhauer and Nietzsche. In: Davis, G. (eds) Ethics without Self, Dharma without Atman. Sophia Studies in Cross-cultural Philosophy of Traditions and Cultures, vol 24. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-67407-0_8

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics