Skip to main content

The Debate About Moral Equality

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Moral Equality, Bioethics, and the Child

Part of the book series: International Library of Ethics, Law, and the New Medicine ((LIME,volume 67))

  • 397 Accesses

Abstract

In this chapter, I delineate some of the problems of classical approaches to parenthood. It will become clear how moral adultism has seeped into much of what has been written about childhood ethics. I examine different approaches, including child rights and welfare rights approaches, that attempt to realize the equal moral consideration of the child and show why, in a significant aspect, they fail to achieve this goal. A moral-equality approach should avoid developmentalism and moral adultism, and focus on the child’s agency and moral self-respect.

It’s time, according to both clinicians and researchers, to change how we relate to children—to move from a subject-object relationship to a subject-subject relationship.

Jesper Juul 2011, p. 6

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 49.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 64.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 99.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    See also Brighouse (2002) and Griffin (2002).

  2. 2.

    For other examples of the proprietarian view, see Archard and Macleod (2002, pp. 1–3); for criticism, see also Murray (1996, pp. 53–62).

  3. 3.

    For a thorough criticism of this perspective, see Dwyer (2006).

  4. 4.

    Likewise, Onora O’Neill classifies parental obligations as “atypical” (O’Neill 1979, p. 27).

  5. 5.

    They do not explain why they consider only the right not to be harmed decisive for limiting parents’ stewardship. Other rights of the child, like the right to privacy or to own property, can also be seriously violated.

  6. 6.

    Yet, Thomas Murray rightly criticizes that the stewardship model wrongly implies detached, selfless care and discounts parents’ interests and welfare in the parent-child relationship (Murray 1996, p. 61): “The child is more than property, and the parent is more than a caretaker. We need a model of the parent-child relationship that acknowledges the immense stake parents and children have in each other’s flourishing. We need a model that emphasizes the central importance of the relationship, without losing sight of the individuality of the parties”.

  7. 7.

    In the past, cruelty to children was often justified this way (Miller 1983). The prominent saying “Spare the rod and spoil the child” served as justification for spanking the child in order to benefit the future person. For a more recent justification of privileging the interests of the future person see Anderson’s and Claassen’s discussion of the case of 14-year-old Laura Dekker who endeavoured a round-the-world sailing tour (Anderson and Claassen 2012, p. 519). Youf (2002, p. 132), also prioritizes the future interests of the child in medical treatment.

  8. 8.

    For a critical discussion of present versus life-time autonomy see Vaught (2008). Christoph Schickhardt , too, dismisses the idea that a benefit for the future adult is an acceptable trade-off for ignoring the child’s well-being right now (Schickhardt 2012, p. 184); for a critical discussion of “subsequent consent” to paternalistic acts in educations see pp. 202–204.

  9. 9.

    For an instructive account of the philosophical preoccupation with the future adult and its critique since Rousseau, see Giesinger (2007, pp. 81–144).

  10. 10.

    For a critical examination of the philosophical underpinnings of Piaget’s developmental theory, see Gareth Matthews (1994, pp. 30–53), Carnevale (2004). For a critical perspective from a sociologist’s point of view on adultism in Piaget’s work, see Jenks (2005, p. 22f); James (2009). On philosophical conceptions of childhood and adulthood see Kennedy (2006).

  11. 11.

    See also Arneil (2002).

  12. 12.

    However, in a critical analysis of the empirical research on early moral development, Augusto Blasi would deny this for children younger than three or four (Blasi 2000, p. 135).

  13. 13.

    See Flasher (1978) and Guessous (2012). Chris Jenks uses the term “ethnocentrism”, instead, to denote the fact that “socialization theories present the normative structure of the adult/parent world as their independent variable. Even though all sociologists are aware that such a notion of normative structure is itself a highly problematic belief from which to begin, it is nevertheless treated as yardstick in relation to the child. Against this yardstick of an assumed consensus of reality the child is judged to be more of less competent and consequently the continuous lived social practice of being a child with a specific and coherent meaning structure is wholly ignored” (Jenks 2005, p. 9).

  14. 14.

    A notable counter example is James Dwyer’s recent argument for the moral superiority of children (Dwyer 2011). Dwyer presents strong arguments to undermine the common conviction that adults are naturally superior to children and shows why one should base moral status on more than just one criterion. I thoroughly sympathize with Dwyer’s mission, yet, unlike him, I am less interested in, and less equipped for, a philosophical analysis of moral status and more interested in the moral agency of children.

  15. 15.

    See, e.g., Robert Noggle’s characterization of infants and very young children: “Infants and very young children begin in an ‘egocentric predicament’. Their concern is focused on their own immediate interests. From this initial stage of straightforward, naïve, and immediate egoism, the child progresses to a stage of more enlightened—though still quite direct—egoism. In this stage, punishment, reward, and the desire to please and imitate the parent operate to make morally decent behaviour pay off in a purely short-term, self-serving way” (Noggle 2002, p. 110).

  16. 16.

    For a detailed historical account of the international reception as well as the German theological discourse, see Surall (2009); for a discussion from the French perspective, see Renaut (2002).

  17. 17.

    The last is the only one not to be conceived of as a clear-cut right.

  18. 18.

    Archard, David William, “Children’s Rights”, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2014 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2014/entries/rights-children/, accessed February. 22, 2016.

  19. 19.

    Freeman (2009, p. 386f). Usually, the CRC’s rights are divided into provision, protection and participation rights. However, provision and participation rights both aim at the welfare of the child. For this ethical analysis, then, I deal with both under the category of welfare rights.

  20. 20.

    J. Giesinger: “Dignity and Education”, Presentation at the Conference “Encountering Children—Dignity, Autonomy, and Care”, June 9, 2011, University of Zurich, Switzerland.

  21. 21.

    Anderson and Honneth (2005) distinguish between self-respect as related to one’s competency and personal authority and self-esteem as related to one’s worth, but since both pertain to the dignity or moral core of one’s personality, I will use them indiscriminately. For a philosophical discussion of the notion ‘self-respect’, see also the book edited by Dillon (1995). Unfortunately, none of the authors of this book discusses the self-respect of children.

  22. 22.

    Cf. Peter Schaber’s interpretation of human dignity as being based on self-respect (Schaber 2004).

  23. 23.

    For a discussion of the case, see Cornock (2010), Schickhardt (2012, pp. 267–274).

  24. 24.

    Tim Bayne and Avery Kolers sketch a pluralistic picture of the nature of parenthood rooted in gestation, genetic derivation and intentions (Bayne and Kolers 2003). Yet, they do not account for the perspective of the child. Michael W. Austin in his book “Conceptions of Parenthood” combines the two approaches and also arrives at a pluralistic account including “a consideration of the interest of current parents, potential parents, children, and society as a whole” (Austin 2007, p. 58). Bonnie Steinbock argues that the concept of parenthood should be based on the standard of the child’s best interest (Steinbock 2006). For a concept based on rights and responsibilities see (Archard 2010).

References

  • Adams, H. 2008. Justice for children. Autonomy Development and the State: State University of New York Press, Albany.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alderson, P. 2008. Young children’s rights. Exploring beliefs, principles and practice. London: Jessica Kingsley Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, J., and R. Claassen. 2012. Sailing alone: Teenage autonomy and regimes of childhood. Law and Philosophy 31: 495–522.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, J., and A. Honneth. 2005. Autonomy, vulnerability, recognition, and justice. In Autonomy and the challenges to liberalism, ed. J. Christman, and J. Anderson, 127–149. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Archard, D. 2004. Children. Rights and childhood. London, New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Archard, D. 2010. The obligations and responsibilities of parenthood. In Procreation and parenthood, ed. D. Archard, and D. Benatar, 103–127. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Archard, D. 2015. Children, Adults, autonomy and well-being. In The nature of children’s well-being. theory and practice, eds. A. Bagattini, C. Macleod, 3–14. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Archard, D., and C. Macleod. 2002. Introduction. In The moral and political status of children, ed. D. Archard, and C. Macleod, 19–30. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Arneil, B. 2002. Becoming versus being: A critical analysis of the child in liberal theory. In The moral and political status of children, ed. D. Archard, and C. Macleod, 70–94. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Austin, M.W. 2007. Conceptions of parenthood. Ashgate, Aldershot: Ethics and the Family.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bayne, T., and A. Kolers. 2003. Toward a pluralistic account of parenthood. Bioethics Quarterly 17: 221–242.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blasi, A. 2005. What should count as moral behavior? the nature of “early morality” in children’s development. In Morality in context, ed. W. Edelstein, and G. Nunner-Winkler, 119–141. Amsterdam: Elsevier.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Blasi, A. 2000. Was sollte als moralisches Verhalten gelten? Das Wesen der ‘frühen Moral’ in der kindlichen Entwicklung. In Moral im sozialen Kontext, ed. W. Edelstein, and G. Nunner-Winkler, 116–145. Frankfurt/M: Suhrkamp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brennan, S. 2002. Children’s choices or children’s interest: Which do their rights protect? In The moral and political status of children, ed. D. Archard, and C. Macleod, 53–69. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Brennan, S., and R. Noggle. 1997. The moral status of children. children’s rights, parents’ rights, and family justice. Social Theory and Practice 23: 1–26.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brighouse, H. 2002. What rights (if any) do children have? In The moral and political status of children, ed. D. Archard, and C. Macleod, 31–52. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Brighouse, H., and A. Swift. 2006. Parents’ Rights and the Value of the Family. Ethics 117: 80–108.

    Google Scholar 

  • Callaghan, T., H. Moll, H. Rakoczy, F. Warneken, U. Liszkowski, T. Behne, and M. Tomasello. 2011. Early social cognition in three cultural contexts. Monographs of the Society for Research in Child Development 76: 1–142.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carnevale, F.M. 2004. Listening authentically to youthful voices: a conception of the moral agency of children. In Toward a moral horizon: Nursing ethics for leadership and practice, ed. J.L. Storch, P. Rodney, and R. Starzomski, 396–413. Toronto: Pearson.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cornock, M. 2010. Hannah Jones, consent and the child in action: A legal commentary. Paediatric Nursing 22: 14–20.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dillon, R.S. 1995. Introduction. In Dignity, character, and self-respect, ed. R.S. Dillon, 1–49. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dwyer, J.G. 2006. The relationship rights of children. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dwyer, J.G. 2011. Moral status and human life. The case for children’s superiority. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feinberg, J. 1980. The child’s right to an open future. In Whose child? children’s rights, parental authority, and state power, eds. W. Aiken, H. LaFollette, 124–153. Totowa,NJ: Littlefield, Adams, and Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Flasher, J. 1978. Adultism. Adolescence 13: 517–523.

    Google Scholar 

  • Freeman, M. 2009. Children’s rights as human rights: Reading the UNCRC. In The palgrave handbook of childhood studies, eds. J. Qvortrup, W.A. Corsaro, M.-S. Honig, 377–393. London: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Giesinger, J. 2007. Autonomie und Verletzlichkeit. Der moralische Status von Kindern und die Rechtfertigung von Erziehung. transcript, Bielefeld.

    Google Scholar 

  • Giesinger, J. 2010. Dignity and education. Presentation at the Conference “Encountering Children—Dignity, Autonomy, and Care”, June 9, 2011. University of Zurich. http://www.erziehungsphilosophie.ch/vortraege/Giesinger-Dignity_and_Education-Vortrag.pdf. Accessed 22 Feb 2016.

  • Giesinger, J. 2012. Respect in education. Journal of Philosophy of Education 46: 100–112.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gopnik, A. 2009. The philosophical child. What children’s mind tell us about truth, love, and the meaning of life. Farrar, Straus and Giroux, New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Griffin, J. 2002. Do children have rights? In The moral and political status of children, ed. D. Archard, and C. Macleod, 19–30. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Guessous, O. 2012. Adultism. In Youth activism. An international encyclopedia, ed. L.R. Sharrod, vol. 1, 48–50. Westport, CT: Greenwood Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Guggenheim, M. 2002. Minor rights: The adolescent abortion case. Hofstra Law Review 30: 589–646.

    Google Scholar 

  • Guggenheim, M. 2005. What’s wrong with children’s rights?. Harvard: Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hafen, B.C., and J.O. Hafen. 1996. Abandoning children to their autonomy: The United Nations Convention on the Rights of the Child. Harvard International Law Journal 37: 449–491.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hamann, K., F. Warneken, J.R. Greenberg, and M. Tomasello. 2011. Collaboration encourages equal sharing in children but not in chimpanzees. Nature 476: 328–331.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hansson, M.G., U. Kihlbom, T. Tuvemo, and A. Rodriguez. 2009. Concern for privacy in relation to age during physical examination of children: an exploratory study. Acta Paediatrica 98: 1349–1354.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Helwig, C.C., and E. Turiel. 2002. Children’s social and moral reasoning. In Blackwell handbook of childhood social development, ed. P.K. Smith, and C.H. Hart, 475–490. Malden, MA: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Holt, J. 1974. Escape From Childhood. The Needs and Rights of Children. Penguin Books, Harmondsworth.

    Google Scholar 

  • James, A. 2009. Agency. In The palgrave handbook of childhood studies, ed. J. Qvortrup, W.A. Corsaro, and M.-S. Honig, 34–45. London: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jenks, C. 2005. Childhood. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Keller, M. 2007. Moralentwicklung und moralische Sozialisation. In Moralentwicklung von Kindern und Jugendlichen, ed. D. Horster, 17–49. Wiesbaden: Verlag für Sozialwissenschaften.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Kennedy, D. 2006. The well of being: Childhood, subjectivity, and education. Albany: SUNY Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • LaFollette, H. 1980. Licensing Parents. Philosophy and Public Affairs 9: 182–197.

    Google Scholar 

  • LaFollette, H. 1996. Personal relationships: Love, identity, and morality. Oxford, Cambridge: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Macleod, C. 2010. Primary goods, capabilities and children. In Measuring justice. Primary goods and capabilities, eds. I. Robeyns, H. Brighouse, 174–192. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Matthews, G.B. 1994. The philosophy of childhood. Harvard: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mayall, B. 2003. Sociologies of childhood and educational thinking. London: Institute of Education.

    Google Scholar 

  • Miller, A. 1983. For your own good. Farrar, Straus, Giroux, New York: Hidden cruelty in child-rearing and the roots of violence.

    Google Scholar 

  • Murray, T.H. 1996. The worth of a child. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Narveson, J. 2007. Parental responsibility. In Taking responsibility for children, ed. S. Brennan, and R. Noggle, 19–45. Waterloo, Ontario: Wilfrid Laurier University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Noggle, R. 2002. Special agents: Children’s autonomy and parental authority. In The moral and political status of children, ed. D. Archard, and C. Macleod, 98–117. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Neill, O. 1979. Begetting, bearing, and rearing. In Having children. Philosophical and legal reflections on parenthood, eds. O. O’Neill, W. Ruddick, 25–38. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Purdy, L.M. 1992. In their best interest? The Case Against Equal Rights for Children. Ithaca, New York: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Renaut, A. 2002. La libération des enfants. Bayard, Paris: Contribution philosophique à une histoire de l’enfance.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schaber, P. 2004. Menschenwürde und Selbstachtung. Ein Vorschlag zum Verständnis der Menschenwürde. Studia Philosophica 63: 93–106.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schickhardt, C. 2012. Kinderethik. Mentis, Münster: Der moralische Status und die Rechte der Kinder.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schrag, F. 1980. Children: Their rights and needs. In Whose child? children’s rights, parental authority, and state power, ed. W. Aiken, and H. LaFollette, 237–253. Littlefield: Totowa, NJ.

    Google Scholar 

  • Steinbock, B. 2006. Defining parenthood. In Children’s health and children’s rights, ed. M. Freeman, 311–334. Leiden, Boston: Martinus Nijhoff Publishers.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Strawson, P.F. 2008. Freedom and resentment [1962]. In Freedom and resentment and other essays, ed. P.F. Strawson, 1–28. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Surall, F. 2009. Ethik des Kindes. Kohlhammer, Stuttgart: Kinderrechte und ihre theologisch-ethische Rezeption.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tomasello, M. 2011. Human culture in evolutionary perspective. In Advances in culture and psychology, ed. M. Gelfand, 5–51. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Turiel, E. 2006. The Development of morality. In Handbook of child psychology, ed. N. Eisenberg, 789–857. Hoboken, NJ: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vaught, W. 2008. Autonomy and the rights of minors. In Autonomy and human rights in health care. An international perspective, eds. D.N. Weisstub, G. Díaz Pinto, 111–122. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Youf, D. 2002. Penser les droits de l'enfant. Paris: Presses Universitaires de France.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Claudia Wiesemann .

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2016 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Wiesemann, C. (2016). The Debate About Moral Equality. In: Moral Equality, Bioethics, and the Child. International Library of Ethics, Law, and the New Medicine, vol 67. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-32402-9_2

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics