Skip to main content

Hylomorphism: Emergent Properties without Emergentism

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Biology and Subjectivity

Part of the book series: Historical-Analytical Studies on Nature, Mind and Action ((HSNA,volume 2))

Abstract

Hylomorphism claims that structure is a basic ontological and explanatory principle. It accounts for what things are and what they can do. The hylomorphic notion of structure provides resources for understanding the place of mind in the natural world. The activities of living things like us are not random physiological occurrences; they are physiological occurrences with a certain organization or structure. We engage in them by imposing an order on the ways our parts manifest their powers. According to the hylomorphic view I defend, thought, feeling, perception, and intentional action are structured activities of this sort. The result is a theory of mental phenomena that rejects physicalism but that is nevertheless naturalistic. It is also antireductive: it denies that psychological discourse is reducible to physical theory. Finally, it provides an unmysterious account of how mental phenomena fit within the natural world.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Other accounts of hylomorphic structure that have appeared in the literature include Fine’s (1999), Johnston’s (2006), Oderberg’s (2007), Koslicki’s (2008), and Rea’s (2011). The account of hylomorphic structured I’ll be developing here differs from theirs in ways that I trust will become evident as I proceed.

  2. 2.

    Brian Ellis states the basic idea as follows: “[W]hich predicates designate properties[?]… I answer: first decide what properties and structure s you must postulate if you wish to give an adequate account of the phenomena, and then decide which expressions of the language refer to these properties or structure s” (2002, pp. 44–45). Consider likewise Armstrong, Molnar, and Swoyer respectively: “[H]ow do we determine what the true universals are? My suggestion is that they are best postulated on the basis of total science (2010, p. 19); “[W]hat properties there are is… determined… on a posteriori grounds, most likely by current best science” (2003, p. 27). “the claim that there are such things as properties is a philosophical one, but determining just what properties there are is – like questions about existence generally – an empirical matter” (1982, p. 205).

  3. 3.

    Martin (1996a) defends this idea with an example: it seems possible that there might be fundamental physical particles in the universe that have the power to interact in various ways with particles around here, and yet that are so far away that they reside outside the light cone of the particles around here. The two groups of particles never actually interact, yet it seems obvious that the distant particles still have the power to interact with the local ones.

  4. 4.

    Harré and Madden’s (1975) examples of radioactive decay and ammonium tri-iodide seem initially to provide counterexamples to the general rule that powers are manifested or exercised in pairs, or triples, or n-tuples. But even here it might be possible to understand the cases in a way that conforms to the general reciprocity model. At the very least the environment surrounding the radioactive nuclei or the ammonium tri-iodide cannot include any agents that inhibit the exercise of their powers to decay or explode, respectively. Environments that are free of inhibitory factors might then be viewed as reciprocal disposition partners for the decaying nuclei and the explosive compound.

  5. 5.

    Craver (2007, Chapter 5) calls purely spatial parts ‘pieces’ and parts in the functional sense ‘components’. Heil (2003, p. 100) also suggests something like the distinction between merely spatial parts and parts of other sorts, which he calls ‘substantial parts’.

  6. 6.

    The term ‘functional analysis ’ is due to Cummins (1975). Becthel (2008) calls it ‘mechanistic decomposition’ or ‘functional decomposition’. Craver (2007) subsumes it under the heading of ‘mechanistic explanation ’. He takes Cummins’s notion of functional analysis to be the exemplar of what he calls the ‘systems tradition’, but argues that Cummins fails to provide an adequate account of mechanistic explanation. He thus distances himself from the term ‘functional analysis ’.

  7. 7.

    Elsewhere I’ve discussed functional analysis in greater detail. I’ve argued among other things that it does not correspond to the notion of function that is operative in discussions of functionalism in the philosophy of mind (including teleological functionalism), and that it does not imply a commitment to reductionism (Jaworski 2011, 2012, 2016).

  8. 8.

    Many hylomorphists of the past have denied the embodiment thesis. Aristotle himself appears to deny it in De Anima III.4. There he appears to argue that understanding or nous, the power to grasp the essences of things, has no organ and is in general unmixed (amigēs) with a body (429a 10–27). There are several things to say in response. First, a commitment to the essential embodiment of our capacities is the default position for a hylomorphist. In fact Aristotle treats embodiment as the default position as well (403a 16–19, 24–27; 403b 17–18). We cannot do most of the things we do (walking, breathing, perceiving, eating, and so on) without some of our parts manifesting their powers in coordinated ways. Against this background of embodied activity the claim that nous is not essentially embodied stands out as anomalous. Commentators like Shields suggest that the claim stretches Aristotle’s hylomorphic framework “almost beyond the limits of recognition” (2014, pp. 354–355). Given the foregoing, a hylomorphist should look to reject the embodiment thesis only if there is a powerful argument against it. Most of the arguments that have been advanced against the thesis are descendants of the argument in De Anima III.4. I argue elsewhere in detail that that argument is flawed in a variety of ways (Jaworski 2016).

  9. 9.

    A version of this paper was presented at the Fordham-Rutgers Metaphysics of Mind Conference held at Fordham University in March 2015. I discuss the hylomorphic view it outlines in greater detail in Structure and the Metaphysics of Mind: How Hylomorphism Solves the Mind-Body Problem (Oxford University Press, 2016). Some of the materials that appears in this chapter was originally published in that book, and has been reproduced by permission of Oxford University Press https://global.oup.com/academic/product/structure-and-the-metaphysics-of-mind-9780198749561.

References

  • Armstrong, D.M. 1978a. Realism and nominalism: Universals and scientific realism, vol. 1. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Armstrong, D.M. 1978b. A theory of universals: Universals and scientific realism, vol. 2. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Armstrong, D.M. 2010. Sketch for a systematic metaphysics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, W., and R.C. Richardson. 1993. Discovering complexity: Decomposition and localization as strategies in scientific research. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, W. 2007. Reducing psychology while maintaining its autonomy via mechanistic explanations. In The matter of the mind, ed. M. Schouten and H. Looren de Jong. Oxford: Blackwell Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, W. 2008. Mental mechanisms: Philosophical perspectives on cognitive neuroscience. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Campbell, K. 1990. Abstract particulars. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Campbell, N.A. 1996. Biology, 4th ed. San Francisco: The Benjamin/Cummings Publishing Company, Inc.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D.J. 2002. Consciousness and its place in nature. In Philosophy of mind, ed. D.J. Chalmers. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Craver, C.F. 2007. Explaining the brain: Mechanisms and the mosaic unity of neuroscience. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cummins, R. 1975. Functional analysis. Journal of Philosophy 72: 741–764.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dewey, J. 1958. Experience and nature. New York: Dover Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ellis, B. 2002. The philosophy of nature: A guide to the new essentialism. Chesham: Acumen.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fine, K. 1999. Things and their parts. Midwest Studies in Philosophy 23: 61–74.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. 1968. The appeal to tacit knowledge in psychological explanation. Journal of Philosophy 65: 627–640.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Glennan, S. 2002. Rethinking mechanistic explanation. Philosophy of Science 69: S342–S353.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grimes, Th.R. 1988. The myth of supervenience. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 69: 152–160.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harré, R., and E.H. Madden. 1975. Causal powers: A theory of natural necessity. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heil, J. 2003. From an ontological point of view. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Heil, J. 2005. Dispositions. Synthese 144: 343–356.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jaworski, W. 2011. Philosophy of mind: A comprehensive introduction. Malden: Wiley-Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jaworski, W. 2012. Structures, powers, and minds. In Powers and capacities in philosophy: The new Aristotelianism, ed. R. Groff and J. Greco. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jaworski, W. 2014. Hylomorphism and the metaphysics of structure. Res Philosophica 91: 179–201.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jaworski, W. 2016. Structure and the metaphysics of mind: How hylomorphism solves the mind-body problem. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Johnston, M. 2006. Hylomorphism. Journal of Philosophy 103: 652–698.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kim, J. 1984. Concepts of supervenience. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 45: 153–176. Reprinted in Kim 1993, 53–78.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kim, J. 1990. Supervenience as a philosophical concept. Metaphilosophy 21: 1–27. Reprinted in Kim 1993, 131–60.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kim, J. 1993. Supervenience and mind Cambridge. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kim, J. 1998. Mind in a physical world. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press/Bradford Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Koslicki, K. 2008. The structure of objects. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ladyman, J., and D. Ross. 2007. Every thing must go: Metaphysics naturalized. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D.K. 1983. New work for a theory of universals. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 61: 343–377.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lycan, W.G. 1987. Consciousness. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Martin, C.B. 1996a. Properties and dispositions. In Dispositions: A debate, ed. T. Crane. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Martin, C.B. 1996b. Replies to Armstrong and Place. In Dispositions: A debate, ed. T. Crane. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Martin, C.B. 1997. On the need for properties: The road to Pythagoreanism and back. Synthese 112: 193–231.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Martin, C.B. 2007. The mind in nature. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Martin, C.B., and J. Heil. 1998. Rules and powers. Philosophical Perspectives 12: 238–312.

    Google Scholar 

  • Martin, C.B., and J. Heil. 1999. The ontological turn. Midwest Studies in Philosophy 23: 34–60.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Martin, C.B., and K. Pfeifer. 1986. Intentionality and the non-psychological. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 46: 531–554.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mayr, E. 1997. This is biology: The science of the living world. Cambridge, MA: The Belknap Press of Harvard University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Miller, J. 1978. The body in question. New York: Random House.

    Google Scholar 

  • Molnar, G. 2003. In Powers: A study in metaphysics, ed. S. Mumford. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oderberg, D.S. 2007. Real essentialism. New York: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Place, U.T. 1996a. Intentionality as the mark of the dispositional. Dialectica 50: 91–120.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Place, U.T. 1996b. Dispositions as intentional states. In Dispositions: A debate, ed. T. Crane. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rea, M.C. 2011. Hylomorphism reconditioned. Philosophical Perspectives 25: 341–358.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schaffer, J. 2009. On what grounds what. In Metametaphysics: New essays on the foundations of ontology, ed. D. Chalmers, D. Manley, and R. Wasserman. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sider, T. 2012. Writing the book of the world. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strawson, P.F. 1974. Subject and predicate in logic and grammar. London: Methuen.

    Google Scholar 

  • Swoyer, Ch. 1982. The nature of natural laws. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 60: 203–223.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van Inwagen, P. 1981. The doctrine of arbitrary undetached parts. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 62: 123–127.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Inwagen, P. 1990. Material beings. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Worrall, John. 1989. Structural realism: The best of both worlds? Dialectica 43: 99–124.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Young, J.Z. 1971. An introduction to the study of man. Oxford: The Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to William Jaworski .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2016 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Jaworski, W. (2016). Hylomorphism: Emergent Properties without Emergentism. In: García-Valdecasas, M., Murillo, J., Barrett, N. (eds) Biology and Subjectivity. Historical-Analytical Studies on Nature, Mind and Action, vol 2. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-30502-8_4

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics